3/3/16 [Draft: not for circulation or citation] Rosenblum: Good Neighbor Nation Chapter 2. Taking Offense, Taking Action What Anyone Would Do “Neighbor” is often used evaluatively; “good” is superfluous. We see neighborliness as a personal and social virtue, and lapses disqualify us from the title: “Thay be not neighbours, sir. Thay be near-dwellers.”1 Sentimentality is smuggled into our terms and experience sometimes confirms our warm, unearned emotions, as in this report: “The town of Essex, sleepy with the approach of winter, had detected the presence of newcomers and roused itself to greet us. In one week, two people knocked on the door of our rental house bearing actual welcome baskets, and three others came by to invite us to the Tuesday-night potluck at St. John’s Episcopal Church. …. The next week we met some people our own age who had us to dinner…the babies were laid down to sleep on the bed and the fiddles came out and the cabin filled up with music, like an episode of Little House on the Prairie but with beer.”2 These idylls are not dependable, or durable. The stories we tell are often indeed mostly miserable. If our accounts of neighbors are not outright painful, they reflect our bafflement, our incredulity at the misconduct or obliviousness of the people next door. We welcome any opportunity to recount our neighbor woes -- I never had to ask twice. We become agitated again in the telling. When friends sit down to report their trials we may feel overcome by ennui and think ‘how tedious’, ‘how petty’. But our own bad neighbors are serious business. Plainly, the value we place on being and having good neighbors comes at least as much from the grinding irritation, inveterate difficulty, ordinary vices, and occasional malice and dangerousness of bad ones. So much so that “good neighbor” might be defined by the absence of trouble and offense. He is quiet. She minds her own business and leaves us alone. Relentlessly barking dogs, blaring televisions, incessant quarrels, an 1 excess of domestic odors. Sounds that startle us at night and disturb our sleep. Bedraggled yards. Snooping and interfering in ways that make us anxious or hostile. Killing time and wounding reputation: A good neighbour, even in this, Is fatal sometimes, cuts your morning up To mince-meat of the very smallest talk, Then helps to sugar her bohea at night With your reputation.''3 The trouble neighbors cause us may be frivolous or costly. They are daily insults, inescapable. “Your next door neighbor is not a man”, one wry observer wrote, “he is an environment. He is the barking of a dog; he is the noise of a piano; he is a dispute about a party wall; he is drains that are worse than yours; or roses that are better than yours.”4 The predominance of bad experiences shouldn’t be surprising. Neither should the fact that once we shed sentimentality, bad neighbor is the background against which good ones stand out in bright, sharp relief. We have so many opportunities to give and even more to take offense. There are so many ways to run amok. “What is there wrong?” “Something you just now said.” “What did I say?”5 Precisely because of the absence of defined rules of conduct and set obligations, the lack of institutional constraints, and the shared purposes and defined outcomes that shape relations at work and other social settings, temperament and disposition or just the mood of the day are given comparatively free reign. Neighbor relations are more individual and fluid than others except the most intimate. Neighbors have latitude to be careless and inattentive, and to unleash their demons on one another. We have innumerable occasions to discharge our desire to get back at offenders, too, so that it may take enormous effort to “represse all appetite of our nighbour’s hurt”.6 Relations among neighbors are largely but not purely personal and dispositional. Largely, because they are also a matter of local knowledge, which brings the abstraction “good neighbor” to life. And confidence in our concrete grasp of what, where we live, “anyone would do” helps explain our propensity to moralism, the poor cousin of moral 2 judgment. We assess our neighbors all the time, not just in relation to ourselves but also for local fit. We may start off taking their measure privately, muttering to our family, often about their failings. We go on to try out and adjust our assessment in conversation with others, and to apply our tests of acceptability and contribution. The usual preoccupations hardly bear mention – they are conventions. They focus on delinquency. In Jhumpa Lahiri’s story, “The fathers complained that Mr. Dixit did not fertilize his lawn properly, did not rake his leaves on time, and agreed that the Dixit’s house, the only one with vinyl siding, detracted from the neighborhood’s charm.”7 That neighbor with the broken down cars in the yard, we state emphatically, is degrading our quality of life (and our property values): “For the eleven months leading up to this day….the neighborhood adults had muttered similar sentiments with the same folding of arms and tsktsks in their appraisals that they were muttering now. That they didn’t appreciate having a squalid unkempt wreck of a home framed in their picture windows.”8 Few things arouse neighbors more strenuously than the behavior of other people’s children. Audible and visible, children are the main lubricant and friction. As a correlate of interaction children take precedence over income, education, ethnicity, religion, and race.9 Encounters over children are one of the most disturbing respects in which we fail to mind our own business. Our judgments are the most sanctimonious. Drury’s fictional neighbors in “Things We Knew When the House Caught Fire” level typical condemnations: “Apparently the Bainer parents…were also rarely seen, if at all, at community meetings, council sessions, and parent-teacher events. They attended no church, they gave to none of the local charities, they didn’t frequent the local businesses. They seemed fine with letting their children wreak unsupervised havoc in public view…”10 We shouldn’t underestimate how closely adherence to local knowledge is tied to the sense of well-being. An important study of immigration reports that Americans’ chief concern is whether immigrants are good neighbors. True, we have opinions about immigration policy shaped by party or ideology, concern about contracting job 3 opportunities or ballooning public services, assessments of immigrants’ contributions to the economy and culture, sympathy or prejudice. In practice, however, acceptance of these particular men, women, and children turns not on documentation or their ability to answer questions about American history but on mundane interactions at home. Being a good neighbor turns out to be more important for immigrants’ acceptance, or “incorporation”, than earning, paying taxes, or citizenship. Do day laborers dart into traffic to negotiate with employers, drink in public? Do neighbors park cars on the grass or cram many people into an apartment? 11 Are new arrivals too shy, deferential, reserved? Their retiring attitude can be taken as self-segregation and mistrust. Passing the test of “good neighbor” in the local idiom counts as evidence that immigrants do not intend to treat residence instrumentally with a view only to jobs or benefits. It is reassurance that they will not willfully disturb the quality of everyday life. It confirms that they are open to learning “what anyone would do” here.12 Giving and Taking Offense The phenomenology of taking offense will be familiar. We all know someone aggravated by (we might say obsessed with) the neighbor who uses his lawn as a shortcut, with that shoddy new construction directly in his view, with teen-agers massed on the sidewalk blocking the way, with pets let loose to soil the hallway, with cars with oversize tail pipes and missing mufflers trolling the street. “How about Mrs. Penny, a nuisance to her children, to everyone in this building, and particularly to me – something I simply cannot face?”13 The grating effects and the offenses are not always known quantities that we can describe convincingly to others. We are sometimes unable to explain our reaction even to ourselves. It’s not like squatters or junkies. The chemistry of proximity to certain individuals is just explosive. What accounts for our aversions? Why do frequent sightings of this young woman and her latest boyfriend set our teeth on edge? Why do we time our comings and goings to avoid encountering that apparently unobjectionable older man? Or why, normally insensitive to aesthetics, do we become fixated on the noxious color of the trim on the house next door, which we experience as an act of aggression? That our neighbor did not intend to offend and that therefore our sense of injury and outrage are unprovoked is not a reliable barrier to hurt or indignation. We are 4 regularly mistaken and overreact, labeling this woman a bad neighbor that it is our misfortune to live beside, and broadcasting this conviction. Once the dynamic of offense is set in motion, it is hard to reverse. A comic account of run-away misperception is Gogol’s “The Tale of How Ivan Ivanovich Quarreled with Ivan Nikiforovich”. A careless word interpreted as an insult provokes an escalating feud between formerly friendly neighbors in the Mirogord shtetl. Each begins to imagine the other has designs on his property. Each Ivan rejects attempts by the other to explain his perspective on events and to roll back the offense. Each represents the other’s claims of innocence as a lie that by itself amounts to a despicable personal insult. Moreover, the Ivans know that their feud has become a public spectacle in the village so that personal betrayal is compounded by dishonor. They demand apologies and compensation from one another, but from the start they have made satisfaction inconceivable. One Ivan initiates a legal battle, which lasts a decade and has no conclusive outcome.14 That’s the thing about physical proximity: neighbors’ careless, impersonal actions can seem to be aimed at us. He didn’t realize that loading the dumpster with the left-over materials from his home repair would make it hard for me to take out my trash; he just wasn’t thinking. But his lack of intent hardly registers with me. His selfish inattention is making my already stressed out life harder. In that moment, he is the last straw. We experience bad neighbors as more than a nuisance; and even a nuisance, if it persists, can degrade everyday life. Indignation and a sense of righteous injury at the hands of a bad neighbor are endemic. We rail against him; he throws us into a rage. Even then, we may exercise self-restraint. We pretend to ignore the offense. We do not acknowledge our neighbor’s bad behavior. We do not express our feelings or our judgment to the offender or to others. We are, with effort, reticent. We don’t advise our neighbors that because they neglect to pull down the shades we see them displaying themselves nude or arguing aggressively, and that it is upsetting to have to be exposed to these intimacies. Whether exhibitionist or just indifferent, they make the difficult business of minding our own business more difficult. Still, we estimate that things would be worse if we spoke out. Most of us exercise restraint most the time. We are selectively inattentive to slamming hallway doors or to doors left ajar, to neighbors who park their car “temporarily” in our assigned spot, to the disturbances caused by errant children. We 5 don’t acknowledge slights or inconveniences even if we find our neighbor’s indifference maddening or detect a whiff of malice. We pretend to ignore her disturbing behavior. Keeping offenses to ourselves is a convention of denial that operates in almost every setting. It keeps us from revealing our every thought and emotion, and thus limits collisions. We have doubtless observed the opposite: a neighbor who is in a state of perpetual agitation, who calls us out on every misstep and slight, real or imagined, who creates awkwardness and excites conflict. We know that our avenues of recourse are limited, and we have a premonition that our attempts to fashion a response will be fumbling and futile. No wonder offenders often do their bad turns with impunity, after all. Speaking up, we judge, is bound to initiate cycles of anger and recrimination. So our reticence or more simply “unacknowledgment” permits us to carry on our interactions, such as they are, without more upset. After all, we may not be able to entirely shun or evade this neighbor, despite what we perceive as selfishness, carelessness, nuisance, excessive demands and intrusions. “It seems more efficient to make explicit acknowledgment function as a signal that something must be collectively dealt with.”15 Returning Bad Turns Often enough, we decide to respond to an offending neighbor. We take tentative initial steps: calm approaches, patient explanations, mild and reasonable protests. Once we are resigned to the fact that these do not move our neighbor to acknowledge the inconvenience or slight, once it is clear that no apology will be offered, and once we have lost confidence that the disturbance will stop, we fall back on reciprocity. Reciprocity holds for bad turns as well as good, after all. But assuming we don’t launch impulsively into retaliation, we discover the asymmetry. It is more difficult to mend wall and balance loaves and balls when offense and injury need returning than greetings and favors. The calibration is especially strained. For the most part, we think that good turns ought to be reciprocated even if they are uninvited, even if assessing what return requires is wearing, even if in the end we feel justified in distancing and withholding. We can choose not to reciprocate (or forget, or err), but normally we think we should respond to a greeting or favor – if not now, later, if not in kind than a rough equivalence. We are less certain about reciprocating bad turns. So our decision to take action may stall, and we try again 6 to turn a blind eye and deaf ear. Our uncertainty about the consequences of returning bad turns is one reason we practice resignation when it is a question of irritation and inconvenience. For this reason alone we may settle into passive endurance. If the offense is persistent and serious enough, inaction can produce troubling self-doubt – do I invite mistreatment? Am I a patsy or a fool? The dynamic has twists. For some people passivity has its own sorry gratifications. We wallow in our sense of injury. We become smugly moralistic (a close relative of sentimentality -- another easy appeal to prepared emotions.) If, however, we determine that the offense requires self-assertion in the form of confrontation or retaliation of some kind, the disturbing difficulty of rough equivalence must be confronted. Thomas Berger’s Neighbors is a surreal account of a mild suburban man’s reaction to his offensive new neighbors. Harry and Ramona have taken occupancy of the only other house on Earl Keese’s cul-de sac. Learning of their arrival, Keese considers asking them to dinner. He wavers. Before he and his wife can make up their minds, Harry and Ramona intrude on them uninvited. The young couple is vulgar, erratic, and vaguely menacing. Local knowledge of acceptable suburban behavior escapes them. They are oblivious to the bounds of what “anyone would do” here. They don’t respect personal space or property. They come and go from Keese’s house; behave with what he sees as crude familiarity towards his wife and daughter; shower in his bathroom; put on his clothes and borrow his car. Keese feels he has lost control of his existence. The normal disapproving remonstrances and gestures have no effect. The only course open for handling the situation, he concludes, is active response in kind. Keese turns out to be a virtuoso, a master of verbal abuse and physical insult. A cycle of bad turns ensues. Keese tries adopting a Hobbesian strategy of preemptive self-defense. “He was not displeased”, Berger writes, “to be considered dangerous”. But this strategy is ineffective given the bizarre unpredictability of his neighbors’ moves (and perhaps by Keese’s paranoid misjudgment). Nonetheless, he tries to calculate what Harry and Ramona are owed in return for each instance of trespass and disturbance. Before and again after each bout, Keese tries to maintain his foothold in reciprocity and to estimate rough equivalence. Did his traps warrant Henry’s failed effort to strangle him with a garden hose? He struggles to find some coherence in his “pay back”, and after each evaluation of the latest give and take “he was satisfied that his version of the outcome 7 was fair.” Well into his ordeal, Keese still imagines that reciprocity will be achieved, the fallen loaves and balls will be picked up and balanced on the wall: “Everything can be put back where it belongs.”16 Harry and Ramona mock Keese’s attempts to “think ethically”. But without local etiquette to keep them from blows, and having rejected what seem to be his wife’s and neighbors’ unaccountably different assessment of the couple, reciprocity is Keese’s lifeline. It is his grounding, his hope to preserve his own equilibrium and a shred of his identity as a good neighbor. Keese never entirely abandons the norm of rough equivalence, though he is thrown off by the worry that he is “in fact defenseless against any form of revenge that a demented adversary might choose”. He wants things to be a bit to his advantage in the final calculation. “I’ve given more than I’ve got”, he observes, and “I don’t mind admitting I’m proud of myself.” 17 Berger’s surreal Neighbors rings true because like Keese sufficient provocation brings us to believe that reciprocity entails the return of bad turns as well as good. For the most part, we don’t cast our bad neighbors as maniacal, and our responses are tempered. Unlike Gogol’s Mirogord neighbors, we don’t wreak havoc on goose pens -- though like Ivan Ivanovich and Ivan Nikiforovich we may sue. Unlike Berger’s Keese, we don’t push our neighbors’ car into a creek, lock them in the cellar, smack them, or give and receive other kinds of physical punishment. Nevertheless, we recognize the psychological logic that propels him. We become confident of our ability to accurately discern injury and offense. We are almost always innocent in our own minds of inviting bad behavior. We fear we have been naïve and allowed ourselves to be suckered. Compensating, we are prone to exaggerate and to work ourselves up. “There is no stopping to read the riot act, no firing over the heads of the mob.”18 Minding Other’s Business: Speaking Up Bad behavior should have consequences, including reputational consequences, and we don’t want our neighbor to offend with impunity. We may worry, though, that despite what may seem to us to be our own sure grasp of the situation, when it comes to proving intent and offense our evidence may not be strong. We know that the accuracy of 8 accounts of offense is often doubtful; we have seen the vagaries of witnesses in other situations. That is a potential embarrassment because not invariably but most often we seek confirmation from other neighbors. We report untrustworthiness, deception, bad attitude, nuisance and offenses to others near-by, and they judge the reliability of our reports. We want our neighbors to see things from our point of view. We want them to agree that our agitation and sense of injury are reasonable, that we are not thin-skinned or acting out of disappointed sentimental expectations. We talk censoriously about the local deviant, and narrate her trespasses in detail. It is not enough that neighbors confirm: ‘the son-of-a-bitch should have it coming to him.’ We want our neighbors to concur that our patience has lasted long enough, that our objections have been ineffective and our actions abortive so that more is called for. We want our neighbors to make our business their own. We want them to agree to take action and to do together “what anyone would do” in this situation: confront, retaliate, ostracize, shame, call the authorities, sue. In some circumstances the move from reticence to dealing with bad neighbors involves appealing to authorities or joining local associations committed to addressing community problems. When we believe our neighbor has violated ordinances, impinged on property rights, or committed crimes and misdemeanors we report to police, zoning boards, housing authorities. We translate ordinary offenses into officially recognized misconduct. For now, though, I focus on offenses that spring from carelessness, spite, or ordinary vices that degrade the quality of everyday life but that hold no interest for local authorities. That is, the innumerable cases where we neighbors are on our own. The most damaging of ordinary vices is cruelty, which often takes the form of bullying those unable to effectively resist. Consider assaulting neighbors with noise. In my condominium building, a converted Payne Elevator industrial space, one couple tormented the family next door – tormented is the right description -- by locating an air conditioner on a spot on the roof that produced motor noise and vibrations and kept the family awake on warm nights. The owners refused to move the compressor to another rooftop location. When a number of neighbors proposed pooling the cost of moving the AC and footing the bill, the offenders declined our offer. They declared that they were within their rights; they hired an engineering firm to testify that the sound and vibration fell within the permissible limits set by the city; they posted the paperwork in the 9 hallway. Their determination to inflict pain and their pleasure in their sleepless neighbors’ impotence were plain. So was the satisfaction they got from observing the rest of us spend fruitless hours trying to mediate and come up with a solution. Their victims were brought to the limits of distraction. They tried earplugs, insulation, moving their beds to a back wall. They tried to sell (were they required to warn potential buyers of the AC racket and the malicious couple next door?) but the real estate market was slow and they got no offers. They were stuck. They became depressed and withdrawn. Their situation was pitiful, and we were sympathetic. The bullies were shameless. All we could do was serve as witnesses to the assault on our neighbor’s quality of life, voice our contempt for the bullies’ flawed characters, and continue to demonstrate our indignation and plead our neighbors’ case. I offer this scenario as an example of “pure” neighborly interaction. A set of contrasts is helpful. Again, speaking up against the noise bully differs from speaking up when official grounds for complaint exist: vandalism, for example, or violations of housing law by exceeding the number of renters allowed. In these cases we can appeal in regular if burdensome fashion to police or local agencies where officials are assigned to the task. There are reasons not to report, the injunction “live and let live” is the subject of Chapter 5. When we do, we are hardly guaranteed satisfaction. The actual noisiness of air-conditioners or leaf-blowers, parties or barking dogs, is a vexed question that depends on environmental conditions. Ordinances are infrequently enforced if only because ensuring compliance is expensive. In any case, requesting official action or participating in organized civic activism is different from speaking out against bullying at home where all we have is confronting, remonstrating, sympathizing, comforting. Moreover, while the situation I describe has urgency for the bully’s miserable targets, it is not an emergency and there is no threat of destruction or danger. There is no intimidation, either, as there sometimes is so that neighbors risk retaliation if they speak out about violent delinquents and challenge them directly or report them to authorities. Finally, the cruel infliction of suffering I describe would be different if the offender were a government official using her authority to single out neighbors for torment for personal or political reasons. Where cruelty is officially condoned and backed by formidable 10 power, neighbors speaking up is a form of political resistance that demands courage, and I turn to dangerous, politically inspired neighbors in “Holding our Lives in their Hands”. The noise bully perpetrates an ordinary offense. Sometimes neighbors’ confrontations are effective. But efforts at correction or for that matter at extracting an apology and effecting reconciliation are often futile. Unfortunately, we can expect only cathartic relief from confronting offenders and demonstrating solidarity with hapless victims. Nonetheless neighbors do rally round, speak up to challenge and defend. How should we understand this act of neighborliness? Whose Responsibility? When political philosophers analyze the obligation to speak up and take action the context is violations of law and public principles of justice, or violations of basic rights and harm to essential well-being. These obligations arise in response to official acts of injustice and in certain quasi- public social and commercial domains where laws apply and adherence to rules and procedures of fairness and nondiscrimination are monitored and enforced. The moral grounds of these obligations vary, of course, and so do explanations of the dynamic that leads citizens to take action. On some philosophical accounts we should speak out when we see that circumstances call fundamental principles of justice into play; our obligation is to affirm and uphold them, and this suffices to impel us to act. On other accounts, we identify with the weak in the face of oppressive authority or powerful groups; our moral obligation and spur to action derive ultimately from pity and a sense of shared humanity. On still others, we speak out as a matter of personal integrity; self-contradiction is painful and we are compelled to remain true to ourselves and to match our actions to the values we hold. In my example, our neighbor’s cruel conduct affects the quality of life of the family next door but does not rise to the level of injustice or violation of a basic right or well-being. None of these moral positions offers a particularly good description of our reasons for speaking out about the offense of a maliciously placed air conditioner. The family of basic moral obligations is unlikely to correspond to our neighbor’s experience of injury or to capture the motivation to 11 defend the victim and confront the offender. In fact, we probably don’t think too closely about our grounds for confronting the bully or deliberate much about whether we have an obligation to respond at all. Moral principles, integrity, common humanity fit ordinary offenses uneasily. If they were invoked, they would probably strike us as grandiose. We may be tempted to speak vaguely of our “responsibility” as a neighbor, though it is difficult to do so without reverting to the high moral terms I just set aside. Invocations of responsibility to speak up in cases of this kind are typically casual, part of the effort to rouse others rather than a thoughtful reference to what is demanded of us personally in situations of this kind and why our status as neighbor dictates action. In fact, “responsibility” is unlikely to move those who do not see speaking out against the bully down the hall as any sort of imperative attached to being a neighbor, for reasons I will lay out. First, however, what is at work for those who do speak out against disturbances in our face, at home? We sympathize with the victims, of course, but speaking out is not just a gesture of general human sympathy of the sort we might express in other settings involving strangers. We act as neighbors, although our connection to the targets of malice is not particularly strong; indeed we may have had no interaction with the family under assault before. Nonetheless, speaking up owes to our standing as neighbors. One thing moving neighbors to speak out is proximity, which gives us a good understanding of the willful deterioration of this family’s quality of life. Sympathy is bolstered by this close look at the disruption and emotional disturbance our neighbors suffer. We are uniquely situated to observe the offense and its consequences. We are also uniquely situated to provide support to the bully’s poor target. But “epistemic opportunity” and our comparatively intimate knowledge of the details of the offense and our neighbors’ suffering are decisive. Added to this, of course, is our sense that we are not immune from this sort of harm, perhaps from this particular bully. Sympathy is buttressed by self-protectiveness. Instrumental reciprocity is in the back (or front) of our minds. It is not hard to imagine 12 that we will want our neighbors’ involvement when some noxious neighbor takes aim at us. There is nothing wrong with prudence: “Better to go down dignified With boughten friendship at your side Then none at all. Provide, Provide!”19 These considerations, which belong to us qua neighbors, are not the end of the story. In addition, we rally to confront the offender and defend his victim and in doing so create or cement our relation as neighbors. Thinking back to “the lay of the land”, we know that ‘neighbor’ refers not to proximity simply but rather to those with whom we have encounters and admit to a relation, however slight. These aroused men and women become part of one another’s lay of the land. We also know intuitively or from wretched past experience that passivity in the face of cruelty and provocation is debilitating. It takes a toll on us personally and individually, and passivity in the face of cruelty takes a specific toll on us qua neighbors. Bullying by neighbors makes it clear to us, as it may not be in the wider society --where bullies have other titles and there are institutional resources for relief and punishment – that speaking out is not somebody else’s business. There is no one else. We elect to make it our business and employ the collective “we”. Sympathetic rallying enacts the value of neighbors – solicitude, presence, and availability. Finally, there is the element of what I call the democracy of everyday life. * Neighbors act apart from any public institution and speaking up is not an obligation of citizenship. Why “democratic”, then? Put simply, because speaking out in this case constitutes resistance to private despotism. At work is the expectation that no one’s private life should be intruded on and disturbed at the pleasure of a cruel, unrestrained will. No one should have to endure willfully imposed and purposeless distress. Malicious arbitrariness should not be exercised with impunity, even if it is invulnerable to official sanctions. In general, we allow neighbors wider license for idiosyncracy, inconstancy, offense and exhibition of * In the Introduction to Good Neighbor Nation I present a preliminary account of the three facets of the democracy of everyday life among neighbors. Two make an appearance in this chapter: speaking up against cruelty and arbitrariness, and the rough equality of reciprocity among “decent folk”. 13 all sorts of ordinary vices than in any other domain of personal or social life. But arbitrariness when it takes the form of senseless, needless attacks on a neighbor’s quality of life and pleasure in cruelty is something else. Indignation propels us – a kind of moral anger aroused by someone seizing more than his due, compounded by using his situation to do ill. Indignation at the bully is as strong an impetus to speaking out as sympathy with the victim. And indignation is heightened by the fact that the despotism occurs at home, where retreat is impossible. At home, where neighbors are mutually vulnerable to one another, and we have a normal expectation that at least our elementary interests will be taken into account. At a minimum, we expect that our well-being once recognized will not be aggressively flouted, the quality of our lives cruelly diminished. Arbitrariness arouses us. Indignation may be as strong or stronger than our anticipation that we may need our neighbors’ support down the line, so that we should step up as insurance that we will receive that good turn in turn, and stronger than the gratification of cooperation with neighbors in the ‘we’ created by taking action. Whatever the relative valence, though, democratic indignation is an independent reason – and motivation – to speak up. Indignation moves us to speak up against domination and humiliation -- in our faces, close to home. Resistance to cruelty and arbitrariness is tied to our standing as neighbors. And speaking out is more than self-defense; it is an expression of democratic indignation. Speaking up against the neighbor bully is one facet of the democracy of everyday life. It has none of the articulated justification or potential consequence of political resistance and it does not count as micro-resistance, either. It is not aimed at abuse of authority or over-weaning social power. Nor is it the same as speaking out publicly against patent unfairness or discrimination. When we speak out against injustice, the obligation to uphold laws and public principles justifies and primes action, whether or not we feel personally immune -- if we don’t belong to the targeted racial, ethnic, or political group, for example. Out in public, in a store or at work, we may remonstrate in defense of strangers who are treated unfairly, particularly if they appear to be targets of discrimination. We explain our action to others on the scene in terms of rudimentary fairness or generally acknowledged terms of justice. Our action is, in part, educative; we 14 pronounce and reinforce civic values. We speak out and others may join our chorus of objections. We may be led further to join organized civic associations in the community and take formal collective action. In this spirit, a Billings, Montana neighborhood responded to a skinhead attack on a Jewish home by pasting drawings of a menorah printed by the Billings Gazette on their windows.20 In the case at hand, however, our cruel neighbor’s offense is a disturbing air conditioner, not injustice. Speaking up alone or with neighbors against the noise bully in the building merits its own characterization. For those who take action against the willful destruction of our neighbors’ quality of life day to day, speaking out is more than sympathy or prudent self-protection. Aimed at arbitrariness and cruelty, speaking up, causing a fuss, running amok against the offender is an exhibition of the democracy of everyday life that falls peculiarly to neighbors. How, then, should we characterize a neighbor’s refusal to rally round? What should we think about the woman down the hall who holds back from joining the chorus of objections in support of the miserable family down the hall? Her aim may simply be to avoid unpleasantness. Or she may be acting selfprotectively according to her calculations; instead of taking a long view of reciprocity and her potential need for assistance, she sticks to the present. She is not injured, and her short-term interest is to remain uninvolved. Or, this disengaged neighbor may have a crystallized judgment of the situation; she has determined that the offender is within his rights or that confrontation is misguided. As often, though, the only judgment she makes is that she will not make this affair her business. Her detachment in this context is not blamable in general moral terms (as it is sure to be regarded if she refused to drive a neighbor suddenly taken ill to the hospital, for example).21 Nor is it blamable in civic terms as it would be in the context of failing to speak out when we witness an act of public injustice. But is the neighbor who declines to speak up against the despot next door a bad neighbor? We know that the terms of neighborliness are loose. There is no list of constitutive acts much less presumptive responsibilities. Speaking out against malicious arbitrariness of a mundane sort is not a necessary or defining 15 characteristic of good neighbor. It certainly does not exhaust what good neighbors do; the neighbor who removes herself here may engage in other good turns, and the step to speaking out does not flow directly from regular reciprocity. Given my characterization of speaking up as a facet of the democratic ethos among neighbors, we might say that resolute detachment in the face of malicious assaults on our neighbors is a failing by the standards of the democracy of everyday life. I think it is, also mitigated by the fact that resistance to arbitrariness is just one facet. Inaction does not amount to a wholesale repudiation of the democratic ethos any more than it denotes wholesale indifference to neighbors’ well-being. Some few actions and failures to act are distinctive if not unique to our status as neighbors and qualify as firm criteria of bad neighbor (the noise bully) and good (alertness to nearby danger and warning those around). I return to the question of responsibility in “Live and Let Live”, where I argue that the injunction is latitudinarian. Going further, speaking up may be in tension with minding our own business. Some neighbors consistently adhere to this pose. They are insulated from the furious goings on. They are protected from the opportunity to know the facts, to observe the consequences, and are immune to a surge of indignation. They are not susceptible to the developing “we” of neighbors rallying and speaking up. Moreover, for the neighbor who assigns minding her own business weight, as she should, self- distancing is a defining characteristic of good neighbor. She feels and could reasonably argue that she is justified in electing disengagement for reasons that are not just selfish. She restricts the bounds of reciprocity, perhaps particularly when it involves collective action. She will not be recruited to join efforts to confront, mediate, appeal. Minding our own business is not a rationalization but a sound reason under many, perhaps most circumstances. We don’t have to accept neighbors’ insistence that it is our responsibility to take sides and take action. We need plausible grounds beyond proximity for thinking we are personally responsible. She can rest her reticence on grounds that it is not her business as a neighbor to try to right every wrong. She won’t earn the accolade “neighborly” but given the indisputable value of both 16 minding our own and others’ business and the shifting boundary between them, she is not a bad neighbor either. Though she is likely to figure as a secondary villain in her activist neighbors’ tales, and I return to this shortly. Keeping Offenses to Ourselves Normally we want others nearby to see just how we have been wronged. We want them to make our business their own. Not always, though. We sometimes choose to keep the injury we have suffered to ourselves. Even though it is meant to be supportive, neighbors rallied in our defense may be reason enough to conceal our grievances. Their eagerness to broadcast the news and enter the fray can be disconcerting. The accident of proximity gives them presumptive authority. They are willing informants, attesting to anyone who will listen including the local TV news: ‘the parents were dutiful and the four-year-old twins drowned in the family pool was a tragic accident’. To eager consumers of gossip: ‘I predicted their divorce: they weren’t screamers but their public demonstrations of affection seemed suspicious, a transparent performance’. Neighbors magnify the importance of what they know and with that magnify their own. We are “there to represent spectatordom, and help make this seemingly insignificant event one with the removal of the gods of Troy.”22 Other inhibitions are at work in keeping offenses to ourselves. If sentimentality colors our encounters with neighbors and if we are particularly trusting we may not initially grasp our misfortune. Our uncertainty about what constitutes offense may provide cover for neighbors to inflict their damage for some time before we are sufficiently miserable that we admit we have been trespassed on, exploited, misused. We wonder if our weakness or misjudgment is to blame. Do we invite bad turns? Do we allow ourselves to be bullied? We find our situation at the hands of our neighbor humiliating. We are unable or unwilling to protest much less recruit others to our cause. We don’t play our part in the cycle of bad turns, and we don’t seek confirmation and reassurance from others. There is something disreputable about our situation, we feel. We don’t want sympathetic attention. Besides, we face another uncertainty. Curiously, nuisances like noisy air conditioners or the stench of cats can be more easily communicated to others than real 17 vices, and we may keep these more painful affairs to ourselves. Consider betrayal, which along with cruelty is one of the ordinary vices neighbors inflict on one another. The list of Old Testament prohibitions against coveting begins with “your neighbor’s wife”. Narratives of infidelity often involve neighbors because proximity provides opportunity, as well as the frisson of the danger of discovery. Infidelity among neighbors is colored by the fact that all the parties are likely to know one another. Choosing a neighbor as a partner in betrayal brings the offense doubly home. The after-effects include the continued, visible presence of the offender next door or around the corner, and the possibility that others nearby will learn all about it. We may keep this betrayal to ourselves, warding off embarrassment and suffering the anxiety that the story will get around. There is also the specific damage to our inner life that comes from knowing that others know: forced to respond to their inquiries or worse their solicitude, our attention is diverted from our own feelings. We are distracted from minding our own business. Neighbors’ attention can disrupt whatever intimacy remains with the partner who betrayed us. We are grateful that neighbors don’t know, or grateful for their reticence in not acknowledging what they know. Less noticed are betrayals rooted in the violation of neighbors’ trust and in these cases too, we may keep the matter to ourselves. In Raymond Carver’s story “Neighbors”, Bill and Arlene Miller are vaguely envious of the couple that lives across the hall. “It seemed to the Millers that the Stones lived a fuller and brighter life. The Stones were always going out for dinner, or entertaining at home, or traveling about the country somewhere in connection with Jim’s work”. When the Millers agree to feed Kitty and water the plants while the Stone’s go out of town, they indulge their fantasies about this brighter life. The Stone’s apartment seems at one visit cooler and darker, another time the air feels heavy and sweet; it is mysterious, a foreign country. On his visits to feed the cat, Bill takes sips of Chivas Regal, pockets pills from the Stone’s bathroom medicine cabinet and cigarettes from the bedside table, tries on Jim’s suits and a Hawaiian shirt and Arlene’s bra, uses the toilet, acts out sexual desire on their bed (which “seemed enormous, with a fluffy white bedspread draped to the floor”). When it’s her turn to feed and water, Arlene trespasses too. She finds pornographic pictures, and urges Bill to accompany her back to the neighbor’s so that 18 they can look at them together. Discovering that they have both turned the Stone’s apartment into a place of experiment and thrilling disorientation, Bill and Arlene imagine that maybe their neighbors won’t return and that the new world across the hall will be a permanent escape from the banality of their lives. One day, caught up in their fantasy, they forget the Stones’ key, locking themselves out of the apartment. Kitty and plants go untended.23 The Stones may never know the dimensions of the betrayal. If they do, they may keep the offense to themselves, not confronting the Millers or speaking out against them to other neighbors in the building. They may be so appalled and feel so queasy about their own misjudgment or the indignity of the violation that they do not want anyone to know. Then there are the developments that we experience as betrayal but don’t communicate to those around us, perhaps because we are aware that our sense of injury doesn’t really match our neighbor’s conduct. The life-cycle of neighbor relations makes this point. Children are a chief source of accidental, circumstantial friendships. These relations fall short of friendship in terms of emotional intimacy, still, proximity makes interactions with the family nearby more frequent and closely intertwined in our daily lives than with other neighbors, or even friends and relatives.24 The course of these relationships tracks children’s development, and as they grow up, they no longer provide the glue. Interactions fall off, neighbors lose their common ground. Sometimes these bonds outlast the shared tasks of parenting, but typically they have an uneasy half-life, and we revert awkwardly to exchanging bare greetings or mundane good turns. Shared personal history can become an embarrassment in any fading relationship, but neighbors must routinely confront one another’s diminished attention. Moreover, the gradual change of heart is unlikely to be similar for all parties, which is why cooling feels like betrayal. These break-ups (or drifts) may be painful, but we don’t speak out. It’s not the case that our neighbor was a bad one or that our trust was misplaced. Simply, walling in and walling out is ongoing and changeable, and may give offense. Rallying Sides/Refusing to be Recruited We are drawn into the storms that gather when neighbors mind one another’s business, as they do. We are invited, entreated, to comfort and help. First comes sharing 19 complaints. We stand in the circle of conversation on the stairwell or sidewalk. Aggrieved neighbors try to convince us that the problem is not purely personal and that we all have an interest in settling this matter. Our property values are at stake, they argue. Or -- the second front in neighbor wars – our health is endangered. Leaf blowers are not only a noisy nuisance, they are “two-hundred-plus-mile-an-hour bazookas – a biohazard buffet of diesel soot, brake-lining particles, fungi, mold, spores, and animal fecal matter” launched onto every near-by property. The claims escalate: “Children exposed to these noise bombs, it’s a disaster: impaired concentration, impaired sleep, inability to learn to read and speak.”25 Then comes resolve that “we must do something”. That is, something beyond confrontation with the disturber of the peace. We neighbors call the police or Department of Family Services. Or show up at the Development Review Board, where one or two neighbors attending a hearing and voicing opposition to erecting a fence or installing new storm windows (opposition that may owe to sour grapes) have disproportionate influence. Or invoke the General Unsightliness Ordinance. Officers Remove 50 Pets From Malodorous Mich. Home By THE ASSOCIATED PRESS Filed at 6:55 p.m. ET August 5, 2010 REDFORD TOWNSHIP, Mich. (AP) -- Police say more than three dozen dogs, a dozen cats and about six rabbits are getting veterinary treatment after being removed from a small home in a Detroit suburb. Police Lt. Eric Gillman says neighbor complaints about the smell prompted police to show up Wednesday at the home in Redford Township. Gillman says… officers described the condition of the house as ''deplorable,'' and that they said floors were ''covered in dog waste, urine.'' A mother and daughter, ages 66 and 44, were taken to a hospital for observation. He says the animals have been taken to shelters and that condemnation proceedings have started for the home. This is a standard example, a cliché. Neighbors engage in much more elaborate organized responses. They advocate for and against a leaf-blower ban under consideration by the 20 town council. Neighbors write to local papers, create websites, convene meetings, arrange for invited experts to gather at a “No Blow” summit and barbecue. We are infinitely inventive in what counts as an offense and in our responses. “Breast-Feeding Boutique in Feud with Condo Board” is the New York Times headline. “The Upper Breast Side” is “a place to buy breast pumps and BPA-free bottles, and to bond over the myriad challenges of what is supposed to be the most natural thing in the world”.26 The condominium board of the Pythian, a building that was once an all-male lodge, lodged a complaint that the door to the community facility’s ground-floor space was left improperly ajar. They wanted to evict the nursing emporium. This dispute involving a condominium covenant, several city agencies, the owner of “Upper Breast Side”, and her customers/clients illustrates the plenitude of offenses and the expansive universe of recourses neighbors seize on. In the face of some offenses like the noise bully, we have little recourse except for the voluntary rallying of neighbors. In the cases I described just now, offenses can be translated into violations of local regulations and ordinances, civil rules of property, contracts and covenants. In affluent neighborhoods and condominium and homeowner associations litigation is a staple action. Neighbors file a complaint or notify an official agency; they may not be rich but they hire a lawyer. My homeowner’s association sued and was sued by the ostentatiously wealthy owner of a lot who tore down the original house and prepared to build an architect-designed structure that violated the association’s covenants. His plan did not conform to limitations on square footage, roof height, or placement on the lot. The review committee was confidently within its rights to deny him permission to build his favored design. My neighbor believed he could have his way by out-lawyering and outspending the association. He did not count on our determination to resist. We were buoyed to keep up the expensive fight by his arrogance and disregard for the reasons underlying the terms of the covenant -- preserving water views. Our lawsuit and numerous appeals dragged on for almost a decade. It became famous in the state for its cost and acrimony. It should be famous for the dynamic of “negative association” that transformed us from proximate home-owners to neighbors brought together by our common enemy. We always had something to talk about with one another. The District 21 Court in Barnstable ruled in favor of Shearwater Association, the first ruling to uphold homeowner association covenants in Massachusetts.27 As this suggests, aroused neighbors make willingness to state grievances and join in collective action a criterion of good neighbor, and when they do just keeping up the old greetings and considerations do not suffice. For activist neighbors, failure to rally may be unforgivable, as the leaf blower controversy shows. To outsiders the question seemed small, “but people are virulent, almost foaming at the mouth, on both sides.” “Somehow the blower issue became a referendum on what it means to be a neighbor: whether neighbors constitute a community or are just nuisances and Nosey Parkers”.28 Once neighbors are geared up, failure to join the fight and to cheer the aggrieved on is taken as evidence of stone coldness, of absence of “feeling like a neighbor”. Inaction provokes the accusation of hypocrisy: playing the part of good neighbor until it entails conflict and cost. Neighbors charge the non-participant with complacency – if her house or comfort or children are unaffected, she is perfectly able to bear the misery of those around her. That is the point. “We” is ramped up, at least rhetorically and temporarily; for the moment we constitute a community. In Jonathan Frazen’s story neighbors level this accusation against the woman who bakes cookies for the neighborhood children: “there was no larger consciousness, no solidarity, no political substance, no fungible structure, no true communitarianism in Patty Berglund’s supposed neighborliness. It was all just regressive housewifely bullshit…it was obvious that the only things that mattered to her were her children and her house – not her neighbors, not the poor, not her country….”29 We are intended to read this characterization as overblown. Again, we have variable expectations of what neighborliness requires under ordinary conditions. Organized neighbors represent themselves as the models of “what anyone would do” here; they persuade and recruit. They invoke responsibility. From their perspective, we are delinquent if we don’t exhibit support on demand, having been offered reasons for rallying. Not joining in is more than a personal character flaw, it is seen as a rejection of the identity of “good neighbor”, a willful derogation of the emerging neighbor “we”. In cases where neighbors move from spontaneous mutual support to organized local activism and seeking correction by organized political or legal means, refusal to 22 participate is further cast as a civic failure. There is a tendency in the U.S. (and in social science) to assimilate good neighbor to good citizen – to the public spiritedness they attribute to speaking out, reporting offenses, and seeking correction by organized political or legal means. A lot of lost by the fusion of good neighbor and good citizen, and I return to this in later chapters.† For now, the considerations that obtain in the informal case of the noise bully hold for organized action and formal complaints to authorities. In both, disengagement and nonparticipation in collective action are consistent with being a good neighbor, though the import diverges in these two cases. I regard it as a partial falling off from the democracy of everyday life if we don’t stand up to the bully, but I do not regard refusal to sign a petition or advocate for or against leaf-blowers in the same light. The first entails opposition to the private despot loose among us; the democratic ethos of resistance to cruel arbitrariness is plain. The second is a conventional disagreement, a conflict of interest over the utility of leaf-blowers. In neither case, however, is joining in a responsibility neighbors must assume. My confidence in this conclusion is supported, it should come as no surprise, by the competing value of minding our own business. The intent behind determination to mind one’s own business rather than take up the cudgels is not always clear, and the meaning of detachment is variable, as I show in the next chapter. But discrete distance and the determination to mind our own business are invited by the voluntary terms of reciprocity among neighbors. It is comprehended by an unsentimental view of neighbors, and the reasons we have for casting a cold eye on these particular activist neighbors and their intentions. Minding our own business is an armature we are justified in putting on. It protects against our own bad impulses and others’, including the irrepressible impulse to invoke our responsibility to take action. It is justified by insistence that qua neighbor it is not my business to try to right every wrong. † “Good neighbor” is a familiar representation of American national character -- as familiar as the proud self-portrait of America as a nation of volunteers and charitable souls who perform good works, and as common as the representation of America as a nation of public-spirited citizens. The three are distinct, however, or so I argue. The elements of the democracy of everyday life associated with neighbors diverge from the core formal principles of democracy. Good neighbors are not good citizens write small, or preparation for it. 23 Something else may commend minding our own business and inhibit participation when taking action involves appeals to local ordinances, or health codes, or covenants. A specifically liberal reticence is grounded in the recognition that we are selectively lawabiding ourselves. We all violate some rule or by-law all the time, in small matters and not so small ones. We dispose of trash improperly; we don’t report cash income; our car couldn’t pass inspection; the rental apartments in our three-decker are not up to code; we pay for child care under the table; we sublet when we should not; we harbor prohibited pets; we operate leaf-blowers during hours ruled out by local ordinances. The list is endless.30 We are all always guilty of something, and one neighbor or another, one authority or another, is ready to take an interest in our conduct. All, if made the cause of collective action and reported to one official agency or another, would cause us trouble and involve expense. At a minimum we would have to make appearances before development review boards; we would be exposed to costly investigation by building inspectors, civil engineers measuring the location of a shed or fence, tax assessors, registry workers, police. We have reasons for reluctance to rally and report, reasons for hesitation at least before we are propelled into action by the presumptive responsibilities of good neighbors. I want to give reciprocal reticence its due. “It is Our Right, and it May be Our Duty, to Caution Others Against Him...” Minding others’ business and speaking up are not always motivated by democratic indignation at arbitrariness and cruelty or the impulse to protest assaults on the quality of life at home, of course. We make it our business to teach those who appear not to have learned the lay of the land. We offer ourselves as models. We admonish and instruct neighbors directly, bluntly. Few lessons are delivered with thoughtful delicacy. “They didn’t look the part, and it was our duty to make them aware of it.”31 The propensity to didacticism is rife among neighbors. Pronouncing the orthodoxies of local knowledge and publicizing deviations can be effective enforcement of “what anyone would do” here. Moreover, taking on the commission to impart local knowledge justifies minding virtually every aspect of our neighbors’ observable business. It grants permission to surveil, intrude, instruct, admonish, condemn, and interfere in a way that 24 we recognize public officials should not and members of the public generally do not, but neighbors do and many believe should. J.S. Mill’s On Liberty is liberalism’s foundational treatise on the social and personal reasons for valuing and protecting the most expansive personal liberty. In democracy, Mill warns, liberty of thought and action is constricted by coercive government and even more by demands for conformity imposed by “society”. Mill is famously a defender of personal liberty but he is also a proponent of progress and selfdevelopment (and on some readings perfectionism), and towards these ends he condemns “selfish indifference, which pretends that human beings have no business with each other’s conduct in life.” Although liberty prohibits punishing others for actions that affect mainly themselves, and although Mill discourages us from thinking that we should be able to control other’s conduct, he does not prescribe minding our own business. Folly, lowness, depravation of taste, rashness, obstinacy, self-conceit, engaging in hurtful indulgences, intemperance, extravagance, being a nuisance, and much more warrant making the person a subject of distaste or even contempt. We are right to judge him a fool or “a being of an inferior order”. Mill goes on to canvass a surprising range of permissible tutelary measures and writes approvingly of a surprising range of disagreeable consequences that rightly flow from these measures and justly afflict the object of our disapproval. “We have a right…in various ways, to act upon our unfavourable opinion of any one, not to the oppression of his individuality, but in the exercise of ours”. We are not bound to seek his society; we have a right to avoid it. We have “a right, and it may be our duty, to caution others against him, if we think his example or conversation likely to have a pernicious effect on those with whom he associates”. We may give others preference over him in “optional good offices”, Mill offers. Mill encourages expressing disapproval and beyond that direct reprobation. He commends active engagement for the purpose of aiding the errant individual’s judgment and strengthening his will: “there is a need of a great increase of disinterested exertion to promote the good of others”.32 We give ourselves these justifications when we monitor and set out to instruct neighbors in “what anyone would do” here. We may tell ourselves that we are minding their business for their own sake, that taking action is benevolent. We certainly tell 25 ourselves that we are acting for the general good. Neighbors who observe goings on, admonish miscreants, share information, and urge others to take action may exert effective pressure and alter behavior. After all, we are normally sensitive to whether neighbors attend to what we do, and surveillance increases the likelihood of conforming to local expectations. Clearing our yard may be worth the trouble and expense for the sake of amicable relations -- if neighbors are watching, if local standards are clear, if others generally conform to them, and if the loss of standing for refusal is credible. Assuming, that is, that we feel planted here and that we see certain benefits from mundane reciprocity. Assuming that we want to avoid being the concerted object of a campaign of improvement or outright hostility as “a being of an inferior order”. Local Knowledge Traps Teaching and enforcing local knowledge and the terms of “what anyone would do” gather force from the conviction that neighborliness has a cumulative effect. Moralism is reinforced by the ammunition social science provides for minding other’s business, which demonstrates the aggregative effects of mundane practices among neighbors. Even apart from specific individual benefits, good neighbors are assets. They produce diffuse but identifiable “social capital” -- the virtuous cycles and networks constructed out of individual acts that taken together constitute the “character of the community”. Reciprocity enacted generally and over time produces public goods from which we cannot be excluded. Robert Putnam, a Harvard political scientist and theorist of “social capital”, confesses that he never attended gatherings in his Cambridge neighborhood. Nonetheless, he points out, “I benefit from those social networks”, which have “powerful externalities”.33 His neighbors’ alertness to the well-being of people and houses on the block protects his home when he is away, for example. Putnam is a free rider. He does not intend to exploit his neighbors’ concern; like many of us, he takes the conditions created by their attentiveness for granted. We may be unwitting beneficiaries, then, until a coin from that stock of social capital is delivered to us in the form of help with packages or the name of a local employer who is hiring. 26 There are advantages to just keeping track. Property left unwatched and in disrepair is a magnet for vandalism in affluent as well as in run-down areas: “Untended property becomes fair game for people out for fun or plunder, even for people who ordinarily would not dream of doing such things and who probably consider themselves law-abiding.”34 Everyone living nearby suffers the consequences of neighbors and their pets strewing trash, loitering, disturbing the night. (I turn to crime and violence in a later chapter.) We understand why the greatest fear expressed by residents in a study of a Boston public housing project was disorderliness and incivility, not crime. A well-known thesis called “broken windows” expands on this point. The cumulative effect of petty vandalism and disorder and in some areas the bother, noise, and interference of “disreputable or obstreperous or unpredictable people -- panhandlers, drunks, addicts, rowdy teenagers, prostitutes, loiterers, the mentally disturbed” -- causes neighbors to stay off the streets, walk hurriedly, avert their gaze. A vicious cycle of dispirited withdrawal ensues, and “the neighborhood will cease to exist except for a few reliable friends whom they arrange to meet.” “Broken windows” policing policy calls for officers to attend to disorder, not just crime, by informal rather than legal means, specifically by enlisting willing neighbors to look out for and confront those who violate the “appropriate level of public order”, that is, a level defined by the discernible standards in this place. Where the policy has been successful “real crime” rates do not go down but neighbors are more apt to leave their homes, less apt to avoid one another, and experience themselves as more effective guardians of the minimal standards of “what anyone would do” here. 35 Confident in our understanding of what “anybody would do” and perhaps further armed with notions of virtuous cycles and social capital, we mind our neighbors’ business. Theorists of social capital and designers of neighborhood public policy don’t attend to the phenomenology of “minding others’ business”, though. They don’t lower their sights to the disposition behind neighbors observing, intervening, taking offense and taking action, or to demeanor when we monitor, scold, and correct. Nor do these studies explore where neighbors fall into common errors: what I’ll call ‘local knowledge traps’. Appeals to our common interests are particularly fertile ground for self-deception. For example, we are prone to rationalize our disapproval and the need to take action by employing the argument that a neighbor’s negligence is diminishing property values. We 27 invoke high collective stakes and charge the presumptive costs to the couple next door. We hold individuals responsible for our predicted losses. This amounts to self-deception when it is an automatic reflex, a routine default divorced from facts. Allowing that it is misguided anxiety and not strategic thinking that propels us to invoke our most valuable asset, it justifies minding others’ business, agitating, rallying allies, and taking action to enforce “what anyone would do”. We are also tempted to view our neighbors’ behavior through the magnifying lens of harmonious social integration and fearful social disarray. We desire a coherent environment, neighbors who behave on balance in ways we have come to expect. The “local knowledge trap” here is projection -- generalizing from our own experience with “unsupervised havoc” down the hall. If examination on the basis of standard measures were to conclude that nothing like a process of social disintegration was at work, our anxiety would not abate. Social science categories like “disintegration” not only translate felt personal experiences, they contribute to shaping them. The terms are available to fuel our disapproval. They give weight to the cry that the sky is falling in when neighbors don’t learn or comply with “what anyone would do” here. Joan Didion painted an apolcalyptic picture in her essay on Haight-Ashbury in the culturally turbulent 1970s: “The center was not holding. It was a country of bankruptcy notices and public-auction announcements and commonplace reports of casual killings and misplaced children and abandoned homes and vandals who misspelled even the four-letter words they scrawled….Adolescents drifted from city to torn city, sloughing off both the past and the future as snakes shed their skins, children who were never taught and would never now learn the games that had held society together.”36 We read a host of deviations as indicators that neighbors don’t learn local knowledge or are indifferent to “what anyone would do” here; they certainly don’t teach their children well. With the result that society is unraveling right around us. Nor are we likely to be receptive to the argument that our perception of local knowledge is skewed by what we find familiar and comfortable, and that our assured understanding of “what anyone would do” is dubious. So another local knowledge trap is acting in the face of what we ignore or deflect: there are different ways of doing things 28 here. Expectations for conduct and demeanor are never single or static. “We have had to agree on a certain set of rules, called etiquette and politeness, to make this frequent meeting tolerable and that we need not come to open war…”, Thoreau advised, but plural sets of rules (which are never rules in any case) can spur us to something close to open war.37 America is a culture of subcultures and when neighbors reject local knowledge rudely, or appear to be indifferent to it, or live by their own variant of taking offense and taking action we may not see them just for themselves but as representative. We attribute to them attitudes and conduct we associate with the group to which they appear to belong. Local Knowledge as Offense The temper of our response to deviations from local knowledge is more than a matter of personal disposition, then. A defining characteristic of America as “good neighbor nation” is what I call the democracy of everyday life associated with neighbors.38 Patterns of response to deviations from local knowledge enact the democracy of everyday life or represent kinds and degrees of falling off from it. The facet of the democratic ethos that shapes these encounters is the rough equality of reciprocity distinctive among neighbors. In one pattern of response we give ourselves license to drive home lessons in “what anyone would do” here. In practice, our methods may involve humiliation and cruelty. We become offenders ourselves. Or, we write these delinquent neighbors off entirely. We tell ourselves that we have a right to avoid their society, and have “a right, and it may be our duty, to caution others against [them]”. Reciprocity along every dimension is aborted; we decline to deal. In both cases our standpoint is superiority. In both cases we stigmatize our neighbor, typically attributing negative traits to her. This is a violation of the democratic ethos, particularly if we ascribe our neighbor’s incorrigible deviation to the social category or identity marker we assign her. We efface her personally and individually. Ethnocentrism or worse, prejudice, justifies our hostile rejection.39 A second pattern of response is to “live and let live”.40 This is a crucial, complex accommodation where mistrust increases the probability of giving and taking offense. Particularly among neighbors who identify with groups that have a history or recent 29 occurrence of conflict, self-distancing and a strategy of avoidance is common. Neighbors may be densely interspersed on crowded streets, but they limit interactions. This pattern deserves consideration. Recall neighbor relations in Brooklyn’s Crown Heights. A rare, racially integrated neighborhood, residents lived interspersed on streets and in buildings. The Hasidic Jews did not join the exodus of other white groups, and neighbors came in daily contact with one another. Spatial integration is not social integration, though. Lubavitch Jews wouldn’t move and they wouldn’t mix.41 “We don’t mingle” is a coherent stance, and no one welcomed official efforts to encourage dialogue and social interaction between Hasidic Jews and African American neighbors.42 “Live and let live” had its own etiquette: guarded, cautious, with limited interactions. Recall Frost’s advice: Before I built a wall I'd ask to know What I was walling in or walling out, And to whom I was like to give offence. To those charmed by a sentimental ideal of good neighbor and to those who expect interactions to be easy, spontaneous and without guarded care, virtual walls and selfdistancing constitute an offense. But “live and let live” gives offense only if their Crown Heights neighbors see Hasidic insularity as discriminatory racial segregation and Jews see their black neighbors as hostile. Only if mistrust flows in just one direction, or is rooted in a history of domination and subordination. Within the constraints of “live and let live”, there is latitude to exacerbate avoidance on one side and to soften the tenor of distancing on the other. Black residents “often complain that their Hasidic neighbors aren’t so neighborly, that they rush around unconcerned with others, without making eye contact or saying hello.” The Lubavitchers respond “with some justification that they’re just as rude to each other…”. A Hasidic woman explains unapologetically: “Sachris [the morning prayer] has a time-frame. Micha [the afternoon prayer] has a time-frame, Maariv [the evening prayer] has a time-frame, Shabbos has a time-frame…And that’s why Jews are always rushing. And that’s supposed to keep us in line, that’s supposed to keep us out of trouble. This whole thing is supposed to keep us spiritual, connected to God….However, the fallout is that people wonder, they consider us 30 insular, they consider us snotty, they consider us – but that’s just ignorance.” Her claim of consistency (rude to everyone) sounds disingenuous. In any case, “that’s just ignorance” demonstrates a reluctance to avoid being misunderstood, to prevent offense. She accepts mutual distancing as entrenched, she is alert to mismatched expectations and the propensity to misread them, but she is indifferent. She is uninterested in trying to minimize disappointment, mistrust, and mutual accusation. The apparently simple injunction to “live and let live” is elastic. It can indicate as it does here the shrug of indifference we associate with the phrase. On the other hand, “live and let live” is compatible with casual encounters that are short of social integration but fit our notions of ordinary interaction: “I don’t love my neighbors. I don’t know my Black neighbors. There’s one lady on President Street – Claire – I adore her. She’s my girlfriend’s next-door-neighbor. I’ve had a manicure done in her house, and we sit and kibbutz and stuff. But I don’t know them. I told you we don’t mingle socially because of the difference of food and religion and what have you here.”43 The point is, day to day cautious distancing is not the equivalent of hostility or disdain, and does not signal superiority or subordination. It differs from one-sided exclusion. Crown Heights neighbors understood the damage that vicious back and forth charges, visible aversiveness, menacing demeanor, and demonstrable mistrust could wreak on decent life in the neighborhood. After the riots a Hasidic woman explains: “Do you know that the Blacks who came here to riot were not my neighbors? …the people in this community want exactly what I want out of life. They want to live in nice homes. They all go to work…. They want to send their kids to college. They wanna live a nice quiet life…The people who came here to riot were brought here by this famous Reverend Al Sharpton… My Black neighbors? I mean, I spoke with them. They were hiding in their houses just like I was.”44 This pattern of response to deviation from “what anyone would do here” falls short of a robust democracy of everyday life, which assumes that give and take extends to 31 those who figure on our lay of the land as “decent folks”. 45 The phrase “decent folks” helps distinguish the rough social equality among neighbors from the political standing of equal citizenship and from formal legal equality.46 “Decent folks” signals deliberate disregard for our neighbor’s position in the wider society, including citizen status and many social differences and distinctions. Carefully calculating social status, drawing finegrained class distinctions, adjusting to racial or religious markers, taking exquisite pains to treat neighbors in the particular terms that fit their standing “outside” is a violation of the democratic ethos among neighbors. The phrase “decent folks” points to a single, latitudinarian standard for reciprocal encounters. It walls out only those who impose, exploit, ignore, offend and injure not once but often or egregiously. So, when we adhere to the democracy of everyday life, we keep our neighbors personally and individually in view and refuse to approach them as representatives or symbols. We do this in the face of our own prejudices, snobbery, ethnic and racial identification, and level of personal comfort. Or we try. We appreciate this particular neighbor as “decent folk”. Cautious distancing in Crown Heights falls short of this democratic ethos, but “live and let live” does not fall off entirely. The democratic ethos is violated when neighbors persistently exhibit indifference or nonrecognition, when they pretend to be invisible to one another. It is eclipsed if neighbors, feeling intimidated by their fellows, are pressured to put on a hostile or blank demeanor, or think that loyalty requires displays of disregard. That is, if neighbors lose the capacity or willingness to initiate or respond to the most minimal encounters. For even nods and “How are you today?” are significant, as they were in Crown Heights. In a gesture or word we acknowledge that we are neighbors, regular presences not trespassing strangers. Because these offerings open us to rebuff they signal our mutual vulnerability. We demonstrate that we intend no harm. We proffer this bit of give and take. We exhibit an iota of good will. It is not full-blown democracy of everyday life but as a day to day matter bare tentative interactions constitute reciprocity among “decent folk”. It is consistent with the guarded, cautious interactions prescribed by “live and let live”. A third pattern of response to deviations from local knowledge comes closer to the democratic ethos that is common in settings without the strain of settled divisions and mistrust. We act with simplicity and consistency – “treating others identically and with 32 easy spontaneity”.47 Treating people similarly does not allow for assessments or adjustments for social status or class, race or religion. We expect simplicity and consistency to be reciprocated, or at least to be received as benign. An ounce of sensitivity should warn us not to be complacent. Treating people identically and with easy familiarity is not always received in the spirit intended. It may go against our neighbor’s standing in a group that has definite notions of what form of address is required as a matter of pride, and what gives offense. The terms may be designed to ward off easy familiarity, to set themselves apart. We, in turn, have to ward off the resentment we feel at having been rebuffed and misunderstood. Which is why this facet of the democracy of everyday life entails not only easy spontaneity but also discipline. It requires the disposition to make allowances and to resist the impulse to magnify slights. We exhibit it when we are slow to take offense. The democracy of everyday life requires us to overlook snobbery and coldness, and to disregard the walls erected out of racial or ethnic mistrust or pride, or to try. When we don’t adopt the democratic ethos of rudimentary reciprocity among “decent folk”, when neighbors perpetually give and take offense and take action, we are drawn into the difficulties I have surveyed: the baffling accounting involved in responding to bad turns, the uncertainty of responsibility to speak up for neighbors who are cruelly mistreated, the ‘local knowledge traps’ that dig us into fixed notions of “what anyone would do” here although we know that not everyone would, or could. Through it all runs the tension between minding other’s business and minding our own. Minding our own business is not a simple proposition. Among neighbors it is strictly an impossibility. Complications emerge when we take the phrase literally. Discrete self-distancing and refraining from interfering with neighbors are one thing, tending to our selves is another. What is our business? In Frost’s words, what are the boulders that have fallen to each? And what relation does our business have to our neighbors’? Minding our own business may involve neighbors profoundly, if only because they spur self-awareness, even transformation. Something happens, and we are startled into thought. From our vantage point as spectators to our neighbors’ lives we gain insight into our own vulnerabilities, moral resources, and the terms of our happiness. The path to care of the self runs through them. That is my next subject. 33 1 OED On-Line 1b. Kristin Kimball, The Dirty Life: On Farming, Food, and Love (New York: Scribner, 2010), p. 71-2. 3 Elizabeth Barrett Browning, Aurora Leigh, Book IV, 1857. 4 Glbert K. Chesterton. 5 Robert Frost, “The Code”. 6 OED 1650 1B. 7 Jumpa Lahiri, “Sexy” in Interpreter of Maladies, p. 95. 8 David Drury, “Things We Knew When the House Caught Fire”, Little Engines, p. 122. 9 Cited in Constance Perin, Belonging in America (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1988), p. 63. 10 David Drury, “Things We Knew When the House Caught Fire”, Little Engines, pp. 122-3. 11 Douglas S. Massey and Magaly Sanchez R. Broken Boundaries: Creating Immigrant Identity in AntiImmigrant Times (New York Russell Sage, 2010), p. 247? 12 Pinckus, Noah and Skerry, Peter, “Good Neighbors and Good Citizens: Beyond the Legal-Illegal Immigration Debate” in Swaine, 95-113. “While the current debate asks whether immigrants can be good citizens, we argue that to many Americans the more immediately pressing question is whether immigrants can be good neighbors.” at 100; 105. 13 Doris Lessing, The Diary of a Good Neighbor, p. 25. 14 Leonard Kent, ed. The Complete Tales of Nikolai Gogol Volume 2 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1985): 169-214. 15 Thomas Nagel, “Concealment and Exposure” in Concealment and Exposure and Other Essays (Oxford, 2002), p. 15. 16 Berger, p. 173, 169, 160, 17 Thomas Berger, Neighbors (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1980), p. 18; p. 162. 18 Thoreau, p. 112. 19 Robert Frost, “Provide, Provide” 20 Discussed in Rosenblum, Membership and Morals, pp. 279-80. 21 Emergencies and situations critical to life and well-being are something else. I will return to the question of responsibility in “Live and Let Live”. 22 Thoreau, p. 40. 23 Raymond Carver, “Neighbors” in Where I’m Calling From, (New York: Vintage, 1989) p. 86; 89. 24 I distinguish neighbors and friends in “Good Neighbors, Good Works, Good Citizens”. 25 Tad Friend, “Blowback” The New Yorker, Oct. 25, 2010, p 50; p, 53. 26 http://www.nytimes.com/2011/03/11/nyregion/l1breast.html 27 Shearwater v. Kline (GET) (I use the case in my class on “Legalism” whose theme is how rules and laws alter relations, for better and worse.) 28 Friend, p. 52; 55. 29 Franzen, op cit. 30 I’m grateful to Lucas Swaine for these examples. 31 Drury, p. 118. 32 J.S. Mill, On Liberty, “Of the Limits to the Authority of Society over the Individual”. 33 Robert D. Putnam, “E Pluribus Unum: Diversity and Community in the Twenty-first Century. The 2006 Johan Skytte Prize Lecture”, Scandinavian Political Studies, Vol. 30, no. 2, 2007: 137-174 at 138. 34 James Q Wildon and George L. Kelling, “Broken Windows”, The Atlantic, March 1982, p. 3. The authors speak of the informal “control mechanisms” neighbors provide enforce. See too George L. Kelling and Catherine M. Coles, Fixing Broken Windows (Free Press: New York, 1996). 35 Local standards may permit public drinking or not, for example. Those who take action experience themselves as more effective guardians of the minimal standards of “what anyone would do”. Wilson and Kelling, p. 2, 6, 8, 4.. 36 Joan Didion, Slouching Towards Bethlehem (New York: Washington Square Press, 1961), p. 94. 2 34 37 Thoreau, Walden, p. 133; p. 129. Two other chapters detail just how the democracy of everyday life is a defining characteristic of America as “good neighbor nation”. 39 For a careful parsing of forms of racial discrimination see Elizabeth Anderson, The Imperative of Integration (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2010). 40 Recent research on trust among neighbors suggests, encouragingly, that traditional in-group/out-group dyamic is waning. In particular, studies find that racial diversity has declined as a predictor of mistrust Robert J. Sampson and Corina Graif, “Neighborhood Networks and Processes of Trust”, in Karen S. Cook, Margaret Levi, and Russell Hardin, ed., Whom Can we Trust?: How Groups, Networks, and Institutions make Trust Possible (New York: Russell Sage, 2009) P. 209. 41 Goldschmidt, p. 8. 42 They may even be seen as an insult insofar as sacred commandments dictating a Hasidic life are cast as “cultural differences”. 43 Cited in Goldschmidt, p. 193; 194; p. 119. 44 Goldschmidt, p. 81-2., Jan Feldman, Lubavitchers as Citizens (Ithaca, Cornell University Press, 2003), p. 54-58. s 45 For an extended discussion of this phrase see Chapter 4, “Good Neighbor Nation”. 46 It is also distinguishable from social equality contrasted with hierarchy, assymetrical relations of command and obedience. Cf. Anderson, p. 102. For the six requirements of equal relations see pp. 106-8. 47 Shklar GET 38 35