Harm and the Right Not to be Harmed Cara Kent Gillis We all agree that harm is bad, but what does this mean?1 On the face of it, it seems to mean that harm should be avoided; but there is a more complicated story to tell then mere avoidance. I want to give a complete account of harm by focusing on two different sides of this story: The first side explains what harm is, which types of harm are more significant than others, and what it means to experience harm. The main argument that will emerge from this aspect is that subjectively experienced harm carries the most amount of significance. The second side addresses how the significance of certain types of harm is so great that it essentially generates a moral right not to be harmed, with all the correlative duty components. There are several arguments that emerge from this second side. One is that a being’s status as harmable2 generates a general claim right that the being not be harmed. Another is that, given the special nature of harm, this general claim right is charged against all relevant individuals without the need for contracting to justify the right. The final argument focuses on the nature of the duties that are necessarily correlative in order to make sense of the right not to be harmed. Because the nature of the right not to be harmed is not as straightforward as the nature of, for example, the right to sustenance, the correlative duties may be exceedingly complex; however, while in some ways this may place more of a burden on the duty-bearer in the harm case, it in no way detracts from the significance of the duty. Introduction Imagine three things, a painting, a dog, and an adult human being, each being slashed with a knife. What, if anything, captures the wrongness of that action? One intuition is that slashing the three objects is wrong, albeit to varying degrees, because it harms them. Many may find this contentious: can we really say that the painting has been harmed? Is it not more appropriate to say that is has been damaged? Although it seems wrong to damage the painting, it seems worse to slash the dog, and many may say even worse yet to slash the human. One account that captures these intuitions is that the wrongness of the harm is, in part, 1 One may argue that there is an unintentional ambiguity here; however, I see this ambiguity as a illuminating two points of interest within the discourse of harm. The first point deals with the apparent fact that there is a general universal consensus that, however it is construed, harm is bad. The second point addresses the issue of what features are specific to harm such that harm is bad in itself. 2 I will use ‘harmable’ as a placeholder for ‘capable of experiencing harm in a morally significant way.’ determined by a being’s ability to experience it. Under such an account, the morally significant aspect of harm is the subjective experience of it and it is questionable whether instances that we refer to as objective harm are not more accurately classified as damage. In light of this, if we think that the dog is in some way less conscious or less aware than the human is, such that it, like the painting, cannot experience the harm, then it is less reprehensible to slash the dog than the human.3 We also may have the intuition that because the human (and arguably the dog) can experience the harm, she at least has a right not to be harmed. While the painting obviously has no such right, the human clearly does, and the dog (depending on what it means to have a conscious experience of harm) may as well. These intuitive judgments suggest that the capacity to experience harm is morally significant in such a way that it generates a right. In what follows, I want to examine the natures of harm and the right not to be harmed; I will argue that beings that can experience harm have a moral status that grants them at least the right not to be harmed. The main point of my argument can expressed as follows: x has the ability to experience harm x has moral status x has rights-bearing status This point is motivated by a central assumption: the best way to make sense of moral status/significance/considerability is by making it a sufficient (although not exclusive) criterion for rights-bearing status. If being morally significant amounts to anything at all, then it at least amounts to the possession of rights (at minimum the possession of one right).4 One very compelling way, although certainly not the only way, that a being (x) can have moral status is by x’s possessing the capacity to experience harm (what I will eventually call ConsciousnessM: the ability to have a relevantly conscious experience of harm). To ground the moral significance of x’s ability to experience harm I will rely on the common intuition that harm is bad, and that the 3 Note that the dog and the human need not be exactly similar in their consciousness for their experiences to be morally significant; rather, they need only be similar in their ability to have a conscious experience of harm. 4 A weaker, but perhaps more acceptable formulation of my claim is that rights are merely one of many ways, although potentially the best way to capture what is required by moral significance. badness of harm in some way, which I hope to clarify, makes the experience of harm morally significant. Although the intuition that harm is bad is obvious, a complete account of the right not to be harmed requires an explanation for the intuition. This explanation needs to take in to consideration that the experience of harm, which seems to focus on the subjective aspect of harm, is not the only account of why harm is bad. Objective harm, the harm a being can incur without consciously experiencing it, is also bad. Although the distinction between the fact and significance of objective and subjective harm needs to be explained, it should not cause tension between my intuition that the experience of harm is morally significant and the common intuition that objective harm is also morally significant (although perhaps not equally so). One potential solution to this tension may be a re-characterization of objective harm as damage. X’s status as morally considerable, in virtue of x’s ability to experience harm, generates at least the general claim right that x has a right to not be harmed.5 My explanation of this aspect of the argument will involve two separate discussions. The first will involve an argument for why status-based approaches offer the best account of how and why beings have (or ought to have) rights, especially when contrasted with the traditional alternative of an instrumentalist justification.6 The second will involve a more detailed examination of the nature of rights, particularly general claim rights in rem, and the correlativity between such rights and duties.7 5 Of course, although the primary focus of the argument seems to justify a right not to be subjectively harmed, there are still independent reasons why beings ought not be objectively harmed. I will need to consider how my theory can focus on the subjective aspect of harm without permitting or remaining neutral on the issue of objective harm. 6 If it is the case that rights are natural, based on status, then a being the satisfies the requisite criteria for such rights necessarily has them; however, as I hope to discuss, the possession of a right may not amount to very much unless the right is recognized by others to the extent that they bear the correlative duty. 7 Although I will develop this discussion much more in what follows, my current thought is that the best way to make sense of this right is to argue that, apart from the general duty of non-interference that Hart and others think emerges from general claim rights, any duty-bearer (y) has an obligation not to cause x to experience any harm. Although this may limit the potential benefits of x’s right not to be harmed, the correlative duty generated by this right is much more intuitive and bearable. To summarize, I will consider the following claims: 1. Harm, especially subjective harm, is bad. 2. The experience of harm is morally significant. 3. x has the ability to experience harm x has moral status x has rightsbearing status 4. A status-based justification for general claim rights in rem best capture what is required by 3. 5. The claim right not to be harm has correlative duties without the need for explicit contracting. Claims 1, 2, and 4 and 5 will be dealt with in respective sections, while claim 3 will serve as the unifying thesis for the entire project. The Nature of Harm To recap what I said in the introduction, my primary area of interest focuses on the moral significance of the experience of harm and the right and obligations can be generated from this. However, there are two further issues that I will also explore to provide a thorough understanding of the nature of harm. The first issue is whether it is the fact that a being has the ability to experience harm that is morally significant or the fact that the being is currently experiencing some harm that it does not ‘want’ to be experiencing that is morally significant. The second issue pertains to the objective and subjective natures of harm. A being is objectively harmed when it is harmed in the physical sense.8 For example, much like a plant is harmed by lack of water, so to is a human or animal. In the case of many at least minimally conscious beings, objective harms often, but not always, lead to subjective harms: a harm that has “some sort of impact upon the mental life of a subject.”9 Beings can be subjectively harmed causally when something causes “a creature’s goals to be subjectively frustrated…or that in one way or another cause a creature to suffer…” and beings can be subjectively harmed a-causally, by “the mere fact that the things that [a being] desires don’t occur (as a matter of objective fact and 8 As I mentioned earlier, it may be the case that objective harm really amounts to instances of damage. 9 Carruthers, 2004a, 101. independently of the animal’s beliefs)…”10 What is significant for our current purposes is that a being can be harmed subjectively when its interests are frustrated or it experiences harm either directly, as in the causal case, or indirectly, as in the a-causal case.11 Since the view I am developing is one designed to strongly justify and potentially expand the sphere of moral consideration and rights-bearing status, explaining a) the nature of the different types of harm, and b) (in the section on Consciousness) how a being experiences the different types of harm are both necessary. On the face of it, the nature of harm seems quite simple and intuitive; this is misleading. Although it may seem obvious that slashing the painting, the dog, and the human are acts of harm, there are clearly different conceptions of harm at work. One way to further understand the tension that may exist here is by considering another example. Imagine two individuals: individual N is a normal human being and individual P is a paraplegic.12 Both are blind. On one hand, it seems equally bad to slash the legs of N and P; however, on the other hand, there may be the intuition that, although the slashing may be morally significant in both cases, it is worse in N’s case because N can have some kind of significant experience of the harm. Upon initial examination, it seems like this account tracks along the objective/subjective experience distinction: both N and P have been objectively harmed in the sense that their legs have been 10 Carruthers, 2004a, 101. 11 This preliminary explanation of the nature of harm discussed for the purposes of this paper merely scratches the surface of a very complex topic and glosses over many areas of debate. One such issue is the potential problem of harmful desires and paternalism. A heroin addict may desire a shot of heroin, but we may say that getting the shot is not in her interests. Therefore, although she perceives it to be arguably both subjectively and objectively in her interest to satisfy her desire for a shot, we may, rightly so, find that she is mistaken in her view about what is in her best interests. This issue of paternalism may raise some problems for this account, and I hope to examine it further. Another issue seems natural to mention now is this issue of causing harm in relation to rights. The rights claims that are generated in the causal case of harm seem much stronger and more evident that the possibility of rights claims emerging from a-causal cases. I will mention these issues more in the section on Rights, and in much greater detail in the complete treatment of this topic. I am relying on the colloquial understanding of “paraplegic”; the technical term for what I want to capture is “lower body paraplegia with anesthesia” wherein the individual has no sensation in or function of his lower extremities. 12 damaged, but N has experienced a much clearer case of subjective harm (especially if P is kept ignorant of the slashing). This is not to say that slashing the legs of a paraplegic is morally analogous to slashing a painting, but it may reflect the intuition that the experience of harm (however that is qualified) is significant in determining what counts as harm and the moral significance of harm.13 The example of N and P may be taken to indicate that the significance of harm is the suffering that it causes; this is not necessarily the case. Breaking down this distinction begs the question of what we consider suffering, which seems to lead to the answer that suffering is both physical pain and/or psychological distress.14 The point I want to make here is to distinguish pain from harm. To expand this distinction let us imagine a strict vegan, V, who is steadfastly against the consumption of any animal product. V’s peer, a meat-eater, M, believes (erroneously) that V’s diet is causing V to lack certain vital nutrients and is secretly lacing V’s food with various animal products. V is not in any physical pain because of M’s actions; however, it seems that, particularly in the case where V becomes aware of M’s action, V has been harmed. This may be an instance of harm because V’s desire to not consume animal products has been thwarted. While that raises other issues to be addressed in the upcoming section on Consciousness, the current point to note is that although pain may be associated, often intimately, with our conceptions of harm, it is not a necessary condition for harm. I have now, at least preliminarily, distinguished harm from pain, but what about the distinction between psychological suffering and harm? This is a much trickier point, especially given my initial claim that the experience of harm (whether the harm be physical or mental) is 13 A problem that I foresee arising from this argument is that if the experience of harm generates a right not to be harmed, and some being is completely incapable of experiencing harm, yet is an otherwise rational autonomous agent, how could the being have any rights? Of course, this capacity is not the only way in which a being may have rights. P could have rights, specifically a right not to have his legs slashed, for a plurality of reasons. 14 For current purposes, I will rely on this very coarse and minimally justified parsing of suffering. I hope to give a more sophisticated account in the full treatment of this topic. significant in generating rights. Regardless, thoroughness requires that, at the very least, psychological suffering and harm be conceptually distinguished. The most obvious way to track the distinction is to once again appeal to the objective/subjective distinction. Psychological suffering may be the product of objective or subjective harm, but one could equally experience psychological suffering without any obvious instance of harm at all. In an attempt to flesh out the intuitions behind this distinction, consider some examples. First, recall the example of the blind paraplegic, P. Imagine I amputate P’s foot. While P has been objectively harmed, P may not be subjectively harmed, given that P may not have a direct awareness of the amputation the way P’s non-paraplegic counter-part might. This is not to say that P does not suffer psychologically. If P finds out that P’s foot has been amputated, P may feel extreme psychological suffering. In this case, it may be safe to say that psychological suffering is, in fact, a form of subjective harm (even though P’s awareness and experience of the harm is achieved by less traditional means); however, we must note that here the subjective harm is a result of the psychological suffering.15 Moving on to a second example, consider a particularly sensitive 12 year-old, T, who stayed up late watching horror films. T has horrible nightmares that night and awakes in a state of extreme terror, convinced zombies are in the room. In this case, it is obvious that there has been no instance of objective harm, but it does seem that the psychological suffering T experiences is a result of some subjective harm (in the sense that T is under the mistaken impression that there is an objective threat of harm posed by zombies in the room). In contrast to the case with P, T’s psychological suffering is a result of T’s subjective experience of harm. Finally, consider a married couple where the scheming husband, H, stands to gain a substantial fortune upon his wealthy wife’s, W, demise. To speed up this process, H is secretly poisoning W with some poison that, until the moment of death, causes W no apparent 15 To clarify this point, it seems that the normal case would be for a subjective experience of some harm to cause some amount of psychological suffering. However, in P’s case, P cannot have a first person experience of the harm. P instead experiences psychological suffering for any number of reasons that seem evident when one realizes one has lost a foot. harm. In this case, W is being objectively, but not subjectively, harmed. Since there is no awareness of the harm, W is not psychologically suffering.16 The point to take away from these examples is that while psychological suffering seems to be closely associated with subjective harm, and to a lesser degree with objective harm, psychological suffering is not identical with either form of harm. The Nature of Moral Significance I am using harm as a backdoor to establishing a) moral significance and b) what such significance requires. This approach is more effective then starting with moral significance because even though it may be generally clear that we have a prima facie obligation not to harm, moral significance generally construed often gives us no indication as to what particular obligations it generates. Insofar as a being is capable of being harmed in the relevant way, we generally agree that it is wrong for us to harm them for no greater purpose (some problematic situations in utilitarianism aside). Our recognition that beings are ‘harmable’ is a necessary part of determining how we will treat a being. Tom Regan offers an account of the significance of certain properties in determining moral status and obligations when he notes: If human beings do not experience pleasure or pain, for example, or do not prefer some things over other, or cannot make decisions and act intentionally, or are incapable of understanding what is involved in treating others with respect, then there could not be anything for ethical theory to be a theory of.17 It is in virtue of certain properties, or attributes, that beings possess that we determine both the structure and extent of our obligations to them. For my purposes, the property is that of being 16 Of course, this example brings up the relationship between harm and death. This is especially significant given that I will be arguing that a being’s ability to experience harm grants the being a right to avoid being caused to experience harm. Although I hope to expand of the nature of the relationship, for now I offer a small point of clarification. I maintain that a right to avoid harm has the correlative duty that others not cause a being to experience harm. If death is generally harmful (an assumption that I realize is contentious and, in fact, not always the case), then some may be inclined to say that a being’s status as harmable means that the being has a right to life. This is incorrect; at best, a being’s right not to be caused to experience harm corresponds to a being’s right to avoid being killed. 17 Regan, 2004, 17-18. ‘harmable’ and the interest this property generates is an interest in not being harmed. In light of this, we say a being, a moral patient, deserves moral consideration from moral agents when it possesses the properties necessary in order for it to have morally relevant interests.18 The relationship between moral agent and moral patient can be expressed more clearly as follows: “For all A, X deserves moral consideration from A. Where A ranges over rational moral agents and moral ‘consideration’ is construed broadly to include the most basic form of practical respect (and so is not restricted to ‘possession of rights’ by X.)”19 Note that there is a marked difference between a being’s possession of moral status and a being’s possession of moral rights, a distinction that is a central issue for the current discussion and one that I will return to in the following sections. To foreshadow the argument ahead: Beings that are ‘harmable’ are moral patients and have a right to not be caused to experience harm. Before turning to address the nature of such a right, consider what it means to have a morally significant experience of harm. Based on how I have classified the significant aspects of harm, it becomes evident that the ability to experience harm is morally significant, although potentially morally significant in a different way then the actual experience of harm itself. In light of this, I need to establish an account of how it is that beings are capable of experiencing harm in a morally significant way. There are two different ways that consciousness matters to moral status: first, it could be the case that merely possessing consciousness is valuable, irrespective of what is represented in conscious states; second, it could be the case that consciousness is desirable because it enables beings to have experiences and interests that are significant. Which of these two options offers a better account of how consciousness is most relevant to moral “Let us consider the question to whom principles of morality apply from, so to speak, the other end – from the standpoint not of the agent, but of the ‘patient.’ What, we may ask, is the condition of moral relevance? What is the condition of having a claim to be considered, by rational agents to whom principles apply?” (Warnock, 1971, 148). 18 19 Goodpaster, 1978, 309. consideration is a difficult issue that I hope to address in the full account of this work; for the purposes of this discussion, we can merely assume that consciousness is at least morally significant because it enables a being to have interests, without excluding the potential that consciousness is morally significant in itself. The task now turns to explaining what account of consciousness is the best candidate for ConciousnessM. While there may be compelling arguments for using phenomenal or higher-order theories of consciousness as the paradigm account for ConciousnessM, I believe that the firstorder desire theory best reflects what ConciousnessM requires.20 Having desires is the foundational element for having interests and, as such, can serve as the most elementary account of consciousness relevant to the experience of harm.21 For example, a being has a desire to drink; it therefore has an interest in satisfying that desire. If that desire is not satisfied, or frustrated in some way, our intuition may be that the being has been harmed. Phenomenal consciousness cannot be the criterion for ConsciousnessM because we can conceive of beings that do not have subjective experiences, yet have interests. Higher-order thoughts cannot be the criterion for ConsciousnessM because we can conceive of beings that have subjective experiences, which may be unpleasant and harmful, yet cannot have thoughts about those experiences. Again, although both of these views of consciousness may be independently significant to moral consideration, neither of them can serve as the minimal criteria for 20 One thing at issue here is whether first-order desires are reflexive desires, i.e. desires of which the desirer is aware, or non-reflexive desires. This is another distinction that I will not, at present, address in any depth. For my purposes, I assume that both types of desires could be frustrated, therefore resulting in harm, even though I recognize that a justification for this assumption would be beneficial. This also raises another issue that, in a more complete account of this view ought to be developed, but will be merely mentioned in the current discussion: the explanation of the relationship between intentionality and desires, especially in the reflexive case. In the full treatment of this topic, I hope to do a complete analysis of these issues. 21 This is not to say that having desires is necessarily sufficient for having interests; in fact, it may be asked whether sentience may also serve as a foundation for having interests. On the face of it, there is a certain plausibility to this view; however, the capacity to feel pain may not generate an interest in avoiding pain unless the sentient being has a desire to not experience pain. Beings that are sentient may be able to experience pain, but pain itself may not carry much moral weight unless the being has a desire to avoid such sensations. ConsciousnessM. The first-order desire account is a more basic account of consciousness that explains how a being can have minimum basic interests. It may seem puzzling how beings can have first-order desires without having thoughts about those desires or a particular subjective feel associated with those desires; I appeal to two examples from Carruthers for a solution. Consider first the case of a hungry animal. It seems perfectly consistent that it can have desires without having higher-order thoughts about those desires: “suppose that an animal has a strong desire to eat, and that this desire is not activated; suppose, too, that the animal is aware that it is not now eating; then that seems sufficient for its desire to be frustrated, despite the fact that the animal may be incapable of higher-order belief.”22 The animal is aware of its desire, and the fact that its desire is unsatisfied, without having any higher-order thoughts about any aspect of the desire or its fulfillment. Higher-order thoughts are not necessary for desires and therefore are unnecessary for having interests. Second, consider the case of ‘Phenumb,’ a being who has desires without phenomenological experiences of those desires. The case of Phenumb is a more complex example, but yields similar conclusions about the necessity of phenomenal consciousness: [When Phenumb] achieves a goal he does not experience any warm glow of success, or any feelings of satisfaction. And when he believes that he had failed to achieve a goal, he does not experience any pangs of regret or feelings of depression. Nevertheless, Phenumb has the full range of attitudes characteristic of conscious desire-achievement and desire-frustration. So when Phenumb achieves a goal he often comes to have the conscious belief that his desire has been satisfied, and he knows that the desire itself has been extinguished; moreover, he often believes (and asserts) that it was worthwhile for him to attempt to achieve that goal and that the goal was a valuable one to have obtained. Similarly, when Phenumb fails to achieve a goal he often comes to believe that his desire has been frustrated, while he knows that the desire itself continues to exist (now in the form of a wish) and he often believes (as asserts) that it would have been worthwhile to achieve that goal, and that something valuable to him has now failed to come about.23 22 Carruthers, 2000, 207. 23 Carruthers, 2000, 206-207. Phenumb has goals without having a subjective, associated feeling regarding what it is like to have goals, achieve goals, or fail to achieve goals. This seems to indicate that it is possible to have first-order desires without any associated subjective feel, thus rendering phenomenal consciousness unnecessary to desires and unnecessary to interests. Although phenomenal consciousness and higher-order thoughts may be relevant to having desires, it is not the case that either is necessary. The ability to have first-order desires is the minimal level of consciousness necessary for ConsciousnessM.24 Of course, there may be objections to this account. One could argue that there are unconscious desires, possessed by plants and animals (including humans). If this is true than plants are also within the sphere of morally considerable beings and, while many people may recognize that at least some animals are morally considerable (i.e., the family pet), few would intuitively extend that consideration to plants. The issue of unconscious desires is one that will need to be considered for a complete, global, criteria for moral significance; however, at present I am offering neither a global nor a complete account. There are arguably many objects that are the appropriate objects of moral consideration, and there are arguably many other theories that can assign moral significance on many criteria. My claim is simply that insofar as beings have conscious desires, they are morally significant in a way that generates rights.25 Another objection to my criteria of sufficiency for moral status is first-order desires may cast the sphere of rights-bearing status too broadly. It might seem absurd to say that honeybees have rights because they perceive or express their quest for honey. Many would be categorically opposed to using this criterion for granting rights (as opposed to a more traditional 24 What I offer here is a nascent account of higher-order desires that has several problems with it. Again, this issue will be further addressed in the complete treatment. 25 One major part of the argument that I have left out here is the connection between the frustration of desires (and higher-order desires in general) and harm. criteria, like rationality). I hope to defend my view against such objections by arguing that firstorder desires can serve as a minimum criterion for assigning to beings that possess this status the very basic right to not be harmed. The Nature of the Right Not to be Harmed Moral status requires particular kinds of treatment if it is to amount to anything at all and, as I shall argue, the best account of what this treatment requires is one that appeals to rights. The Pragmatic Justification for Rights On the face of it, merely identifying a being as morally considerable may be enough to ensure appropriate treatment. If this is true, then it seems that an account of rights is not strictly necessary; but at least two problems undermine this. The first is that while moral status may require moral consideration, what that consideration amounts to may not require very much, particularly in the case of treatment. The second problem is that while moral status seems to require something in the way of consideration, it really does nothing to guarantee consideration or treatment the way rights-claims do. In short, in order to secure the significance of moral status, especially in the case of harmability, the status needs to be codified by rights. To appreciate the claim that rights are the best way to capture moral significance more fully, consider a more complete treatment of the two previously mentioned problems. The first was that moral status might be practically vacuous. If all that moral status requires is that I give some, or perhaps even equal, consideration to your interest in avoiding harm, then it is not clear that I have any strong obligation to actually avoid or refrain from harming you. Although this shortcoming may happen in any account of how we ought to act, it is particularly prevalent in utilitarian approaches. An excellent example of this is evident in Peter Singer’s utilitarianbased account of how we ought to treat animals. Singer argues that beings have inherent value (which is roughly analogous to my use of moral significance) in virtue of their ability to experience pleasure and pain. Because sentience is inherently valuable, there is no moral justification for refusing to consider the interests of beings that suffer.26 Any being that has the ability to experience pleasure and pain, and therefore an interest in not suffering, ought to be counted and weighed as much as any being with that same interest. In this sense, all animals are to be considered equally. Though Singer argues because every sentient being ought to be given due consideration, what counts as due consideration on his views need not necessarily amount to much. Because utilitarianism is a maximizing doctrine, many trivial benefits to different beings could outweigh one very significant harm to a single being. For example, the pain and suffering of civets, whose musk is used by the perfume industry as a carrier to extend fragrance, can (in principle) be offset by the arguably trivial pleasure many people feel knowing that the scent of the perfume they put on in the morning will last until they re-apply it the next day. Therefore, although we may consider the suffering of the civets, we are under no obligation to treat them in any way that minimizes their suffering given that it is offset by utility aggregation. Inherent value in Singer’s theory, and arguably other non-rights-based approaches, need not count for very much in terms of treatment. 27 The second problem with mere moral considerability, that moral considerability may not guarantee any type of treatment or consideration, can be best understood with an example influenced by Lyons and Thomson.28 Imagine an orange farmer, O, who has the status of owning an orange tree. O has this status in virtue of owning the land the tree is on, having planted the tree, and having tended and cared for the tree until the present. Under normal circumstances, most would agree that O’s status as the owner of the orange tree means that 26 Singer, Animal Liberation, 8. Such aggregation does not violate the Benthamic principle of equal consideration. A being’s interests can be given equal consideration, but ultimately very little weight. 27 From the “Mary” example in David Lyon’s “Utility as a Possible Ground of Rights” and from the “Famous Violinist” example in Judith Jarvis Thomson’s “A Defense of Abortion.” 28 we ought not pick fruit from, or otherwise interfere with, the tree. However, if someone, S, was starving and the only food source close enough to save S’s life was an orange from O’s tree, many people would have the intuition that it is perfectly acceptable, if not required, to either take an orange from the tree or for O to give S an orange. In a case where there was any kind of interest competing with O’s ownership of the tree, it seems like it is permissible to infringe on O’s status as owner. The case seems to be quite different if we say that O has a right to the tree, and we view that right in the strong sense.29 Once we grant that O has a right to the tree, it does not matter that S may be starving—we ought to respect O’s right. In light of this, while O may be very unkind if O refuses S an orange, S would be acting unjustly taking an orange without O’s permission. It seems like a rights-based account of status ensures particular treatment more than mere moral considerability. The Status-Based Approach and Its Benefits over Interest/Utilitarian Theories The previous section has argued that we need a rights-based account in order for moral status to have any significant force. One of the foundational assumptions in that argument was that a status-based justification of rights was the best approach for justifying the right not to be harmed. In the full treatment of this topic, I hope to give an argument for why the status-based justification for rights, in particular the right not to be harmed, is the most desirable justification. For now, I offer a brief presage of the argument. A status-based approach reflects the significance of certain natural attributes. We often find such attributes so significant that we think rights emerge from them. These rights are, ideally, inviolable (or serve as constraints) against the claims and interests of others. So, for example, I have the right to bodily integrity since I am a rational autonomous being who can control her physical self. Under interest theories of rights, a being has a right if and only if that being has some interest that is sufficient Although this needs to be developed, the intuition behind the “strong” rights claim is one that views rights as inviolable side-constraints. 29 to generate a duty.30 Interest theories do not seem to generate rights that have the same strength since such rights seem to be violable in cases where their violation would benefit either some other, more pressing interest of the individual, or overall interests of the individual’s community. The discussion of the strengths and weakness of these contrasting justifications is much more complex than what I have sketched above; however, the basic claim that I will return to is that the status-based justification is more desirable since it yields rights that are more robust.31 To further strengthen my nascent argument regarding the benefit of the status approach for the case of harm, consider the following two examples: The first will show that the status-based approach yields more robust, less violable rights; and the second will show that paternalism, which may be especially relevant in the harm case, is better avoided under the status-based approach. Example 1. Although interest theories of rights may justify rights that are strong when the interest motivating them is strong, they may equally justify the violation of such rights when there are stronger conflicting interests. Consider Thomson’s example of the famous violinist with a slight shift in focus.32 In this example, I awake one morning to find that my kidneys have been attached to the failing kidneys of a famous violinist without my consent. No one would deny that, generally, everyone having the right to bodily integrity promotes interests; however, the interest account may permit the violation of that right when a more pressing right, like the right to life, requires it.33 The promotion of the violinist’s right to life, which is seen as a right 30 Raz, 166. 31 Much of the discussion here will be motivated by existing arguments about status v. interest theories of rights justification. On the status-based side, I will consider discussions from Betham, 1796; Griffin, 1989, Kamm, 2002; Quinn, 1993; Nagel, 2002; Nozick, 1974; Scanlon, 1977, Sen, 1982. 32 33 Thomson, “A Defense of Abortion.” Of course, many may argue that there is no right to life but instead a right not to be unjustly killed. For the sake of this example, I intentionally omit this debate. that promotes stronger interests, may justify the violation of my arguably weaker interest in my bodily integrity. This is intuitively unsatisfactory. Even when the example requires that I only be attached to the violinist for one hour, it still seems problematic to say that the violinist’s right to life exerts a duty on my that I forsake my right to bodily integrity and provide him with access to my kidneys. A status-based theory of rights would arguably justify both the right to life and the right to bodily integrity by appeal to the same criteria -- most likely status as a moral person. Under this account, there could be no justifiable violation of one right by appeal to the stronger interests of the other right since “The strength of the right is not a mark of the strength of the interest it protects, but a mark of the fact that the right is a response to a characteristic of persons that makes persons important.”34 Example 2. Interest theories of rights run the risk of justifying rights that are, or are perceived to be, in the interest of a being without necessarily respecting fundamental features of a being.35 Consider a 21 year old who is pulled over while driving drunk, D. The judge decides that, since it is D’s first offense, D will not be punished even though she was found guilty. The judge may offer the justification that D has a history of being an upstanding young person and it is neither in her interest, not society’s, to punish her for a momentary transgression. D’s right to be punished is overridden when the judge decides that the interests of all relevant parties are best served by overriding that right.36 To see why this is problematic I turn to Kant’s argument for punishment: that the right, and correlative duty, of punishment emerges from the fact that the punished is the kind of person who deserves that right. Kant argues, rightly so, that not punishing a rational being who has committed a crime fails to 34 Kamm, Rights, 487. As Kamm notes: “ …some rights are a response to the good (worth, importance, dignity) of the persons and/or his sovereignty over himself, rather than a response to what is good for the person.” (487). 36 This example is motivated by the arguments for the right and duty of punishment in Morris, Herbert, 1968, "Persons and Punishment," The Monist, 52, pp. 475-501 and in Immanuel Kant, The Philosophy of Law, Part II trans. W. Hastie (1887). Note that the original right to punishment was justified, in this case by an interest account. 35 respect the person as a rational end in herself. In D’s case, the judge’s decision to promote overall interests arguably fails to respect D as they kind of being she is. Ontology, Taxonomy, and Correlativity I have been talking about rights without giving a clear account of what I think they really are, how they are classified, and what they amount to. One of the things I hope to do in the larger treatment of this topic is to give a more complete justification for using general claim rights in rem as the kind of rights that best capture what the right not to be harmed requires. This will involve a more detailed explanation, as well as an analysis of terminological distinctions, of what general rights are and why they should be taken as the basic right-unit to emerge from a being’s status as harmable. My initial intuition is that general claim rights most easily emerge from a status-based or natural rights approach. General rights are a class of rights put forth by HLA Hart that have characteristics very much distinct from the arguably more robust ‘special right.’ Although I hope to offer an argument in favor of general rights, for now consider Hart’s explanation of the differences between general rights and specific rights: 1) General rights do not arise out of any special relationship or transaction between men. 2) They are not rights which are peculiar to those who have them but are rights which all men capable of choice have in absence of those special conditions which give rise to special rights. 3) General rights have as correlatives obligations not to interfere to which everyone is subject and not merely the parties to some special relationship or transaction, though of course they will often be asserted when some particular persons threaten to interfere as a moral objection to that interference.37 The primary benefits I see for viewing rights based on a being’s status as capable of experiencing harm as general rights are a) the rights exist more or less naturally, without any need for contracting, and b) they seem to capture features unique to the nature of harm, without placing undue and unjustified burdens on duty-bearers. The further distinction of claim rights into rights in rem and rights in personam offers a degree of finesse that a general account of HLA Hart, “Are There Any Natural Rights?” in The Philosophical Review, vol. 64, No. 2 (Apr., 1955), 188. 37 claim rights may not adequately capture in the case of harm.38 I hope to show that since general claim rights in rem can necessitate correlative duties without the need for explicit contracting, they may offer the best rights framework for the case of harm. This would be very beneficial because it seems patently absurd that, if I am the kind of being that can experience harm if you kick me, that I need to contract with you in order for me to have the right that you refrain from harming me in this way. Of course, this raises the objection of whether uncontracted rights can really have any strictly correlative duties. It seems problematic to assume that merely because I have a right emergent from some status other beings necessarily have a duty to respect that right. Concluding this analysis of the nature of rights I will offer a discussion of correlativity and the duties that correspond to a right to not be harmed.39 Although at this point I will not delve into the textual analysis required by the above section, I can offer some remarks regarding tensions I foresee with rights and duties functioning within the concept of harm. Assume that I have successfully argued that beings with the appropriate status have a right to not be harmed. Assume also that I have argued that, in order to best make sense of what rights require, if one or more beings who can perform the correlative duty exists, such beings will have that duty.40 On one side I want to argue that, 38 Although I will elaborate on this distinction further, for now an overview of the terms is in order. General claim rights in rem, in relation to the issue of harm, would have the approximate form: x has a right that she not be interfered with when she does not want interference. Such a right is not directed against any particular person, but against all interference in general. General claim rights in personam are in some ways more complex. There is argument that it is very difficult to have general claim rights in personam since in personam rights usually require some form of contracting and are thus typically viewed as special rights. Of benefit to the discussion of duties may be an examination of Kant’s arguments regarding the nature of duties towards animals presented in Lectures on Ethics. Kant claims that we, at best, have indirect duties to animals, which are in effect direct duties to humans. This argument may be of interest because it allows for duties (albeit indirect ones) that are not correlative to rights (since animals are not capable of bearing rights). 39 40 Please forgive the awkwardness of this phraseology. The reason for it is that I want status-based rights to be natural, and not contingent on the existence of an appropriate duty-bearer. What I mean by this is that if a being possesses the appropriate criteria to bear a right, then the being has that right even if the since the aspect of harm that is more significant for generating rights is the subjective aspect, beings have duties to not cause me to experience any harm. At least two potential problems that emerge from this. The first is that this way of stating the duty perhaps permits (or at least does not fault) unintentional instances where the duty-bearer causes harm. The second, and potentially more damning, problem is that focusing so much on the subjective nature of harm may mean that instances where beings objectively, but not subjectively, harm me are not violations of my right. While I believe that the first problem could be more easily fixed, the second problem seems to have solutions that are more difficult. The most obvious solution to the second problem is to change the right from ‘a right not to be caused to experience harm’ to ‘a right not to be harmed’; however, this strikes me as undesirable and leads to the other side of my argument. It is obvious that objective harm is bad; this was especially evident in the example of the poisoned wife. No one would say that W’s right to not be harmed has not been violated merely because she had no subjective experience of the harm. At the same time however, many would have the intuition, as in the original case of P and N, that instances where objective harms lead to subjective harms are somehow worse than objective harm alone. This tension leads to some problems in how exactly I can express the nature of both the right and correlative duties that emerge from a being’s status as harmable. The duties that emerge from the right to not be harmed (regardless of how, specifically, I end up qualifying the right) may be exceedingly complex; however, this need not detract from the legitimacy of the right itself. Conclusion being is the last being in existence (i.e., there is no correlative duty-bearer). However, the only way to really make practical sense of what the right requires is to conceptualize it in terms of duties such that if another being was present, and he or she has the satisfied the criteria necessary for duty-bearing status, then he or she is obligated to uphold the correlative duty. My goal in this discussion was to show that the nature of harm is both conceptually complex and significant enough to serve as a foundation for a right. Some of the potential outcomes of such a view of rights may involve a reclassification of what types of beings may count as, at least in a minimal sense, rights-bearing agents. I hope to test a full account of the theory presented here against problematic cases involving torture, animals, and human beings who are developmentally different from the norm. It is my hope that testing a harm-based rights view against such non-standard cases with illuminate and shortcomings with the view that may not be obvious when it is tested against the “normal” human paradigm. Future plans aside, I hope to have raised some interesting issues about the nature of harm and the nature of rights that may emerge from viewing harm as morally significant. BIBLIOGRAPHY Jeffrey, Andrew “Polemarchus and Socrates on Justice and Harm” Phronesis: A Journal of Ancient Philosophy, vol. 24, pp. 54-69, 1979 Applbaum, Arthur Isak. "Are Violations of Rights Ever Right?" Ethics: An International Journal of Social, Political, and Legal Philosophy, vol. 108, no. 2, pp. 340-366, January 1998 Bekoff, Marc; Gruen, Lori “Animal Welfare and Individual Characteristics: A Conversation Against Speciesism” Ethics and Behavior, vol. 3, no. 2, pp. 163-175, 1993 Benditt, T.M. “Benefit and Harm” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, vol. 37, pp. 116-120, September 1976 Bentham, Jeremy, (1796), Anarchical Fallacies, in Waldron, Jeremy Nonsense Upon Stilts: Bentham, Burke, and Marx on the Rights of Man, London: Methuen ,1987: 46-76 Block, N. (1990), "Inverted Earth," Philosophical Perspectives, 4, J. ed. Tomberlin, Northridge: Ridgeview Publishing Company. Bonkowsky J.L., Johnson J., Carey J.C., Smith A.G., Swoboda K.J., “An infant with primary tooth loss and palmar hyperkeratosis: a novel mutation in the NTRK1 gene causing congenital insensitivity to pain with anhidrosis” in Pediatrics. 2003 Sep;112(3 Pt 1):e237-41. Brandt, Richard B. "The Concept of a Moral Right and Its Function." Journal of Philosophy, vol. 80, pp. 29-45, January 1983 Brentano, F. (1995) Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint, ed. L. McAllister, trans. A. C. Rancurello, D.B. Terrell, L. McAlister, London: Routledge. Brink, David. “The Separateness of Persons, Distributive Norms, and Moral Theory.” in Value, Welfare, and Morality, Frey, R G (ed)New York: Cambridge Univ Pr, 1993 Brock, Dan W. “The Non-Identity Problem and Genetic Harm--The Case of Wrongful Handicaps” Bioethics, vol. 9, no. 3-4, pp. 269-275, July 1995 Brown Jr., Stuart M. "Inalienable Rights." Philosophical Review, vol. 64, pp. 192-211, April 1955 Campbell, Tom (ed) Human Rights: From Rhetoric to Reality (Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell Ltd., 1986). Carrier, L.S. “Abortion and the Right to Life” Social Theory and Practice: An International and Interdisciplinary Journal of Social Philosophy, vol. 3, pp. 381-401, Fall 1975 Carruthers, P. (1989), “Brute Experience” in The Journal of Philosophy, 89: 258-269. Carruthers, P. (1992), The animals issue: Moral theory in practice, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Carruthers, P. (1998), “Animal Subjectivity” PSYCHE, 4 (3). Carruthers, P. (1999), “Sympathy and Subjectivity,” in Australasian Journal of Philosophy 77, 465–482. Carruthers, P. (2000), Phenomenal Consciousness: A Naturalistic Theory, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Carruthers, P. (2004a ), “Suffering without Subjectivity,” in Philosophical Studies, 121:99-125. Carruthers, P. (2004b), “Phenomenal Concepts and Higher-order Experiences,” in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 67, 316–336. Chalmers, D.J. (1996), The Conscious Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Churchland, P. (1985), "Reduction, Qualia, and Direct Introspection of Brain States," Journal of Philosophy, 82, 8-28. Carter, Alan “Can We Harm Future People?” Environmental Values, vol. 10, no. 4, pp. 429454, November 2001 Dagger, Richard “Harm, Utility, and the Obligation to Obey the Law” Archiv fuer Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie, vol. 68, pp. 102-108, 1982 Dalton, Peter “The Irony of the Self Harm Principle” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, vol. 63, pp. 381-391, October 1982 Davies, M. and Humphreys, G. (1993) Consciousness, Blackwells: Oxford. Decew, Judith Wagner. "Moral Rights: Conflicts and Valid Claims." Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition, vol. 54, pp. 63-86, July 1988 Dretske. F. (1993) “Conscious Experience” in Mind 102: 406, 262-283. Dripps, Donald A. “The Liberal Critique of the Harm Principle” Criminal Justice Ethics, vol. 17, no. 2, pp. 3-18, Summer-Fall 1998 Dworkin, Gerald, Morality, Harm, and the Law, Boulder : Westview Press, 1994 Dworkin, Ronald. "Rights as Trumps." in Waldron, 1984 Feinberg, Joel. "Duties, Rights, and Claims." American Philosophical Quarterly, vol. 3, pp. 137144, April 1966 Feinberg, Joel “Environmental Pollution and the Threshold of Harm” Hastings Center Report, vol. 14, pp. 27-31, June 1984 Feinberg, Joel. Freedom and Fulfillment: Philosophical Essays. Princeton: Princeton Univ Pr., 1996 Feinberg, Joel “Human Duties and Animal Rights” eds. Morris, Richard Knowles and Fox, Michael W. On the Fifth Day Washington : Acropolis Books, 1978 Feinberg, Joel “The Moral and Legal Responsibility of the Bad Samaritan” Criminal Justice Ethics, vol. 3, pp. 56-68, Winter-Spring 1984 Feinberg, Joel. "The Nature and Value of Rights." Journal of Value Inquiry, 4, 1970: 243-257. Finnis, John. Natural Law and Natural Rights. Oxford : Clarendon Press ; New York : Oxford University Press, 1980 Finkelstein, Claire “Two Men and a Plank” Legal Theory, vol. 7, no. 3, pp. 279-306, September 2001 Francione, Gary L. “Comparable Harm and Equal Inherent Value: The Problem of Dog in the Lifeboat” Between the Species: A Journal of Ethics, vol. 11, no. 3-4, pp. 81-89, Summer-Fall 1995 Frankfurt, Harry, “Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person.” Journal of Philosophy, vol. 68, pp. 5-20, January 1971 Frankena, William K. "Natural and Inalienable Rights." Philosophical Review, vol. 64, pp. 212232, April 1955 Frazier, Robert L. (1998). Duty. In E. Craig (Ed.), Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London: Routledge. Retrieved December 10, 2006, from http://www.rep.routledge.com/article/L018SECT1 Fried, Charles. "Distributive Justice." Social Philosophy and Policy, vol. 1, pp. 45-59, Autumn 1983 Gandhi, Ramchandra “Injury, Harm, Damage, Pain, Etc.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, vol. 34, pp. 266-269, December 1973 Gewirth, Alan. "Are There Any Absolute Rights?" Philosophical Quarterly, vol. 31, pp. 1-16, January 1981 Gewirth, Alan. "Can Utilitarianism Justify Any Moral Rights?" in Rights and duties ed Carl Wellman New York : Routledge, 2002 (vol 2) Gibbs,-Paul-J “Ethical Connectionism” Contemporary Philosophy, vol. 18, no. 4 & 5, pp. 50-57, July-August-September-October 1996 Glendon, Mary Ann. Rights Talk: The Impoverishment of Political Discourse. New York : Free Press ; Toronto : Collier Macmillan ; New York : Maxwell Macmillan, c1991 Gontar, David P “Permitting Harm: A Reply to Eric Mack” Southwestern Journal of Philosophy, vol. 9, pp. 15-22, Fall 1978 Goodpaster K.E. (1978), “On Being Morally Considerable” in The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 75, No. 6 Goodrum, Craig R “Notes on the Harm Principle” Personalist, vol. 57, pp. 239-250, Summer 1976 Grey, William “Epicurus and the Harm of Death” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, vol. 77, no. 3, pp. 358-364, September 1999 Griffin, D. R. (1976), The Question of Animal Awareness: Evolutionary Continuity of Mental Experience, New York, The Rockefeller University Press. Griffin, D.R. (1981), The Question of Animal Awareness: Evolutionary Continuity of Mental Experience, New York: The Rockefeller University Press. Griffin, D. R. (1984), Animal Thinking, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Griffin, D. R. (1992), Animal Minds, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Griffin, D.R. (2001), Animal Minds: Beyond Cognition to Consciousness, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Griffin, James. "Towards a Substantive Theory of Rights.” in Frey, ed., Utility and Rights Griffin, James (1989) Well-Being: Its Meaning, Measurement, and Moral Importance, Oxford: Oxford University Press Grover, Dorothy “Posthumous Harm” Philosophical Quarterly, vol. 39, pp. 334-353, July 1989 Hacker, P.M.S. “Definition in Jurisprudence” Philosophical Quarterly, vol. 19, pp. 343-347, October 1969 Hardin, Russel. Morality within the Limits of Reason. Harman, G. (1990), "The Intrinsic Quality of Experience," in Philosophical Perspectives, 4, J. Tomberlin, ed., Northridge: Ridgeview Publishing Company. Harman, John D. “Harm, Consent, and Distress” Journal of Value Inquiry, vol. 15, pp. 293-310, 1981 Hart, H.L.A., 1961, The Concept of Law, Oxford: Oxford University Press Hart, H.L.A. 1982, Essays on Bentham: Studies in Jurisprudence and Political Theory, Oxford: Clarendon Press Hart, H.L.A. "Are There Any Natural Rights?" Philosophical Review 64 (1955): 175-191 Hart, H.L.A. "Legal and Moral Obligation.” in Essays in Moral Philosophy (ed.) A.I. Melden Seattle: University of Washington Press, 1966. Hart, H.L.A. “Legal Responsibility and Excuses.” Hausman, Daniel M “Liability, Responsibility, and Harm” Ethics: An International Journal of Social, Political, and Legal Philosophy, vol. 97, pp. 263-269, October 1986 Hohfeld, Wesley Newcomb, Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1919) Holtug, Nils “The Harm Principle” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice: An International Forum, vol. 5, no. 4, pp. 357-389, December 2002 Horgan, T. and Tienson, J. (2002), “The Intentionality of Phenomenology and the Phenomenology of Intentionality.” In D. Chalmers, ed., Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings. Oxford University Press. Husak, Donald. "Why There are No Human Rights," in Smith and Blocker, ed. Applied Social and Political Philosophy, Prentice Hall, 1994 Husserl, E. (1970). Logical Investigations, trans. J. Findlay, London: Routledge. Jenni, Kathie “The Ethics of Awareness: Inattention and Integrity Post Humous Harm” Contemporary Philosophy, vol. 18, no. 4 & 5, pp. 30-36, July-August-September-October 1996 Kagan, Shelly. Normative Ethics. (Boulder, Colo.: Westview, 1998) Kamm, Frances, 1992, "Non-Consequentialism, the Person as an End-in-Itself, and the Significance of Status", Philosophy and Public Affairs, 21: 354-89. Kamm, Frances (2001). Inviolability. In E. Craig (Ed.), Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London: Routledge. Retrieved December 10, 2006, from http://www.rep.routledge.com/article/L140 Kamm, Frances 2002, "Rights", in The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law, Coleman, J., and Shapiro, S. (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press: 476-513. Kant, Immanuel, Lectures on Ethics, Louis Infield, trans. (New York: Harper and Row, 1963) Kant, Immanuel The Philosophy of Law, Part II trans. W. Hastie (1887) Kleinig, John “Crime and the Concept of Harm” American Philosophical Quarterly, vol. 15, pp. 27-36, January 1978 Knowles, Dudley R “A reformulation of the Harm Principle” Political Theory: An International Journal of Political Philosophy, vol. 6, pp. 233-246, May 1978 Kuflik, Arthur, (1998). Moral standing. In E. Craig (Ed.), Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London: Routledge. Retrieved December 10, 2006, from http://www.rep.routledge.com/article/L062 Kymlicka, Will. Multicultural Citizenship: A Liberal Theory of Minority Rights. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996) Ladenson, Robert F. "Two Kinds of Rights." Journal of Value Inquiry 13 (1979): 161-175 Levine, J. (1983) "Materialism and Qualia : The Explanatory Gap" in Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64, 354-361. Lockwood, Jeffrey A. “Not to Harm a Fly: Our Ethical Obligations to Insects” Between the Species: A Journal of Ethics, vol. 4, pp. 204-211, Summer 1988 Lycan, W.G. (1996), Consciousness and Experience , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press. Lyons, David “Liberty and Harm to Others” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, vol. 5 (suppl.), pp. 1-19, 79 1979 Lyons, David “The Correlativity of Rights and Duties” Noûs, vol. 4, pp. 45-57, February 1970 Lyons, David. Utility and Rights, Minneapolis : University of Minnesota Press, c1984 Machan, Tibor. "Some Recent Work in Human Rights Theory." 17 American Philosophical Quarterly 103-16 (1980) Mackie, John, 1979, "Can There be a Rights-Based Moral Theory?", in Waldron 1984: 168-81. Martin, Rex. "Human Rights and Civil Rights." Philosophical Studies 37 (1980): 391 Martin, Rex, (1998). Rights. In E. Craig (Ed.), Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London: Routledge. Retrieved December 10, 2006, from http://www.rep.routledge.com/article/S054 Martin, Rex and Nickel, James “Recent Work on the Concept of Rights” American Philosophical Quarterly, vol. 17, pp. 165-180, July 1980 McCarthy, J. (1980), "Beliefs, machines, and theories" in Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3: 435. McCarthy, David “Intending Harm, Foreseeing Harm, and Failures of the Will” Noûs, vol. 36, no. 4, pp. 622-642, December 2002 McCarthy, David “Harming and Allowing Harm” Ethics: An International Journal of Social, Political, and Legal Philosophy, vol. 110, no. 4, pp. 749-779, July 2000 McCloskey, H.J. "Rights - Some Conceptual Issues." Australian Journal of Philosophy 54 (1976): 99-115. McDowell, Ward. “Are Moral Reasons Hypothetical Imperatives?” McGinn, C. (1991), The Problems of Consciousness: Essays Toward a Resolution, London: Basil Blackwell. McLaughlin, B.P. (2003). “A Naturalist-Phenomenal Realist Response To Block’s Harder Problem,” in Philosophical Issues 13, 2003:163-204. Melden, A. I. Rights and Persons. (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980) Mele, A. Autonomous Agents, New York : Oxford University Press, 1995 Mill, John Stuart, On Liberty Morreim, E Haavi “Conception and the Concept of Harm” Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, vol. 8, pp. 137-158, May 1983 Morris, Herbert, 1968, "Persons and Punishment," The Monist, 52, pp. 475-501 Mullock, Philip “Causing Harm: Criminal Law” Law and Philosophy: An International Journal for Jurisprudence and Legal Philosophy, vol. 7, pp. 67-105, April 1988 Nagel, T. Concealment and Exposure, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002. Nagel, T. (1974), "What is it Like to be a Bat?" in Philosophical Review 83: 435-50. Nagel, T. (1979), Mortal Questions, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Nelson, William. "On the Alleged Importance of Moral Rights." Ratio 18 (1976): 145-155 Nozick, Robert Anarchy, State, and Utopia, New York : Basic Books, (1974) O’Neill, Onora, Faces of Hunger London ; Boston : G. Allen & Unwin, 1986 Passsmore, J. (1974), Man’s Responsibility for Nature, New York: Scribner’s Press. Peffer, Rodney. "A Defense of Rights to Well-Being." 8 Philosophy & Public Affairs 65-87 (1978) Pettit, Philip. "Rights, Constraints, and Trumps." 47 Analysis 8-13 (1987) Porter, Jean. "From natural law to human rights: or, why rights talk matters." 14 J.L. & Relig. 77-96 (1999-2000) Postow,B.C. “Pornography, Indirect Harm, and Feminist Analysis: A Response to the Professors Hayry” Journal of Value Inquiry, vol. 31, no. 4, pp. 553-556, December 1997 Persson, Ingmar “Harming the Non-Conscious” Bioethics, vol. 13, no. 3-4, pp. 294-305, July 1999 Quinn, Warren, Morality and Action, Cambridge ; New York : Cambridge University Press, 1993 Radner, D. and Radner, M. (1989) Animal Consciousness, Buffalo, New York: Prometheus Books. Rainbolt, George. "Rights as Normative Constraints on Others." 53 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ___ (1993)Raphael, D.D. "The Rights of Man and the Rights of the Citizen.” n Political Theory and the Rights of Man (ed.) Raphael London: MacMillan, 1967 Raz, Joseph. "On the Nature of Rights." Mind 93 (1984a): 194-214 Raz, Joseph. "Right-Based Moralities" (1984b) in Waldron, ed., Theories of Rights Raz, Joseph., 1986, The Morality of Freedom, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Regan, T. (1985), “The Case for Animal Rights,” in In Defense of Animals, ed. Peter Singer (New York: Blackwell. Regan, T. (2004), The Case for Animal Rights, Los Angeles: UC Press. Scanlon, T.M. “The Aims and Authority of Moral Theory.” Scanlon, T.M. “Rights, Goals, and Fairness” in Waldron 1984 Schauer, Frederick “The Phenomenology of Speech and Harm” Ethics: An International Journal of Social, Political, and Legal Philosophy, vol. 103, no. 4, pp. 635-653, July 1993 Scheffler, Samuel."Natural Rights, Equality, and the Minimal State." 6 Canadian Journal of Philosophy 59-76 (1976) Schiller, Marvin. "Are There Any Inalienable Rights?" Ethics 79 (1969): 309-315 Sen, Amartya. "Rights and Agency." Philosophy and Public Affairs 11 (1982): 3.-39 Sellars, W. (1956), “Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind” in eds. H. Feigl and M. Scriven, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Mind, vol. 1, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Sharpe, Virginia A. “Why "Do No Harm?"” Theoretical Medicine: An International Journal for the Philosophy and Methodology of Medical Research and Practice, vol. 18, no. 1-2, pp. 197-215, March-June 1997 Shoemaker, S. (1990), "Qualities and Qualia : What's in the Mind" in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 50, Supplement, 109-131. Shue, Henry, Basic Rights, Princeton, N.J. : Princeton University Press, 1980 Shue, Henry “Mediating Duties” Ethics, vol. 98, pp. 687-704, July 1988 Simon,Thomas “Group Harm” Journal of Social Philosophy, vol. 26, no. 3, pp. 123-137, Winter 1995 Sinari,Ramakant “Comments on G.P. Ramachandra's note 'Is There Such a Thing as SelfConsciousness'?” Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research, vol. 15, no. 1, pp. 129132, September-December 1997 Singer, Marcus G. "The Basis of Rights and Duties." Philosophical Studies 23 (1972): 48-57 Singer, P (2002), Animal Liberation, New York : Ecco. Sobel, David “Varieties of Hedonism” Journal of Social Philosophy, vol. 33, no. 2, pp. 240-256, Summer 2002 Sorabji, R. (1993), Animal Minds and Human Morals: The Origin of the Western Debate (Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press. Thomson, Judith J. The Realm of Rights, Cambridge, Mass. : Harvard University Press, 1990 Tierney, Brian. "Villey, Ockham and the Origin of Individual Rights." in John Witte, Jr., & Frank Alexander, The Weightier Matters of Law 1-31 (Atlanta, 1988) Unger, Peter “Causing and Preventing Serious Harm” Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition, vol. 65, no. 3, pp. 227-255, March 1992 Van De Veer. "Are Human Rights Inalienable?" Philosophical Studies 37 (1980): 165-176 Waldron, Jeremy. Theories of Rights (Oxford,1984) Waldron, Jeremy. "Rights in Conflict." Ethics 99 (1989): 503-519 G.J. Warnock, (1971), The Object of Morality, New York: Methuen. Warren, M. (1987), “Difficulties with the Strong Rights Position” in Between the Species Vol. 2, No. 4, 433-441. Wenar, Leif, “The Nature of Rights” Philosophy and Public Affairs, vol. 33, no. 3, pp. 223-252, Summer 2005 White, S.L. (1986), “The Curse of Qualia” in Synthese, Vol 68, 333-68