Andrew Gow (Prof. University of Alberta) Response to Dominique Avon, “Le fait religieux et l’instance critique de l’historien en climat libéral” Cold Frogs vs. Warm-Blooded Theists If were we able to disengage our historical and critical assessments of religious phenomena from our own religious (or anti-religious) engagements, we would attain the form of scholarly distance Dominique Avon suggests as a remedy for confessional and other partisan forms of the history of religion. We ought to be able, he suggests, to describe, analyze and critique religious phenomena in the same way whether they belong to our own religious tradition or not, whether or not we are atheists, whether or not we might have an interest of any kind in the outcome of such critiques and analyses. Or at least he implies the latter, as he does not admit directly or explore the sort of interests we might bring as scholars to the analysis of a religious phenomenon. Avon’s ideas build on and refine the best of the strong tradition of French laïcité and lay scholarship. He admits that secular scholarship on religion can evolve into atheist condemnation of religion, or can be strongly coloured by it. He warns us as much against a scholarship that seeks to discredit religion or to explain it away (as extrinsic to a given problem, or as ‘merely superstructural,’ etc.) as he warns us about the dangers of a confessionally partisan approach. In a lay secular humanist’s ideal world, in an intellectual life lived exclusively according to the dictates of universalist (secular) rationalism à la française, it might indeed be possible to attain the status of the ‘cold frog’ Avon constructs as the ideal scholarly observer of religion. I will admit up front that I respect and like the idea, I might even desire it as a goal, and yet I find that there is a great deal about it that I think does not work. Perhaps some version of it could be made to work for those of us who study religion and have strong religious commitments of our own, but such a position would be both less neutral and more conscious of religious factors. Especially for those of us who are not Christians and therefore whose ‘religion’ might work very differently from the christonormative model of religion posited by Enlightenment laïcité, a different position that does not try to attain complete neutrality but nonetheless provides the same benefits as the position Avon sketches seems to me a better solution. If we were to change those things that need changing (i.e., *mutandis* mutandis) in order to be able to apply Avon’s ideas to scholars of religion in cultures other than that of liberal rationalism (e.g., the intellectual, personal and faith engagements of scholars in other, less secular scholarly cultures), I think we would find that his scholarly ideal would appear both unnatural and impossible from a number of important perspectives. I want, in fact, in some ways at least, to desire it, but I find it impossible to imagine attaining the perspective Avon proposes--at least as it is stated in the article. In many western academic cultures, one’s confessional engagements are worn (even proudly) on one’s sleeve, and in some, those scholars charged primarily with the study of religion have positions in Faculties of Theology (Germany, the Netherlands, but also Anglo-American ‘divinity schools’) with direct and powerful ties to particular churches or confessions -- and not in secular university departments or chairs. Already the institutional frame contributes to a predetermined set of possibilities for the study of religion by such ‘theologians’ (German Theologen), as they often call themselves as a disciplinary designation. The personal history, culture and convictions of such scholars and their loyalties both religious and professional actually exclude them a priori from the cool delights of ‘cold frogdom’. Rather, they tend to see themselves as warm-blooded theists and ordained ministers (as they often are) of their religious community, whose scholarship is designed and mandated to subtend, enrich, refine and expand the theological culture of their fellow Christians (Lutherans, Catholics, Calvinists, Presbyterians, etc.) as well as to make broader scholarly contributions to a broader scholarly community and set of discussions. For many of these ‘official theologians’ -- whose positions are often guaranteed by the State via a concordate with the relevant church, as in Germany --, there is and should be no distinction between faith-based scholarship and scholarship that addresses the larger scholarly community -- since both are undertaken ad maioram gloriam D-i, though in different modes and according to different rules. While Avon is interested less in ‘what is’ than in ‘what should be’, I find it impossible to limit my critique to an ideal when there are so many interesting actual examples to study and consider in practice -- and I submit that only by doing so might one perhaps arrive at a way of critiquing Avon’s ideal that does not also assume that many existing institutional arrangements are inadequate or worse. They might indeed be those things, but I would like at least in this instance to try to be the kind of ‘cold frog’ Avon praises. Continental scholarship outside France about religion not only has a long tradition, it has a number of important pedigrees that themselves provide alternatives to Avon’s rationalist, universalist suspension of judgement. Both Hegelian and Kantian philosophical trajectories come to mind, along with the ideas of a number of early modern French theists. That none of these will suffice for a contemporary historian is probably a moot point. But they provide an intellectual context that also allows, even encourages a certain distance from the religious phenomena one might be observing without insisting that the historian entirely suspend judgement or preference a priori. As much as I dislike the charged partisan approach of both nineteenth-century polemicists and certain contemporary ‘church historians’ such as Thomas Kaufmann (the Professor for early modern Church History at Göttingen), I also like the self-critical but avowedly confessional approach of Volker Leppin (Professor of Reformation History in the Lutheran Faculty of Theology at Jena), an ordained Lutheran minister but in no way a narrow ‘Luther-booster’ -- on the contrary. Neither one could under any circumstances be accused of being ‘cold frogs’ -- and I think scholarship benefits from their passion and engagement for the greater glory of G-d and the enrichment of their own church. The agon in which these two superb scholars of ‘evangelical religion’ (Lutheranism) are engaged could not possible exist in the mode Avon projects as the ideal approach to the history of religion. His approach would actually be detrimental to the vibrant scholarly and ecclesiastical debates about the history of Lutheranism, Protestantism and Christianity in which such scholars are engaged. The problem is that as much as Avon might like us to be able to inhabit, if only intellectually, a thoroughly secular and ‘lay’ space (personally and intellectually), that space is both inaccessible and inhospitable to a large number of the people who might ideally inhabit it. Neither do individuals live in such spaces -- secular Frenchmen and North Americans live just as surely in the long christonormative hangover of Christianity as evangelical Americans live in *both* the Christian present *and* in its aching hangover in secular society. Avon suggests a kind of methodological atheism. But all attempts to arrive at that type of bloodless atheism betray the fixity and power of the fundamentally theological framework in which we, as members of western cultures and as western scholars of religion, remain trapped. In her preface to Politics of Piety: The Islamic Revival and the Feminist Subject (Princeton University Press, 2005), Saba Mahmood writes: “I have come to question our conviction, however well-intentioned, that other forms of human flourishing and life worlds are necessarily inferior to the solutions we have devised under the banner of ‘secular-left’ politics—as if there is a singularity of vision that unites us under this banner, or as if the politics we so proudly claim has not itself produced some spectacular human disasters. This self-questioning does not mean that I have stopped struggling or fighting against the injustices…that currently compound my social existence. (…) [Rather,] we can no longer arrogantly assume that [our] formulations necessarily exhaust ways of living meaningfully and richly in this world” (xi-xii). If we change the phrase “‘secular-left’ politics” to “secular cold-frog methodological atheism” and “life-worlds” to “scholarship”, we can approach a critique of Avon’s ideal that is rooted in both real experience and actual personal engagements and commitments. Mahmood identifies (here implicitly) ‘secular-left politics’ with universalist claims to cultural and social superiority based on the instrumental and utilitarian civic logic of Enlightenment political philosophy. ‘Methodological atheism’ presupposes, just as Enlightenment political philosophy does, that no religious *engagements* have a place in a public sphere constructed according to the dictates of rational discourse. I think one need call only on Kant to suggest the opposite, and I submit that the entire enterprise of the scholarly study of religion from the vantage point of a religiously committed member of a religious community--in a Catholic or Lutheran or even Jewish professorship--is in fact a Kantian undertaking that relies as much on rationality as any methodologically atheistic ( i.e., epistemologically skeptical) approach can do. Rationality, understood in a Kantian manner, is not merely an inorganic logic machine, but the function of a thinking soul-and here is where the cold frogs might find the kitchen too hot. Indeed, the presupposition that we ought to function as cold frogs suggests that the kitchen from which we come, as scholars -- the partisan or at least engaged study of theology -- was too hot for methodologically respectable scholarship and that we had, therefore, to leave the seminary and the cloister to become responsible citizens of a secular republic of letters. This is a specifically French Enlightenment vision of scholarship about religion, of the institutional changes needed to shake off the supposed obscurantism and irrationality of the Old Regime church. Neither Lutheran nor Anglican nor Jewish institutions got in the way, in the 19th century, of a rational approach to scholarship -- historicalcritical Biblical scholarship and the Wissenschaft des Judentums (scholarly Jewish studies) did not grow up in a secular environment, but in Faculties of Theology and divinity schools/institutions for training clergy; and many Catholic scholars and institutions of the 19th century made signal contributions to the development of modern Biblical and religious studies. Neither can these developments in scholarship be attributed directly to the French Revolution, as they were already well underway in the 18th century as elements of alternative forms of ‘Enlightenment’, whether German idealism and empiricism, Anglo-Scottish liberalism, or the Jewish Haskalah. In all these forms of ‘Enlightenment’, as among many French thinkers of that age, theism, even a very warm engagement for theist solutions to ‘mechanical’ problems, was dominant. But unlike in France, that theism and the confessional engagements of individual scholars remained central to scholarship on religion throughout the 19th and 20th centuries -- often with mediocre and quite self-satisfied results, admittedly. ‘Religious studies’ as a project of recuperation, with its roots in Chicago and the work of such scholars as Eliade, was not so much a repudiation of theism as a sidelining of the issue: the contemporary discipline of religious studies assumes that theists and atheists, as well as confessionally bound and unbound scholars can work on religious topics with equal rights and legitimacy -- so long as their engagements are clear. To return to Avon, one might speak here of suspending not disbelief, as readers of fiction must do, but of temporarily suspending belief -- in an absolutely contingent way and for heuristic purposes only, without assuming a foreign subjectposition that requires a decoupling of one’s lived commitments from one’s scholarly persona and approach. Perhaps I have arrived at a position not very far from Avon’s, yet the difference seems important to me: I wear a kippa in the archive and the library and the classroom; I do not work or attend meetings or give papers on the sabbath or on Jewish holidays. I cannot entirely disengage those commitments from my readings and my interpretations -though as a scholar I feel I must not allow that perspective to pre-determine my conclusions, to block my vision, or to disallow particular avenues of research, even if they might be distasteful or annoying to me. A modest and rather postmodern form of ‘full disclosure’ (à la Hayden White) and a deliberately artificial ‘suspension of belief’ seem to me a better path than a universalizing call for methodological atheism, even as a temporary state.