Separation of Powers and the Judicial Branch Cheryl Saunders “A society in which the observance of the law is not assured, nor the separation of powers defined, has no constitution at all.”1 1. Introduction Much of the debate in this country over the changes to the office of Lord Chancellor and the creation of a Supreme Court was cast in terms of separation of powers; although more cautiously on the part of the government, at least in those terms.2 The purpose of this paper is to explore the meaning of the doctrine of separation of powers in its application to the judiciary in countries in the British or (perhaps more suitably) the Commonwealth constitutional tradition, with particular reference to questions of a broadly constitutional kind that many such countries are facing. It is thus intended to be comparative, rather than directed specifically to the circumstances of the United Kingdom, although the topic clearly is prompted by developments, here. The comparison might have been less productive before these changes were set in train. The institutional arrangements for the protection of judicial independence and the rule of law in most Commonwealth countries are broadly similar to the arrangements that were broadly assumed to be in place in the United Kingdom, or at least in England and Wales. Relevantly, in most Commonwealth countries they are justified by a doctrine of separation of powers; often as a constitutional requirement. In fact, however, the arrangements in this country were quite different in significant respects. This does not mean that they were worse. It helps to explain, however, why Goodhart Professor of Legal Science 2005-2006, University of Cambridge; Professor of Law, University of Melbourne 1 Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen, Article 16, http://www.hrcr.org/docs/frenchdec.html 2 See for example, Judges’ Council, Response to the Consultation Papers on Constitutional Reform http://www.dca.gov.uk/judicial/pdfs/jcresp.pdf : “One of the reasons given by the government for the abolition of the Office of Lord Chancellor and the creation of a Supreme Court is to increase the separation of powers”, at [33]. See also Andrew Le Sueur, “Judicial Power in the Changing Constitution”, in Jeffrey Jowell and Dawn Oliver (eds) The Changing Constitution 5th ed, 2004, 323, 336 -1- the doctrine of separation of powers has had here what Trevor Allan rightly describes as “unsympathetic treatment”.3 It also explains why the changes that are in train align the position of the judiciary in this country more closely with countries elsewhere, removing some obstacles to effective comparison and bringing the United Kingdom under what I will argue is a distinctive separation of powers umbrella. 2. Separation of powers in the British constitutional tradition The concept of separation of powers, as used in western constitutionalism,4 assumes that there are three categories of public power, legislative, executive and judicial, that are vested in three distinct groups of institutions, similarly described.5 There are notorious difficulties with the concept, which once led Geoffrey Marshall to dismiss it as “infected with so much imprecision and inconsistency that it may be counted little more than a jumbled portmanteau of arguments for policies which ought to be supported or rejected on other grounds”.6 For present purposes the difficulties may be categorised in the following way. First, every constitutional system that purports to be based on a separation of powers in fact provides, deliberately, for a system of checks and balances under which each institution impinges upon another and in turn is impinged upon. There is an open question whether this qualifies a system of separation of powers7 or completes it “by giving each department the necessary constitutional means…to resist 3 Trevor Allan, Law, Liberty and Justice, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1993, 50; see also Eric Barendt “Separation of Powers and Constitutional Government” [1995] Public Law 599, to much the same effect. 4 For a general introduction see John Morrow, History of Western Political Thought Palgrave, 2nd ed 2005, chapter 9 5 The definition here is deliberately cast in general terms, for reasons that will become obvious. Some, relatively standard definitions are more prescriptive, however. Barendt cites as the “classic formulation…three distinct functions of government…which should be discharged by three separate agencies…and that no individual should be a member of more than one of them.” 6 Geoffrey Marshall, Constitutional Theory Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1971, 124 7 It might qualify a separation of powers institutionally (one institution affects the operations of another) or functionally (in doing so, the institution exercises a part of the power of the other): see, on this distinction, Marshall, op.cit., 102. Marshall also notes that the notion of checks and balances comes from the theories of mixed government. -2- encroachment by the others”.8 The answer must depend in part on the actual checks and balances in each case. Secondly, there is some disagreement about what is separated pursuant to the doctrine. The two principal options are: A separation of institutions; which might, for example, preclude overlapping membership A separation of functions, empowering each institution to exercise the function for which it is designed (and perhaps, by extension, no other function) In reality, however, these are not mutually exclusive options. Any system of separation of powers must involve at least a measure of both. And this in turn leads to the third area of uncertainty: the degree of separation that such a doctrine requires. Complete separation is impossible. There must be a point, however, at which partial separation is not worthy of the name. Where, then, should the lines be drawn? And how should the lines that are drawn be enforced? It is possible to approach the answers to these questions through a consideration of the purposes of a separation of powers. Received wisdom has it that there are two such purposes: One is to prevent the abuse of public power through the concentration of power. Thus James Madison in Federalist 47: “The accumulation of all powers, legislative, executive and judiciary, in the same hands, whether of one, a few, or many, and whether hereditary, self-appointed or elective, may justly be pronounced the very definition of tyranny”. The other is to enhance the efficiency of government. In its original form this rationale was used to justify the institution of a strong presidency in the United States,9 but it might be turned to more general purposes. It might be argued, for example, that separation of powers in this respect recognises that each of 8 James Madison, Federalist Paper 51 in Alexander Hamilton, James Madison and John Jay, The Federalist, Everyman Library, London, 265, 266 9 Geoffrey R Stone, Louis M. Seidman, Cass R. Sunstein, Mark V. Tushnet, Constitutional Law 2nd ed 1991, 363 -3- the branches is peculiarly well equipped to exercise the particular functions assigned to it. Alternatively, it might be argued that the collective effect of a particular configuration of separated powers is a form of government with attributes best suited to the needs of a particular state. Both of the two purposes traditionally assigned to a separation of powers were originally formulated by reference to the separation of legislative and executive power; indeed this was also the genesis of the theory in the writings of Montesquieu and Locke. Both purposes could be adapted to the separation of the judicial branch. As a generalisation, however, the doctrine of separation of powers has not been well developed in relation to the judiciary, at least in a way that is useful here. The explanation lies in the distinctive constitutional arrangements of both the two states that have been the flagships of the separation of powers doctrine. One is the United States, in which the relationship between the legislature and the executive as part of a balanced three-way separation of powers dominates the discourse and influences the doctrine;10 incidentally suggesting caution in borrowing conceptions of “deference” from that source. The other is France, where the separation of powers places emphasis on the judiciary; but with a view to precluding it from impinging upon the other branches of government.11 By contrast, the constitutional arrangements in the United Kingdom are quite different, in key respects. Unlike the United States, this country has a parliamentary system with at best a weak institutional separation of the legislative and executive branches. Unlike France, judicial review of executive action, at the hands of the general courts, is a core feature of the constitutional system. For reasons that are easy to understand, moreover, the doctrine of the separation of powers has had only muted and partial recognition in the United Kingdom.12There is 10 See for example, Stone et al, op.cit, where even the examination of the significance of the doctrine for the rule of law is undertaken by reference to the relationship between the legislature and the executive. 11 Marshall, op.cit. 99. Marshall also quotes Hans Kelsen: “the judicial review of legislation is an obvious encroachment upon the principle of separation of powers”, at 99, from Hans Kelsen, General Theory of Law and State trans. A. Wedberg (1961), 269 -4- of course a strong tradition of judicial independence, given teeth through a range of guarantees enshrined in statute and long-standing constitutional convention.13 There is a long tradition of limited government, involving the division of power in various ways, through the “mixed” and “balanced” constitutions.14It is even possible to argue for a significant degree of functional separation of powers in reality, if not in outward form.15 And the great William Blackstone himself adapted Montesquieu and Locke to argue for a “distinct and separate existence of the judicial power in a peculiar body of men…separated from both the legislative and the executive power”.16 But the intermixture of institutions is such that it is almost impossible to describe it as a separation of powers, without becoming entangled in endless, unproductive debate. This is most obviously the case with the relationship between the legislature and the executive, famously claimed by Walter Bagehot as a fusion of powers. For present purposes, however, the triple hats of the Lord Chancellor and the dual functions of the House of Lords are a further obstacle to describing the system as characterised by a separation of powers. In an additional twist, it is even possible to argue that these mixed institutions have been key mechanisms for protecting judicial independence. Clearly, such a case can be made for the multiple functions of the Lord Chancellor. In a speech in this university just over 2 years ago Lord Woolf observed that it had not been “appreciated sufficiently that the Lord Chancellor played a pivotal role in co-ordinating the three arms of government” nor that he “was able to act as a lightening conductor at times of high tension between the executive and the judiciary”.17 In time it may also come to be appreciated that a similar case could have been made for the Appellate Committee of the House of Lords. Paul Craig has said that it is “regarded as a central construct in our constitutional structure”; in a context, however, that is confined to the scope of judicial power vis-à-vis the other branches: Paul Craig, “Fundamental Principles of Administrative Law”, in David Feldman (ed) Public Law OUP 2004, 689, 706 13 For detailed description and analysis see A.W. Bradley, “The Constitutional Position of the Judiciary” in David Feldman (ed) Public Law OUP 2004, 333, 339-363 14 Marshall, op.cit., 101. 1515 Barendt, 615. Trevor Allan has argued also for a de facto institutional separation of powers that relies on the “firm conventions governing…[the] various roles” of public officers: Trevor Allan, op.cit 52 16 William Blackstone, The English Constitution 7th ed, 1984, 10, quoted in Allan, op.cit., 50 17 Lord Woolf, “The Rule of Law and a Change in the Constitution”, the Squire Centenary Lecture, 3 March 2004, http://www.dca.gov.uk/judicial/speeches/lcj030304.htm 12 -5- Countries with a system of government most similar to that of the UK are, not surprisingly, found in the Commonwealth. Many of them have parliamentary systems. These include Australia, Canada, India and South Africa, which I use as occasional examples in the next part. All four have a judiciary that reviews executive action and, for that matter, legislation as well. All place great store on judicial independence. In all of them, however, the judiciary is institutionally and to a large extent functionally separate from the other branches of government. And in all of them, with the possible, but by no means certain exception of Canada, the relationship of the judiciary to the other branches is conceived in terms of the separation of powers. Traditional mechanisms for protecting judicial independence, of which guarantees of tenure are an example, can be understood as features of the separation of judicial power. The points of necessary interface with the other branches in relation to, for example, the appointment and removal of judges and the funding of courts can be analysed within a framework of checks and balances. This is, however, a latter-day rationalisation. In historical reality, most of the arrangements in these countries for the constitution of the judiciary were modelled as far as possible on comparable arrangements here. The limits of the possible were reached with the position of Lord Chancellor and the institution of the Appellate Committee of the House of Lords,18 which could not be replicated elsewhere. The transformation of the first and the pending replacement of the second by a Supreme Court thus bring Britain closer to Commonwealth experience in this regard.19 There is considerable interest throughout the Commonwealth in what has been considered necessary here to provide protection for judicial independence, once those two institutions are gone. Changes that attract particular attention include the creation of a position of President of the courts of England and Wales, with representational and management responsibilities;20 a Judicial Appointments Commission; statutory protection of the principle of judicial 18 For the role played by the Lord Chancellor in relation to judicial appointments see Sir Thomas Legg, “Judges for the New Century” [2001] Public Law 62. See in particular the following: “it is important to understand the real nature of the present system. Otherwise, it might stand in the catalogue as simply appointment by the executive. Appointment is indeed on the advice and personal decision of a government minister. But he is a very unusual kind of minister….”: at 65. 19 For a detailed exposition of the process by which the changes were made see Lord Windlesham, “The Constitutional Reform Act 2005” Parts 1 and 2, [2005] Public Law 806; [2006] Public Law 35 20 Constitutional Reform Act 2005 section 7 -6- independence; and the use of a “concordat” to record aspects of the arrangement less susceptible to codification, including the structures for administrative support.21 Many of the problems that have been anticipated in the course of negotiations over the Constitutional Reform Act also currently are problems elsewhere. In consequence, there will also be Commonwealth interest in the effectiveness of the solutions that have been put in place. And the converse, presumably, also is true. Assuming that this is so, the next part canvasses some issues that have arisen in broadly comparable countries in connection with the separation of judicial power, making due allowance for relevant differences including, critically in this context, the impact of entrenched constitutions elsewhere. Those experiences in turn assist to throw light on the effects and utility of the doctrine of separation of powers in its application to the judicial branch. 3. Commonwealth experience with the separation of judicial power For convenience, I divide the issues to which I propose to draw attention into two groups: those connected with the institutional separation of powers (including the impact of checks and balances) and those connected with a functional separation of powers. a. Institutional arrangements At one level, the implications of an institutional separation of powers for the constitution of the judiciary are straightforward. Judges may not be members of other branches; members of other branches cannot be appointed to courts. Some significant questions nevertheless arise at the margin. One is whether judges can perform other public functions that are not judicial in character in their personal capacities. At the Commonwealth level in Australia, where the separation of powers is constitutionally protected, this question has generated a substantial body of case law, distinguishing permissible from non-permissible functions by reference to a standard of incompatibility and the purpose of protecting the perception of the independence of 21 The Concordat, January 2004, http://www.dca.gov.uk/consult/lcoffice/judiciary.htm -7- the courts.22 Practice varies in the Australian states, where the doctrine receives significantly less constitutional protection. In at least one state, Victoria, such appointments will not be accepted by the judiciary at all. The principal area of concern under the broad rubric of institutional separation on which I wish to focus, however, arises from the points of institutional interface between the judiciary and the other branches, representing checks on the judicial branch. These are, of course, numerous, but I will focus on three in particular: the appointment of judges; judicial remuneration; and the administration of courts. All have implications for judicial independence. All necessarily and properly involve one or other or both of the other branches, with their somewhat different preoccupations and accountability mechanisms. To balance these potentially opposing interests, all rely on inter-branch respect and self-restraint. Hope once was placed in the office of Attorney-General to this end; but political realism has now prevailed. In all three areas there is considerable movement, with no clear resolution in sight. i. Appointment of judges In all four countries, appointment of judges once lay with the executive branch. Exercised with wisdom, such a mechanism is capable of producing good results, questions about transparency and inclusiveness aside. Used as a source of patronage, however or, worse, as a means by which the overall predilections of a court might be influenced by the executive branch, it detracts from the quality and independence of the courts. Questions about transparency and inclusiveness can no longer so readily be put aside, however, and the gains from patronage too often prove tempting. The difficulty has been to find new arrangements that preserve at least some of the strengths of the old, while overcoming their weaknesses. There is a range of variables, all controversial in different degrees: the institution(s) through which appointment is made; the degree of openness in the processes of application and selection; and the extent of lay involvement in the appointment process. 22 Wilson v Minister for Aboriginal and Torres Strait Islander Affairs (1996) 189 CLR 1 -8- The result for the moment is a smorgasbord of different procedures, on which the Constitutional Reform Act may now also be placed.23 At one end is Australia, still clinging to executive appointment to the judiciary, after some inconclusive inquiries into options for change.24 At the other is India, where since 1993, as MP Jain describes it, in a masterly understatement: “the effective power to appoint Supreme Court judges has …passed from the Executive to the Judiciary itself which has greatly strengthened judicial independence”.25 Canada was until recently closer to Australia; following changes announced on 20 February this year, however, nominees to the Supreme Court must appear before a (televised) parliamentary committee hearing, although the final decision remains with the Prime Minister, in the form of advice to the Governor-General.26 In South Africa, the reconsideration de novo of the constitutional settlement following the fall of apartheid provided an opportunity for experimentation with new mechanisms for judicial appointment. The result is the Judicial Services Commission, with a mixed membership of 23, which is consulted in relation to some key appointments and identifies a short list for others, from which the President must choose.27 The hearings of the JSC are public; a feature that can be seen as important in principle in post-apartheid South Africa, whether or not is has the effect of allowing South Africans to “get to know” the appointees that Canadian Prime Minister recently claimed for his new appointment procedure.28 For other common law processes, see Ministry of Justice, “Appointing Judges: A Judicial Appointments Commission for New Zealand?” April 2004, http://www.justice.govt.nz/pubs/reports/2004/judicial-appointment/index.html x 24 Attorney-General Philip Ruddock “Selection and Appointment of Judges”, 2 May 2005, http://www.ag.gov.au/agd/WWW/MinisterRuddockHome.nsf/Page/Speeches_2005_Speeches_2_May_ 2005_-_Speech_-_Selection_and_Appointment_of_Judges . The Attorney noted, inter alia, his opposition to the notion of a Judicial Appointments Commission along United Kingdom lines: “…it represents an abrogation of the Executive’s responsibility…you just move the debate from who is being appointed to the bench to who is being appointed to the appointments commmission”. 25 MP Jain, Indian Constitutional Law 5th ed 2003, Wedhwa and Company Nagpur, 332. See in particular SC Advocates on Record Association v Union of India AIR 1994 SC 268 26 CBC News, The Supreme Court http://www.cbc.ca/news/background/supremecourt/ . The first Supreme Court Justice to be appointed following the process is Mr Justice Marshall Rothstein, on 1 March 2006. Justice Rothstein appeared before an “Ad Hoc Committee”, with a non-parliamentary chair, pending finalisation of the procedures. Announcing the appointment, the Prime Minister observed that it “marks an historic change in how we appoint judges in this country. It brought unprecedented openness and accountability to the process. The hearings allowed Canadians to get to know Justice Rothstein through their members of Parliament in a way that was not previously possible.” http://pm.gc.ca/eng/media.asp?category=1&id=1041 27 Constitution of South Africa, section 178 and implementing legislation 28 Ibid 23 -9- ii. Judicial terms and conditions It is a commonplace for common law countries to adopt the Act of Settlement guarantee against reduction of judicial salary while in office. It is equally a commonplace that protection of this kind is symbolically significant but practically insufficient. It takes no account of inflation or the relativities between the salaries of judges and other public office-holders, much less of the levels of remuneration available at the bar. It is ambiguous in its protection of other terms and conditions of judicial office including pension or superannuation entitlements. It may be that a more effective guarantee can be fleshed out by reference to broader constitutional principles, such as Canadian Charter section 11(d), protecting a right to a hearing by “an independent and impartial tribunal”. In this event, however, the fleshing out is done by the judges themselves, creating an unseemly impression of self-interest that it is likely to be difficult to dispel. But the alternative is that the adequacy of judicial remuneration lies almost entirely in the discretion of the government and parliament of the day. A familiar checks and balances problem thus arises. Granted, these are important questions for both the independence and quality of the courts. But the provision of resources, the control of public spending and the management of the economy lie, properly, with the other branches requiring, once again, a mediating principle that recognises the responsibility of the elected branches, while meeting the appropriate needs of the courts. One solution, widely adopted, is the establishment of an independent body, to advise on judicial salaries and other terms and conditions. Such a solution distances deliberation on judicial salaries from the political process, but cannot remove it altogether. A body of which I am a member illustrates the point. The Judicial Remuneration Tribunal for the Australian state of Victoria for had authority, for a period that proved startlingly short, to make determinations about judicial salary increases that would come into effect through a special appropriation unless disallowed by either House. The first such recommended increase survived disallowance – just: the second failed to do so. An event of this kind arguably is more damaging to the standing of the judiciary than leaving the decision to the normal - 10 - political process in the first place.29 In the course of the furore that followed, the authority of the JRT over salary levels was removed, in favour of a system that tied the salaries of Victoria judges over time to those of their federal counterparts,30 themselves dependent on determinations by the federal remuneration tribunal. In Canada, these issues have given rise to a significant degree of litigation, exploring the limits of the Charter. In an initial skirmish over judges’ pensions, in which the validity of a contributory requirement was upheld, the Supreme Court of Canada observed that judges must “bear their fair share of the financial burden of administering the country.”31 Shortly afterwards, the Court was asked to advise on the validity of legislation reducing the salaries of provincial judges. The Court held the legislation invalid, because it was made “without recourse to an independent, objective and effective process for determining judicial remuneration”.32 Commissions were duly established. In due course, however, their recommendations for increases in salaries were not accepted and the issue returned to the Supreme Court. The Court held that governments are not bound by the recommendations of such Commissions as long as they justify their departure from such recommendations with “rational reasons”, relying on a “reasonable factual foundation,” in a manner that respects the purposes of the creation of the Commissions in the first place: “preserving judicial independence and depoliticising the setting of judicial remuneration”.33 Most of the challenged provincial decisions met these criteria; but that of the government of Quebec did not. There is currently some media interest in whether a recent decision by the Government of Canada not to accept in full the recommendations of the federal commission ultimately will go to the Court, requiring In her statement in response to the government’s decision, the Chief Justice of Victoria described it as “a direct interference with the independence of the courts”: http://www.supremecourt.vic.gov.au/CA256902000FE154/Lookup/MediaReleases/$file/MediaStatetCJJudSalApr04.pdf. 30 Supreme Court, Victoria, Annual Report 2004 http://www.supremecourt.vic.gov.au/CA256902000FE154/Lookup/AnnualReport/$file/AR0204Revie w.pdf 31 R v Beauregard [1986] 2 SCR 56 32 Reference re Remuneration of Judges of the Provincial Court (P.E.I.), [1997] 3 S.C.R. 3; for consequential litigation concerning the validity of decisions made by courts in these circumstances, see Reference re Remuneration of Judges of the Provincial Court (P.E.I.), [1998] 1 S.C.R. 3 33 Provincial Court Judges' Assn. of New Brunswick v. New Brunswick (Minister of Justice); Ontario Judges' Assn. v. Ontario (Management Board); Bodner v. Alberta; Conférence des juges du Québec v. Quebec (Attorney General); Minc v. Quebec (Attorney General), 2005 SCC 44, [2005] 2 S.C.R. 286 29 - 11 - it to determine a question concerning the salaries of all federal judges, including their own.34 iii. Administering the courts The constitutional dimensions of court administration have not, until quite recently, become apparent. For much of the 20th century courts in common law countries have been funded and administered, more or less effectively, through Departments of Justice or their equivalents. By the end of the 20th century, however, extending into the first part of the 21st, this had become yet another issue between the courts and the other branches, raising questions about the separation of powers. The reason for its sudden prominence may lie in the equally sudden rise of new public sector management practices, with their requirements for productivity measures, outcome based reporting and efficiency dividends, with consequential implications for the administration of the courts. There can be no dispute about Parliament’s role in appropriating funds for court services and about the need for accountability for expenditure. Equally, there can be no dispute about the interests of the executive in the efficiency and effectiveness of court performance. On the other hand, as the Supreme Court of Canada has now emphasised on several occasions, “administrative” independence is a core characteristic of judicial independence, which may affect either its individual or its institutional dimension.35 The scope of administrative independence for this purpose has not been fully explored. The Court has said that it includes, at least, “the assignment of judges, sittings of the court, and court lists — as well as the related matters of allocation of court rooms and direction of the administrative staff engaged in carrying out these functions”.36 The issue thus is the positioning of the dividing line between the functions of the courts and the executive branch so as to safeguard that aspect of judicial independence 34 Canadian Bar Association E-News June 2006, http://www.cba.org/CBA/newsletters/news406/news.aspx 35 Reference re Remuneration of Judges of the Provincial Court (P.E.I.), [1997] 3 S.C.R. 3, Lamer CJ, [118]-[119]. See also Valente v. The Queen, [1985] 2 S.C.R. 673. 36 Valente v. The Queen, [1985] 2 S.C.R. 673. In the PEI case Lamer referred to this list as “narrow”: [117] - 12 - that concerns court administration while ensuring that the courts comply with accountability and other public standards. For the moment, there is a range of approaches to this issue, with Australia illustrating both ends of the spectrum. For the most part the Australian states have retained the traditional model. The federal courts, on the other hand, administer themselves, within a framework imposed by their constituent statutes. Thus section 17 of the High Court of Australia Act 1979 empowers the court to “administer its own affairs” including the power to contract and to manage court precincts. The matters covered by the Court’s annual report suggests that the management burden is significant.37 It seems, however, to have held the line in some respects. Its 2004-5 report identifies for the Court “a single output, High Court business, contributing towards the overall outcome, which is ‘interpreting and upholding the Australian Constitution and performing the functions of the ultimate appellate Court in Australia”.38 The price of the outcome was $14.3 million. An illustration of the difficulties that can arise is provided by recent events in South Africa. Section 165 of the Constitution of South Africa relevantly provides that: The judicial authority of the Republic is vested in the courts The courts are independent… No person…may interfere with the functioning of the courts Organs of state…must assist and protect the courts to ensure [their] independence. In 2005, extending into 2006, the government proposed an amendment to the Constitution which would have added two new sub-sections, specifying that the Chief Justice was “head of the judicial authority” and that the “Cabinet member responsible for the administration of justice exercises authority over the administration and budget of all courts”.39 What did this mean; and did it matter? Many people thought that it did; and their concerns were exacerbated by the terms of a proposed Superior Courts Bill creating, for example, a position of Executive Secretary to the Chief Justice as an officer in the department, with general responsibility to administer the office of the See for example the requirement for “ Monthly reporting to the Department of Finance and Administration, in accordance with the Budget Estimates and Framework Review”, High Court of Australia, Annual Report 2005, 31 38 Ibid, 31-32 39 Constitution Fourteenth Amendment Bill 2005 37 - 13 - Chief Justice, admittedly under his direction. The government for its part argued that it was doing no more than giving effect to what it described as “the Commonwealth model of the separation of powers between the Executive and Judiciary”. In the context of court administration that is something of an exaggerated claim. For the moment I am told that the proposals are shelved. It seems likely however that they will in time re-emerge, in this or an altered form. iv. Conclusion At this point some brief concluding remarks about institutional separation are in order. The subject raises a wide range of issues. I have focussed only on three, in which there is a significant interface between the judiciary and the other branches. In each case the arrangements in question are long-standing. In each, for a variety of reasons, the traditional forms are undergoing change. The process of change is irreversible. It has implications for the composition and operation of the courts and, by extension, for judicial independence. As may be inevitable at such a time, the changes are taking place in isolation from each other. There is a still-open question about the extent to which a doctrine of separation of powers can be developed to give them direction and coherence. b. Questions about power I now move to explore, albeit more briefly, the issues that arise in connection with a functional separation of powers, with its emphasis on the isolation of judicial power itself, rather than of the institution by which it is exercised. i. Scope of judicial power The doctrine necessarily has two dimensions. First, it identifies and, under a system of controlled constitutionality prescribes, what courts should do (and other branches should not do). Viewed in this light, the doctrine has implications for due process and civil liberties. These can best be illustrated by experience in Australia, where the doctrine of separation of judicial power is highly developed and formal - 14 - rights protection is almost entirely absent.40 It is clear in Australia, for example, at least at the federal level, that only a court can adjudge a person guilty of an offence and impose punishment accordingly41 or exercise other “core” judicial functions. The doctrine also inhibits other branches, at least to a degree from directing the courts in the manner of the exercise of their powers.42 For a time, it also appeared that the doctrine might limit the authority of the Parliament to order detention without trial (obviously exceptional circumstances, such as quarantine, aside) although it no longer seems likely that this will prove to be so.43 ii. Limitations on judicial power In its second dimension, however, a functional separation of powers serves to identify what courts may not do. In a system that recognises constitutional rather than parliamentary supremacy, the doctrine thus precludes conferral on courts of nonjudicial power, requiring some fine lines to be drawn.44 More significantly, perhaps, for present purposes, the doctrine may be used to suggest limits that the courts should impose on themselves. In Australia, for example, a separation of powers argument has been used to explain why courts should hesitate to supply the deficiencies of statutes,45 review decisions on the merits,46 overturn previously established decisions,47 invalidate legislation prospectively,48 or apply unincorporated international treaties.49 Paul Craig has argued that in these respects “The concept operates as a source of judicial legitimacy; with the courts defending their role as the rightful interpreters of Justice Deane once described the separation of judicial power as the ‘most important’ of the guarantees of rights and immunities, express or implied, under the Australian Constitution: Street v Queensland Bar Association (1989) 168 CLR 461, 521 41 Polyukhovich v Commonwealth (1991) 172 CLR 501, per Mason CJ 42 Chu Kheng Lim v Minister for Immigration (1992) 176 CLR 1, in which the majority of the Court invalidated a section that they interpreted as a direction from the Parliament not to release specified persons from custody, even if they were unlawfully held 43 The possibility was based on a reading of Lim. It finally faded with the decision in Al-Kateb v Godwin [2004] HCA 37. See generally Simon Evans “Australia” (2006) 4 International Journal of Constitutional Law 517 44 In Australia, for example, federal courts cannot be given arbitral power, which has been held to be non-judicial 45 Strickland v Rocla Concrete Pipes Ltd (1971) 124 CLR 468 46 Minister for Aboriginal Affairs v Peko-Wallsend Ltd (1986) 162 CLR 24 47 Queensland v Commonwealth (1977) 139 CLR 585 48 Ha v New South Wales (1997) 189 CLR 465. 49 Minister for Immigration and Ethnic Affairs v Teoh (1995) 183 CLR 273, 287 40 - 15 - legislation, and of the legality of executive action. It serves also as the foundation for judicial restraint…”50 This is, of course, nothing new.51 But it may have new significance, at a time of expansion in both the depth and breadth of judicial review. Expansion in depth tends to break down the distinction between judicial and merits review. Expansion in breadth brings the judiciary face to face with the executive in unfamiliar and sometimes sensitive areas. Both have the potential to lead to claims that the judiciary is trespassing into the sphere of the other branches. It is possible to refute some such claims by reference to the separation of powers. As David Feldman has recently observed: “One can respect the role of the executive as makers of policy while upholding the obligation of the courts to ensure that the policy is not unlawful…”52 At some point, however, separation of powers places limits on judicial review. The courts are unlikely to be the only branch to have a view about where these limits are properly drawn. 4. Evaluation A doctrine of separation of powers now provides the principal framework within which the relationship of the courts to the other branches of government is resolved in this and many other Commonwealth countries. The courts were not originally the principal focus of the doctrine; clearly enough, however, it can be adapted to the purpose. In its present form, however, the doctrine is somewhat too general to provide much assistance in resolving a range of existing and emerging difficulties at the interface between courts and the other branches. A degree of tension is inevitable, representing checks and balances in action. It may also be that what is perceived as a difficulty by one branch may be viewed in a different light by others.53 Elaboration nevertheless would be useful, in the interests of both persuasion and prediction. At 50 Craig, op.cit., 707 Duport Steels Ltd v Sirs [1989] 1 All ER 529, 541; R v Secretary of State for the Home Department; ex p Fire Brigades Union [1995] 2 AC 513, 567; Bradley, op.cit., 340-341 52 David Feldman, “Human Rights, Terrorism and Risk: The Roles of Politicians and Judges” [2006] Public Law at 376 53 David Feldman, ‘None, one or several? Perspectives on the UK’s constitution(s)’ [2005] CLJ 329 51 - 16 - the very least the separation of powers in relation to the judiciary needs to be explained in terms of purposes specifically applicable to the judiciary: protecting judicial independence, grounding legitimacy and securing the rule of law. Those values in turn might be better understood and accepted by placing judicial review in the context of a broader constitutional vision; as an integral part of a tradition in which the virtues of limited government have managed to survive an ever-closer union between the legislative and executive branches. - 17 -