The trouble with multiculturalism The term ‘multicultural’ has come to define a society that is particularly diverse, usually as a result of immigration. It has also come to define the policies necessary to manage such diversity. The concept of multiculturalism, in other words, has come to embody both a description of a society and a prescription for managing that society. Multiculturalism has become both the problem and the answer. Another way of putting this is that we often confuse the distinction between diversity as lived experience and multiculturalism as a political process. On the one hand multiculturalism describes the experience of living in a society that is less insular, less homogenous, more cosmopolitan than before. On the other hand, it has come to mean a political process through which cultural differences are given public recognition and affirmation and the acceptance of the idea that social justice requires the equal treatment not just of individuals but also of their cultural beliefs. I want to argue here that the multiculturalist description of society is a highly distorted one, while the multiculturalist prescription creates the very problems it is meant to solve. Multiculturalism, I want to suggest, is not a response to a diverse society. Rather, the pursuit of multicultural policies has led us to imagine that we are far more diverse than we are. They have also helped resurrect ways of thinking about difference that are rooted in racial theory. Kenan Malik / University of Surrey/ ‘The trouble with multiculturalism’ To put these arguments in context I will begin by looking briefly at the historical and philosophical roots of multiculturalism. Then I want to explore some of the philosophical and political problems raised by multiculturalism, and why we feel ours to be particularly diverse age. And finally, I want to look at the political and sociological consequences of multiculticultural policies in this country. Contemporary multiculturalism is a marriage between the Romantic idea of culture and an equally Romantic idea of identity. Romanticism is one of those concepts that cultural historians find invaluable but which is almost impossible to define. It took many political forms – it lies at the root both of modern conservatism and many strands of radicalism – and appeared in different national versions. Romanticism was not a specific political or cultural view but rather described a cluster of attitudes and preferences: for the concrete over the abstract; the unique over the universal; nature over culture; the organic over the mechanical; emotion over reason; intuition over intellect; particular communities over abstract humanity. These attitudes came to the fore towards the end of the eighteenth century largely in reaction to the predominant views of the Enlightenment. Much has been written about the varieties of beliefs and arguments within the eighteenth century and it is no longer fashionable to talk about the Enlightenment. Nevertheless, beneath the differences there were a number of beliefs that most of the philosophes held in common. 2 Kenan Malik / University of Surrey/ ‘The trouble with multiculturalism’ There was a broad consensus that humans possessed a common nature; that the same institutions and forms of governance would promote human flourishing in all societies; that reason allowed humans to discover these institutions; and that through the development of such institutions social inequalities and hierarchies could be minimised and even erased. The Romantic counter-Enlightenment challenged all these beliefs. Whereas Enlightenment philosophes saw progress as civilisation overcoming the resistance of traditional cultures with their peculiar superstitions, irrational prejudices and outmoded institutions, for the Romantics the steamroller of progress and modernity was precisely what they feared. Enlightenment philosophes tended to see civilisation in the singular. Romantics understood culture in the plural. Distinct cultures were not aberrant forms to be destroyed but a precious inheritance to be cherished and protected. The philosopher who perhaps best articulated the Romantic notion of culture was Johann Gottfried Herder. Herder rejected the Enlightenment idea that reality was ordered in terms of universal, timeless, objective, unalterable laws that rational investigation could discover. He maintained, rather, that every activity, situation, historical period or civilisation possessed a unique character of its own. What made each people or nation – or volk - unique was its Kultur: its particular language, literature, history and modes of living. The unique nature of each volk was expressed through its volksgeist – the unchanging spirit of a people refined through history. Every culture was authentic in its own terms, each adapted to its local environment. 3 Kenan Malik / University of Surrey/ ‘The trouble with multiculturalism’ Herder occupies an ambiguous role in modern political thought. In the eighteenth century, Herder saw himself as part of the Enlightenment tradition, but also as someone forced to challenge some of the basic precepts of the philosophes – such as their stress on universal law and on the universal validity of reason – in order to defend the cherished ideals of equality. In the nineteenth century, Herder’s concept of the volksgeist encouraged, albeit unwittingly, the development of racial science. Volksgeist became transformed into racial make-up, an unchanging substance, the foundation of all physical appearance and mental potential and the basis for division and difference within humankind. By the late nineteenth century, Herder’s cultural pluralism came, paradoxically, also to give succour to the new anthropological notion of culture championed by critics of racial science. Franz Boas, the German American who played a key role in the development of cultural anthropology, sought, in the words of historian George Stocking, to define the Romantic notion of ‘the genius of the people’ in terms other than those of racial heredity. His answer ultimately was the anthropological notion of culture. And in the twentieth century, Herder’s relativism and particularism came to shape much of antiracist thinking. The roots of barbarism, many came to believe, lay in Western arrogance and the roots of Western arrogance lay in an unquestioning belief in the superiority of Enlightenment rationalism and universalism. 4 Kenan Malik / University of Surrey/ ‘The trouble with multiculturalism’ The second theme in Romantic thinking important to modern multiculturalism is the idea of identity. ‘There is a certain way of being human that is my way’, wrote Charles Taylor in his essay on ‘The Politics of Recognition’. ‘I am called upon to live my life in this way… Being true to myself means being true to my own originality’. This sense of being ‘true to myself’ Taylor calls ‘the ideal of “authenticity”’. The ideal of the authentic self finds its origins in the Romantic notion of the ‘inner voice’ that spoke uniquely to every individual, guided their moral actions and expressed a person’s true nature. The concept was developed in the 1950s by psychologists such as Erik Erikson and sociologists like Alvin Gouldner who pointed out that identity is not just a private matter but emerges in dialogue with others. The inner self, in other words, finds its home in the outer world by participating in a collective. But not just any collective. The world is comprised of countless groups – philosophers, truck drivers, football supporters, drinkers, train spotters, conservatives, communists and so on. But in contemporary debates about identity, each person’s sense of who they truly are is seen as intimately linked to only a few special categories – collectives defined by people’s gender, sexuality, religion, race and, in particular, culture. 5 Kenan Malik / University of Surrey/ ‘The trouble with multiculturalism’ These comprise, of course, very different kinds of groups and the members of each are bound together by very different characteristics. Nevertheless, what collectives such as gender, sexuality, religion, race and culture all have in common is that each is defined by a set of attributes that, whether rooted in biology, faith or history, is fixed in a certain sense and compels people to act in particular ways. Identity is not something the self creates but something through which the self is created. Identity is that which is given, whether by nature, God or one’s ancestors. ‘I am called upon to live my life in this way’, as Charles Taylor has put it. Unlike, say, politically defined collectives, these collectives are, in philosopher John Gray’s words, ‘ascriptive, not elective… a matter of fate, not choice.’ The collectives that are important to the contemporary notion of identity are, in other words, the modern equivalents of what Herder defined as volks. For individual identity to be authentic, so too must collective identity. ‘Just like individuals’, Charles Taylor writes, ‘a Volk should be true to itself, that is, its own culture.’ This view of culture and identity has transformed the way that many people understand the relationship between equality and difference. For much of the past two centuries important strands of both liberal and radical thought drew upon Enlightenment insights to view equality as requiring the state to treat all citizens in the same fashion without regard to their race, religion or culture. 6 Kenan Malik / University of Surrey/ ‘The trouble with multiculturalism’ Most contemporary multiculturalists, on the other hand, argue that people should be treated not equally despite their differences, but differently because of them. ‘Justice between groups’, as the political philosopher Will Kymlicka has put it, ‘requires that members of different groups are accorded different rights’. An individual’s cultural background frames their identity and helps define who they are. If we want to treat individuals with dignity and respect we must also treat with dignity and respect the groups that furnish them with their sense of personal being. ‘The liberal is in theory committed to equal respect for persons’, Bhikhu Parekh argues. ‘Since human beings are culturally embedded, respect for them entails respect for their cultures and ways of life.’ Tariq Madood takes this line of argument to make a distinction between what he calls the ‘equality of individualism’ and ‘equality encompassing public ethnicity: equality as not having to hide or apologise for one’s origins, family or community, but requiring others to show respect for them, and adapt public attitudes and arrangements so that the heritage they represent is encouraged rather than contemptuously expect them to wither away.’ We cannot, in other words, treat individuals equally unless groups also treated equally. And since, in the words of Iris Young, ‘groups cannot be socially equal unless their specific, experience, culture and social contributions are publicly affirmed and recognised’, so society must protect and nurture cultures, ensure their flourishing and indeed their survival. 7 Kenan Malik / University of Surrey/ ‘The trouble with multiculturalism’ Some go further, requiring the state to ensure the survival of cultures not just in the present but in perpetuity. Charles Taylor, for instance, suggests that the Canadian and Quebec governments should take steps to ensure the survival of the French language in Quebec ‘through indefinite future generations’. Most multiculturalists – and certainly the likes of Will Kymlicka and Charles Taylor – would probably consider themselves as standing in the liberal Enlightenment tradition. But the rootedness of their argument in the Romantic counter-Enlightenment often gives a distinctly illiberal sheen to the policies they advocate. Take Tariq Modood’s demand that people be required to give respect to various cultures and that public arrangements be adapted to accommodate them. Does this mean that schools should be forced to teach Creationism because it is part of Christian fundamentalist culture? Or should public arrangements be adapted to reflect the belief of many cultures that homosexuality is a sin? These are not simply abstract questions. In 2002, in Australia’s Northern Territory, Jackie Pascoe Jamilmira, a 50 year-old Aboriginal man was given a 24-hour prison sentence for assaulting and raping a 15-year-old girl. He had apparently been plying the girl's family with gifts since her birth so that she would become his wife upon coming of age. According to the judge because the girl was an Aborigine, she ‘didn't need protection. She knew what was expected of her. It’s very surprising to me he was charged at all.’ 8 Kenan Malik / University of Surrey/ ‘The trouble with multiculturalism’ In California, a young Laotian-American woman was abducted from her work at Fresno State University and raped. Her assailant, a Hmong immigrant (one of the boat people who had fled Cambodia and Laos in the final stages of the Vietnam war) explained to the court that this was a customary way of choosing a bride among his tribe. The court agreed that he had to be judged largely by his own cultural standards and sentenced him to just 120 days in jail. Most multiculturalists would argue that such cases have little to do with real multicultural policies. Yet it is not difficult to see how the demand that everyone’s heritage should be respected and that public arrangements be adapted to preserve each distinct heritage would inevitably create situations such as these. In Australia, courts increasingly accept that Aborigines should have the right to be treated according to their own customs rather than be judged by ‘whitefella law’. According to Colin McDonald, a Darwin barrister and expert in customary law ‘Human rights are essentially a creation of the last hundred years. These people have been carrying out their law for thousands of years.’ This is a central theme to many kinds of multicultural policies - that to preserve cultural authenticity, we must respect the right of certain people to do X because their ancestors also did X. Or, in Charles Taylor’s version, that my descendants, through ‘indefinite future generations’, must do Y because I am doing Y. The demand that because a cultural practice has existed for a long time, so it should be preserved, is a modern version of the naturalistic fallacy - the belief that ought derives from is. 9 Kenan Malik / University of Surrey/ ‘The trouble with multiculturalism’ For nineteenth century social Darwinists, morality - how we ought to behave - derived from the facts of nature - how humans are. This became an argument to justify capitalist exploitation, colonial oppression, racial savagery and even genocide. Today, virtually everyone recognises the falsity of this argument. Yet, when talking of culture rather than of nature, many multiculturalists continue to insist that ‘is’ defines ‘ought’. In any case, there is something deeply inauthentic about the demand for authenticity. The kinds of cultures that most multiculturalists wish to recognise, affirm and preserve are largely ‘traditional’ cultures, particularly those that they believe to be under threat from the steamroller of modernity and globalisation. They are however different in a significant respect from truly traditional cultures that existed in the premodern world. There was, in the premodern world, no sense of cultural integrity or authenticity. There were no alternatives to the ways of life that people followed. Cultures were traditional but in an unselfconscious fashion. Those who lived in such cultures were not aware that they should value their difference or claim it as a right. In the absence of some compelling reason for doing things differently, people went on doing them in the same way as they had in the past. Cultural inertia, in other words, preserved traditional ways because it was the easiest way to organise collective life. Contemporary multiculturalism, on the other hand, exhibits a selfconscious desire to preserve cultures. Such ‘self-conscious traditionalism’ is a peculiarly modern, post-Enlightenment, phenomenon. 10 Kenan Malik / University of Surrey/ ‘The trouble with multiculturalism’ In the modern view, traditions are to be preserved not for pragmatic reasons but because such preservation is a social, political and moral good. Maintaining the integrity of a culture binds societies together, lessens social dislocation and allows the individuals who belong to that culture to flourish. Such individuals can thrive only if they stay true to their culture - in other words, only if both the individual and the culture remain authentic. Modern multiculturalism seeks self-consciously to yoke people to their identity for their own good, the good of that culture and the good of society. A clear example is the attempt by the Quebecois authorities to protect French culture. The Quebec government has legislated to forbid French speakers and immigrants from sending their children to English-language schools; to compel businesses with more than fifty employees to be run in French; and to ban English commercial signs. So, if your ancestors were French you, too, must by government fiat speak French whatever your personal wishes may be. Charles Taylor regards this as acceptable because the flourishing and survival of French culture is a good. ‘It is not just a matter of having the French language available for those who might choose it’, he argues. Quebec is ‘making sure that there is a community of people here in the future that will want to avail itself of the opportunity to use the French language.’ Its policies ‘actively seek to create members of the community… assuring that future generations continue to identify as French-speakers.’ 11 Kenan Malik / University of Surrey/ ‘The trouble with multiculturalism’ An identity here has become a bit like a private club. Once you join up, you have to abide by the rules. But unlike the Groucho or the Garrick it’s a private club you must join. An identity is supposed to be an expression of an individual’s authentic self. But it can too often seem like the denial of individual agency in the name of cultural authenticity. Take for instance the argument put forward by the sociologist Joseph Raz argues, in common with many multiculturalists, that ‘It is in the interest of every person to be fully integrated in a cultural group’. But what is to be fully integrated? If a Muslim woman rejects sharia law, is she demonstrating her lack of integration? What about a Jew who doesn’t believe in the legitimacy of the Jewish State? Or a French Quebecois who speaks only English? Would Galilleo have challenged the authority of the Church if he had been ‘fully integrated’ into his culture? Or Thomas Paine have supported the French Revolution? Or Salman Rushdie written The Satanic Verses? Cultures only change, societies only move forward because many people, in Kwame Appiah’s words, ‘actively resist being fully integrated into a group’. For them ‘integration can sound like regulation, even restraint’. Far from giving voice to the voiceless, in other words, the so-called politics of difference appears to undermine individual autonomy, reduce liberty and enforce conformity. Part of the problem here is a constant slippage in multiculturalism talk between the idea of humans as culture-bearing creatures and the idea that humans have to bear a particular culture. Clearly no human can live outside of culture. But then no human does. 12 Kenan Malik / University of Surrey/ ‘The trouble with multiculturalism’ To say that no human can live outside of culture, however, is not to say they have to live inside a particular one. To view humans as culture-bearing is to view them as social beings, and hence as transformative beings. It suggests that humans have the capacity for change, for progress, and for the creation of universal moral and political forms through reason and dialogue. To view humans as having to bear specific cultures is, on the contrary, to deny such a capacity for transformation. It suggests that every human being is so shaped by a particular culture that to change or undermine that culture would be to undermine the very dignity of that individual. It suggests that the biological fact of, say, Jewish or Bangladeshi ancestry somehow make a human being incapable of living well except as a participant of Jewish or Bangladeshi culture. This would only make sense if Jews or Bangladeshis were biologically distinct – in other words if cultural identity was really about racial difference. The relationship between cultural identity and racial difference becomes even clearer if we look at the argument that cultures must be protected and preserved. Will Kymlicka argues that since cultures are essential to peoples’ lives, so where ‘the survival of a culture is not guaranteed, and, where it is threatened with debasement or decay, we must act to protect it.’ For Charles Taylor, once ‘we’re concerned with identity, nothing ‘is more legitimate than one’s aspiration that it is never lost’. Hence a culture needs to be protected not just in the here and now but through ‘indefinite future generations’. 13 Kenan Malik / University of Surrey/ ‘The trouble with multiculturalism’ But what does it mean for a culture to decay? Or for an identity to be lost? Will Kymlicka draws a distinction between the ‘existence of a culture’ and ‘its “character” at any given moment’. The character of culture can change but such changes are only acceptable if the existence of that culture is not threatened. But how can a culture exist if that existence is not embodied in its character? By ‘character’ Kymlicka seems to mean the actuality of a culture: what people do, how they live their lives, the rules and regulations and institutions that frame their existence. So, in making the distinction between character and existence, Kymlicka seems to be suggesting that Jewish, Navajo or French culture is not defined by what Jewish, Navajo or French people are actually doing. For if Jewish culture is simply that which Jewish people do or French culture is simply that which French people do, then cultures could never decay or perish – they would always exist in the activities of people. So, if a culture is not defined by what its members are doing, what does define it? The only answer can be that it is defined by what its members should be doing. And what you should be doing, for cultural preservationists, is what your ancestors were doing it. Culture here has become defined by biological descent. And biological descent is a polite way of saying ‘race’. As the American writer Walter Benn Michaels puts it, ‘In order for a culture to be lost… it must be separable from one’s actual behaviour, and in order for it to be separable from one’s actual behaviour it must be anchorable in race.’ 14 Kenan Malik / University of Surrey/ ‘The trouble with multiculturalism’ For all the talk about culture as fluid and changing, multiculturalism invariably leads people to think of human cultures in fixed terms. Indeed, it is difficult to imagine how multicultural policy could conceive of cultures in any other way. How could rights be accorded to cultures, or cultures be recognised or preserved if they did not possess rigid boundaries? Once membership of cultural types is defined by the possession of certain characteristics, and rights and privileges granted by virtue of possessing those characteristics, then it is but a short step to deny membership of a culture to people who do not possess those characteristics and hence to deny them certain rights and privileges. The language of diversity all too easily slips into the idiom of exclusion. Will Kymlicka suggests that ‘It is right and proper that the character of a culture changes as a result of the choices of its members.’ But, he goes on, ‘while it is one thing to learn from the larger world’, it is quite another ‘to be swamped by it’. What could this mean? That a culture has the right to keep out members of another culture? That a culture has the right to prevent its members from speaking another language, singing non-native songs or reading non-native books? Kymlicka’s warning about ‘swamping’ should make us sit up and take notice. It is, after all, the right that has long exploited fears of cultural swamping. Will Kymlicka is a liberal anti-racist and certainly no xenophobe. But once it becomes a matter of political principle that cultures should not be swamped by outsiders, then it is difficult to know how one could possibly resist such anti-immigration arguments. 15 Kenan Malik / University of Surrey/ ‘The trouble with multiculturalism’ Herder, the French philosopher Alain Finkielkraut observes, has become the cheerleader for both sides of the political spectrum. ‘No longer silenced by post-World War II taboos’, Finkielkraut has written, ‘he reigns supreme inspiring at the same time… unyielding celebrations of ethnic identity and expressions of respect for foreigners, aggressive outbursts by xenophobes and generous pronouncements by xenophiles.’ The two sides have ‘conflicting credos but the same vision of the world’. The irony in all this is that we’ve all become multiculturalists at the very time the world is becoming less, not more, plural. ‘When I was a child’, the Ghanaian born Kwame Appiah recalls, ‘we lived in a household where you could hear at least three mother tongues spoken each day. Ghana, with a population close to that of New York State, has several dozen languages in active use and no one language that is spoken at home – or even fluently understood – by a majority of the population.’ So why is it, he asks, that in America ‘which seems so much less diverse than most other societies we are so preoccupied with diversity and inclined to conceive of it as cultural?’ The proportion of foreign born Americans is far less than it was at the beginning of the twentieth century. Intermarriage between immigrant groups continues to increase. More than 97 per cent of Americans speak English. At the beginning of the twentieth century. Then, new immigrants did not simply speak their own language, but read their own newspapers, ate their own food and lived their own lives. In 1923, for instance, the Polish community alone published 67 weekly newspapers, 18 monthlies and 19 dailies, the largest of which had a circulation of more than a hundred thousand. 16 Kenan Malik / University of Surrey/ ‘The trouble with multiculturalism’ Today, not just language, but the shopping mall, the sports field, the Hollywood film and the TV sitcom all serve to bind differences and create a set of experiences and cultural practices that is more common than at any time in the past. Indeed, even before today’s immigrants set foot on US soil they are probably more American than previous generations of Americans. Much the same is true of Europe. Take the current debate about the impact of mass migration, and in particular of Muslims, on social cohesion and national identity. Both sides in this debate make a link between the diversity of peoples and the diversity of values. Multiculturalists believe that the presence in a society of diversity of peoples precludes the possibility of common values. Nativists want to limit immigration because, they suggest, such values are possible only within an ethnically homogenous society. And both sides suffer from a collective memory loss. The claim that European nations used to be homogenous but have become diverse does not stand up. Historian such as Eugene Weber in France and Eric Hobsbawm and Terence Ranger in Britain have shown the extraordinary modernising effort that was required in the nineteenth century to unify what we now think of as homogenous European nations and the traumatic and lengthy process of cultural, educational, political and economic ‘self-colonisation’ that this entailed. 17 Kenan Malik / University of Surrey/ ‘The trouble with multiculturalism’ These developments created the modern French nation and allowed for notions of European superiority over non-European cultures. But it also reinforced a sense of how socially and anthropologically alien was the mass of the rural, and indeed urban, population. A vignette of working class life in the Saturday Review, a well-read liberal magazine of the era, is typical of English middle class attitudes of this era: The Bethnal Green poor… are a caste apart, a race of whom we know nothing, whose lives are of quite different complexion from ours, persons with whom we have no point of contact. And although there is not yet quite the same separation of classes or castes in the country, yet the great mass of the agricultural poor are divided from the educated and the comfortable, from squires and parsons and tradesmen, by a barrier which custom has forged through long centuries, and which only very exceptional circumstances ever beat down, and then only for an instant. The slaves are separated from the whites by more glaring… marks of distinction; but still distinctions and separations, like those of English classes which always endure, which last from the cradle to the grave, which prevent anything like association or companionship, produce a general effect on the life of the extreme poor, and subject them to isolation, which offer a very fair parallel to the separation of the slaves from the whites. Of course the descendants of the Bethnal Green poor that the Victorian middle class viewed as a ‘race apart’ are now seen as part of indigenous British (or perhaps English) culture while a new generation of Bethnal Green poor, who only arrived there after the Second World War, are now regarded as not just a race apart but a culture apart too. 18 Kenan Malik / University of Surrey/ ‘The trouble with multiculturalism’ Yet, the social and cultural differences between a Victorian gentleman and a farmhand or a machinist were probably greater than those between a native white Briton and a second generation British Asian or Afro-Caribbean today. Indeed a 60-something white Briton would probably find a 20-something white Briton more culturally alien than either would an Asian or an Afro-Caribbean of their own generation. So, why is it that on both sides of the Atlantic we’ve become obsessed by cultural differences at the very time that real cultural differences have less and less meaning in our lives? Much of the answer lies, I believe, in the narrowing of the political sphere. The end of the Cold War, the collapse of the left, the fragmentation of the postwar order, the defeat of most liberation movements in the third world and the demise of social movements in the West, have all transformed political consciousness over the past two decades. The broad ideological divides that characterised politics in the previous two hundred years have been all but erased. Politics has became less about competing visions of the kinds of society people than a debate about how best to manage the existing political system. As the meaning of politics has narrowed, so people have begun to view themselves and their social affiliations in a different way. Social solidarity has become increasingly defined not in political terms - as collective action in pursuit of certain political ideals – but in terms of ethnicity or culture. The question people ask themselves are not so much ‘What kind of society do I want to live in?’ as ‘Who are we?’. 19 Kenan Malik / University of Surrey/ ‘The trouble with multiculturalism’ The first question looks forward for answers and defines them in terms of the commonality of values necessary for establishing the good life. The second generally looks back and seeks answers – and defines identity – in terms of history and heritage. The politics of ideology has given way to the politics of identity. And part of the reason it has done so is that public policy has helped narrow people’s sense of self-identity. One of the enduring myths of multiculturalism is that Britain has become a multicultural nation because minority groups have demanded that their cultural differences be recognised and be afforded respect. In fact, while the question of cultural differences has preoccupied the political elite from the beginnings of mass immigration, it was not a question that particularly troubled black and Asian Britons for a considerable period. First and second generation postwar immigrants were concerned less about preserving cultural differences than about fighting for political equality. Throughout the sixties and seventies, four big issues dominated the struggle for political equality: opposition to discriminatory immigration controls; the struggle for equality in the workplace; the fight against racist attacks; and, most explosively, the issue of police brutality. These struggles politicised a new generation of activists and came to an explosive climax in the inner city riots of the late seventies and early eighties. 20 Kenan Malik / University of Surrey/ ‘The trouble with multiculturalism’ It was against this background that the policies of multiculturalism became institutionalised through a strategy, pioneered by the GLC, of organising consultation with black communities, drawing up equal opportunities policies, establishing race relations units and providing funding for black community organisations. At the heart of the strategy was a redefinition of racism. Racism now meant not simply the denial of equal rights but the denial of the right to be different. Different peoples should have the right to express their specific identities, explore their own histories, formulate their own values, pursue their own lifestyles. In this process, the very meaning of equality was transformed: from possessing the same rights as everyone else to possessing different rights, appropriate to different communities. By the mid-eighties the political struggles that had dominated the fight against racism in the sixties and seventies had became transformed into battles over cultural issues. Political struggles unite across ethnic or cultural divisions; cultural struggles inevitably fragment. Since state funding was now linked to cultural identity, so different groups began asserting their particular identities ever more fiercely. The shift from the political to the cultural arena helped entrench old divisions and to create new ones. Take Bradford. In April 1976, 24 people were arrested in pitched battles in the Manningham area of Bradford, as Asian youth confronted a National Front march and fought police protecting it. It was seen as the blooding of a new movement. The following year the Asian Youth Movement was born. 21 Kenan Malik / University of Surrey/ ‘The trouble with multiculturalism’ AYM activists did not distinguish themselves as Muslim, Hindu or Sikh; indeed many did not even see themselves as specifically Asian, preferring to call themselves ‘black’. They challenged not just racism but also many traditional values too, particularly within the Muslim community, helping establish an alternative secular leadership. Faced with this growing militancy- and particularly in response to the trial and victory of the Bradford 12 - Bradford council drew up GLCstyle equal opportunity statements, established race relations units and began funding black organisations. A 12-point race relations plan declared that every section of the ‘multiracial, multicultural city’ had ‘an equal right to maintain its own identity, culture, language, religion and customs.’ By the mid-eighties the focus of anti-racist protest in Bradford had shifted from political issues, such as policing and immigration, to religious and cultural issues: a demand for Muslim schools and for separate education for girls, a campaign for halal meat to be served at school, and, most explosively, the confrontation over the publication of The Satanic Verses. This process was strengthened by a new relationship between the local council and the local mosques. In 1981, the council helped set up and fund the Bradford Council of Mosques. By siphoning resources through the mosques, the council was able to strengthen the position of conservative religious leaders and to dampen down the more militant voices on the streets. 22 Kenan Malik / University of Surrey/ ‘The trouble with multiculturalism’ As part of its multicultural brief to allow different communities to express their distinct identities, the council also helped set up two other religious umbrella groups for Sikhs and Hindus, both created in 1984. The consequence was to create divisions and tensions within and between different Asian communities as each fought for a greater allocation of council funding. Asian communities started dividing, both physically and politically, on communal lines. Muslims, Sikhs and Hindus, began increasingly to live in different areas, attend different schools and organise through different institutions. A similar process has taken place in Birmingham. In 1988, largely in response to the 1985 Handsworth riots, Birmingham council proposed the development of a new framework for the engagement of minority communities. It created a series of Umbrella Groups based on ethnicity and faith the function of which was to represent the needs of their communities. By 1993 there were nine of these – the African and Caribbean People’s Movement, the Bangladeshi Islamic Projects Consultative Committee, the Birmingham Chinese Society, The Council of Black-led Churches, the Hindu Council, the Irish Forum, the Vietnamese Association, the Pakistani Forum and the Sikh Council of Gurdwaras. A Standing Consultative Forum was established as a single body through which the Umbrella Groups could collectively represent the views of minority communities and to aid policy development and resource allocation. The impact was anything but democratic. First, as in Bradford, the policy treated minority communities as homogenous wholes, ignoring conflicts within those communities. As a Birmingham Council Equalities Division Report in 1999 put it, 23 Kenan Malik / University of Surrey/ ‘The trouble with multiculturalism’ The perceived notion of homogeneity of minority ethnic communities has informed a great deal of race equality work to date. The effect of this, amongst others, has been to place an over-reliance on individuals who are seen to represent the needs of views of the whole community and resulted in simplistic approaches toward tackling community needs. At the same time as ignoring conflicts within minority communities, Birmingham’s policies created conflicts between them. As a study by Southampton University’s Smith and Stephenson concludes, Birmingham’s ‘model of engagement through Umbrella Groups tended to result in competition between BME communities for resources. Rather than prioritising needs and cross-community working, the different Umbrella Groups generally attempted to maximise their own interests’. Once political power and financial resources became allocated by ethnicity, then people began to identify themselves in terms of those ethnicities. Once again multicultural prescription made real the description to which it was supposedly a response. The practical consequences can be seen in last year’s Lozell’s riots which pitted African Caribbeans and Asians against each other. The experience of Bradford and Birmingham has been repeated in countless other places. And what that experience suggests is that multiculturalism creates its own myths and its own monsters. 24 Kenan Malik / University of Surrey/ ‘The trouble with multiculturalism’ The problem with multicultural policies is not that they stress diversity. It is that they possess too rigid a notion of what diversity entails and why it is useful. The consequence is to create the kinds of conflict that are politically neither useful nor resolvable. The irony of multiculturalism is that, as a political process, it undermines what is valuable about cultural diversity. Diversity is important, not in and of itself, but because it allows us to expand our horizons, to compare and contrast different values, beliefs and lifestyles, and make judgements upon them. In other words, because it allows us to engage in political dialogue and debate that can help create more universal values and beliefs, and a collective language of citizenship. The narrowing of the political sphere makes such a process much more difficult to pursue. As a result diversity has come to be seen as a good in itself. That is why multiculturalism should not be seen as a response to a diverse society. Rather, the pursuit of multicultural policies has led us to imagine that we are far more diverse than we are. 25