The Ethics of Active Defense I. The Traditional View of Forceful Self-Defense. The traditional view of selfdefense (and I will use this term to include defense of property) sets forth a number of necessary conditions for the justifiable use of force (physical or technological) to defend against a threat: A. Victim’s apprehension of a threat must be reasonable. B. Force must be directed against the person creating the threat to Victim’s interests. This means that one cannot permissibly harm – at least not knowingly – innocent bystanders in order to defend against the threat. The rationale for this principle is that the innocent bystander has done nothing that would justify infringing her rights with the use of force. C. The behavior that creates the threat against Victim’s interests must be morally culpable. This is perhaps the most controversial element of the traditional view: if correct, it entails that it would be morally impermissible, for example, to use force against someone with a severe psychotic illness who threatens your life. D. The force must be proportional to the interest being threatened. Proportionality here should not be thought of as strict equality: it seems reasonable to think that the victim can use somewhat more force than is used by the aggressor to repel the attack. But there are obvious limits to how much more force. If someone attacks me with his fists, it would, other things being equal, be impermissible for me to respond by stabbing him with a knife. The proportionality requirement is probably the least controversial – though can be extremely difficult to apply in cases that do not involve direct physical attacks. What, for example, aggressive response would be proportional to the threat posed by someone stealing your wallet? Your car? Setting fire to your home? Applied ethicists seem, in any event, to agree that it is impermissible to take a life to defend property (though some laws allow deadly force in defense of one’s dwelling). E. The force must be necessary to prevent the interest from being harmed. This has a number of interesting implications. 1. The threatened harm must be imminent. There are always other ways to deal with a non-imminent threat. 2. Victim has a duty of escape. If one can protect the interest from harm by running away, then one has a duty to run away. 3. Victim has a duty to adopt the least aggressive measure needed to protect the interest. If escape isn’t possible and the threatened harm is imminent, then one has a duty to respond in with as little force as is reasonably needed to prevent the interest from being harmed. Here’s an example to illustrate the principle. Suppose A attacks V and V has the ability – and knows this – to effectively respond to A in two ways. V can disarm A either by inflicting an injury that is proportional to the one that A is attempting to inflict on V or by adopting defensive measures that will neutralize the attack without inflicting any injury. If V adopts the more aggressive response, V has committed a moral wrong. 4. II. The measure must be reasonably calculated to protect the interest. One cannot permissibly use force to retaliate against a successful attack. If A smashes V’s car and then runs away, V cannot permissibly go smash A’s car – according to the traditional view of self-defense. Retaliation (or punishment) is not covered by the ethical rules governing self-defense. Defense of Others. Generally, the same principles govern the forceful defense of other persons. One person can direct proportional force against a culpable threat to another person’s interests if necessary to prevent the latter’s interests from being harmed. There are, however, a couple of ethical caveats. A. 3rd Party Defender’s apprehension of a threat must be reasonable. Here it is important to note that the Victim has information available to him that 3rd Party Defender may not. E.g., Victim will know whether the attack is genuine – and not staged or play-fighting. B. 3rd Party Defender may not violate any rights of Victim in defending Victim. If 3PD causes morally significant harm to Victim (without Victim’s express or implied consent) in the course of defending Victim, 3PD has potentially wronged Victim. III. Necessity Defense. While it is generally impermissible for one person to infringe the rights of an innocent person to defend against an attack, a person may permissibly infringe the rights of an innocent person if needed to defend against grave harm to an individual or the public provided that the infringement (and resulting harm) to the innocent person is significantly less serious than the harm prevented. IV. The Implications of the Traditional View for Active Defense. Here are some examples of active defense measures that seem to violate the principles described above. A. Conxion v. E-hippies. E-hippies, an online activist group, launched a DoS against Conxion, which hosted a WTO server. Conxion traced the attack directly back to E-hippies server. Instead of responding to the attack by simply filtering the incoming packets at the router, Conxion directed them back to the E-hippies server, which shut it down for several hours. Though they did not add any mail of their own, this seems to violate principle IE3 above. B. The Good Samaritan Worm. In response to the MSBlaster worm, someone wrote and released a worm that deletes MSBlaster and attempts to install the proper security patch on affected machines. This violates principle IIB. The writer of the friendly worm commits a trespass against the machines it attempts to help. Moreover, the wrong is compounded to the extent that the friendly worm actually results in additional harm to those machines. C. DDoS Attacks. One concern here is that a counterattack may cause damage to persons whose machines have been used without their knowledge by the person staging the attack. This would seem to violate IB, above. D. Tracebacks. Even tracing an attack back to its source can raise ethical issues. Insofar as one has to trace the attack through innocent machines that have been used or compromised by the attacker, one may violate the rights of the owners or those machines.