106756041 Meditation IV&VI: Divine Benevolence and Human Error Some of my judgements are mistaken. I hold false beliefs. If there is a benevolent God then one would think that He would have created me in such a way that I do not err in the judgements I form. Now, Descartes maintains that he has established the existence of a benevolent God and that it is clear that God cannot deceive. I recognise that it is impossible that God should ever deceive me. For in every case of trickery or deception some imperfection is to be found…The will to deceive is evidence of malice or weakness and so cannot apply to God. (Med IV AT VII 54; CSM II 37) A worry that is parallel to the traditional problem of evil looms. If there is an omnipotent, benevolent God who created me with a mind and capacity to make judgements, then it is puzzling that I should be prone to make errors as I (inevitably) do. It would seem to contradict God’s goodness to deliberately create us with minds which are not as good (truth-detecting) as they could be. It would undermine the notion of divine omnipotence if God were unable to create us with the best possible cognitive faculties; and it would be a denial of divine omniscience were God not to know what such mindedness would entail on the part of His creation. The Cartesian response also runs parallel to one of the ways in which the problem of evil is addressed – an appeal to free will. Our errors are not due to a fault in the intellect, but they arise because of the way in which we exercise our will. While our intellect or understanding is finite (as opposed to the infinitude of the divine intellect) our will is unrestricted in the freedom we possess in exercising it. It is this unrestricted freedom which leads us into error. For there will be occasions when we decide to endorse a belief even though our intellect has not yet a clear understanding of it. My will drags my judgement ahead of where it is really entitled to go and so I come to believe that something is the case before my understanding has a clear and distinct grasp of it. Of course, it may frequently be the case that my belief is true, but on those occasions when it is not the fault is down to the will outstripping the understanding. The source of my mistakes is that the scope of the will is wider than that of the intellect; but instead of restricting it within the same limits, I extend its use to matters which I do not understand. (Med IV AT VII 58; CSM II 40) Error is then not a flaw in divine creation or indicative of a problem in the conception of the God. Rather, it is a phenomenon emerging from the way in which we can exercise our will – and because that is freely exercised there is nothing a benevolent God can do to (pre)determine the manner in which we exercise it. The analysis of error in Meditation IV does provide us with a rule for being able to arrive at true beliefs. If whenever I make a judgement, I restrain my will so that it extends to what the intellect clearly and distinctly reveals, and no further, then it is quite impossible for me to go wrong. (Med IV AT VII 62; CSM II 43) In Meditation VI Descartes raises the issue of how we are to explain the fact that we err when making judgements concerning our sensory states. While one cannot be mistaken that right now I am, say, feeling thirsty, one can go wrong in one’s judgement about the source of the sensory experience or the good or harm of acting 106756041 in light of it. The function of the senses is ‘to inform the mind of what is beneficial or harmful for the composite of which the mind is a part’ (Med VI, AT VII 83; CSM II 57). Now, if there is a benevolent, omnipotent God, then surely we should expect our sensory states to lead us to make true rather than false judgements relating to them. Yet, as is plain from our experience this is not always the case. A couple of examples should help to make plain the worry. A person suffering from dropsy (a disease with watery fluid collecting in the body) feels thirsty and wants to drink. Yet the belief that I ought to drink is an erroneous one for drinking water should be minimised when one has dropsy. I am led to do something harmful by my sensory state – feeling thirsty and the desire to drink. Or, think of our favourite example of making the wrong judgement on the basis of one’s sensory state, the case of the person enduring phantom limb pain. The amputee has no arm, but nonetheless experiences a pain just as if damage had been suffered by that arm. Descartes rejects one way of addressing the problem. This way sees the diseased or otherwise faulty human body as being like a malfunctioning machine – his own example is a clock. Both the human body and the poorly made clock obey the laws of nature just as perfectly functioning machines do. However, in the case of the diseased body and the poorly made clock, each is departing from its true nature. This is not a promising way of explaining away the problem since, as Descartes observes, a sick man is no less one of God’s creatures than a healthy one. This approach should also be rejected because it seems to rely on locating the problem as one that is entirely within the workings of the body. This will not do for Descartes because the error is not just that something has gone awry in the functioning of a biological machine, the body. Rather, the sensation (of thirst, pain) is experienced by one’s mind, which is intermingled with the body. A solution must recognise that sensations are experienced by us and our judgements made as embodied entities, as mind qua distinct substance inextricably interwoven (in some way) with body qua distinct substance. Descartes develops his answer by drawing attention to the fact (so he says) that our sensations depend on the effect the body has on the mind and that the interaction between brain and mind takes place at a single point, the pineal gland. Our sensations arise when we receive particular signals from the body. These are for the most part reliable – our feelings of pain arise in response to the signals coming from damaged parts of the body. However, the same signal can be sent or activated by mistake. The stabbing pain in the foot I experience when the opposing forward stamps on it results from the signal sent along a network of nerves. The same kind of signal can be transmitted to the pineal gland by activating an intermediate point – for example, by stimulating a nerve in my leg (see Descartes’ example of the cord) In the case of the dropsical man the disease means that nerves are activated so that the signal is one inducing the feeling of thirst. 106756041 Imagine a nerve stretching from the pineal gland to the tip of one’s toe, and that nerve has four points on it ABCD (D being the point nearest the gland, A the furthest). [As in Fig. 1 below] Now, once a person has had an amputation at the knee their nerve still has points B-D. If point B is stimulated in such a way that it would have been stimulated were point A still in existence then the information transmitted up the nerve could be presented to the mind as if it arose from A. Now there is nothing chaotic about this arrangement. We would expect nothing else of the behaviour of wires and nerves. It is a good thing that our nerves behave in such an ordered and systematic fashion – after all if our actual foot is in the fire, then it’s a good thing that our mind is alerted to the fact, and that we don’t instead get a misleading tickling sensation in our ears. Since, our body tells us things more often than not that are true and the so-called deceptions arise in a systematic and explicable fashion then we do not really have anything to worry about here. The problem of error can also be countered by the fact that we have at our disposal certain God-given faculties for avoiding deception. If I use all of my senses in combination, as well as my memory and intellect, then I wouldn’t be deceived in the first place. Take the phantom limb case. If I get an itching feeling in my finger I need only look at the space below my elbow where my hand used to be, or perhaps try to touch it with my other hand, or maybe tap the non-existent finger on the table to see if it makes a sound, and so on, to tell me that I have no finger, and therefore, a fortiori, 1 no itch in my finger. Further, I can call upon my memory. I recall, very vividly, the operation to have my arm amputated. And finally, deploying my intellect, if the above observations have been made, it doesn’t take a Sherlock Holmes to deduce that there is no finger, and so no itch (we can run the same sort of story with the dropsy case, mutatis mutandis)2. Of course, if we have everything we need to avoid deception, but we rashly judge things to be the way they are on first appearance, then God is hardly to be blamed. The error in our sensory judgement thus comes about because there has been some faulty signalling in the body, thereby producing a sensation which would normally play a beneficial role. While this explains why the error arises one may still not be satisfied that it explains why such mistakes are consistent with divine benevolence. After all, surely God could have designed the way in which mind and body are intermingled so that this kind of mistake would not occur. Well, that is just what God could not do and why our mistaken sensory judgements are consistent with His benevolence. The physical system we possess and the way in which it relates to the mind is the best that it is possible to create. It may go wrong sometimes, but ours is the best system because it produces in the mind just the one and appropriate kind of sensation for any given physical state. That ensures that for the most part our sensory judgements do lead us to take the appropriate course of action. My final observation is that any given movement occurring in the part of the brain that immediately affects the mind produces just one corresponding sensation; and hence the best system that could be devised is that it should produce the one sensation which, of all possible sensations, is most especially and most frequently conducive to the preservation of the healthy man. And experience shows that the sensations which nature has given us are all of this kind; and so there is absolutely nothing to be found in them that does not bear witness to the power and goodness of God. (Med VI AT VII 87; CSM II 60) 1 2 ‘By the stronger argument’ ‘Making the necessary alterations’