From Historicism, The Idea of Progress to Postmodern Revisionist History Almost two centuries before Postmodern leftists gained control over the great chair of the humanities, especially history, the seeds were being laid for historicism. Theories of historicism have agreed in emphasizing the uniqueness of historical events. A distinct contrast is Karl Popper's definition of historicism in his book, The Poverty of Historicism. (Boston, 1959), p. 3. "It will be enough if I say here that I mean by 'historicism' an approach to the social sciences which assumes that historical prediction is their aim and which assumes that this aim is attainable by discovering the 'rhythms' or "patterns' of the laws or trends' that underlie the evolution of history." (see the sharp criticism of Popper by Hans Meyerhoff in The Philosophy of History in Our Times (NY, 1956), p. 29. For an excellent attempt to define "Historicism" and its many conflicting meanings, see Dwight E. Lee and Robert N. Beck, "The Meaning of Historicism", American Historical Review, LIX (1953-1954): 568-577. Historicism itself developed in late 18th century Germany. The Enlightenment that flourished in France and Britain came late to Germany. Its impact became visible after mid 19th century (see my paper and syllabus, "The Enlightenment"). The philosophies of the German Enlightenment, the Aufklarer, were not swept away in the waves of enthusiasms for 'enlightened' ways. The achievements of the French philosopher did not soon impact German thought. The key to the distinctive German Enlightenment is its high regard for tradition. French tradition was treated with contempt in Germany. German Aufklarer were dismayed by the scorn for revealed religion evident in the writing of Voltaire and his contemporaries. They found that French and Scottish philosophical history paid too little attention to the details of the past (see especially G. P. Gooch, History and Historians in the Nineteenth Century (London, 1952), p. 9; and Isaiah Berlin, Vico and Herder: Two Studies in The History of Ideas (London, 1976); perhaps the greatest precursor of historicism was an early 18th century Florentine professor of rhetoric, Giambattista Vico); P. H. Reill, The German Enlightenment and The Rise of Historicism (Berkeley, CA, 1975). The religious contribution came briefly from pietism. Pietism laid much stress on personal religion that verged on mysticism. Pietism contrasted reason with spiritual illumination. Wisdom (Sophia) and Reason had access only to logical distinction. Sophia is the power of God. A twin influence produced historicism-pietism and antiquarianism (tradition). The Germans, Gatterer once remarked, were people exactly suited to the products of learned footnotes (Herbert Butterfield. Man and His Past: A Study of History of Historical Scholarship (Cambridge. 1955), p. 38). German concern for historiography becomes visible in the number of historical periodicals which rose from 3 in 1700 to 131 in 1790 (Butterfield, p. 39). Two further contributors to the rise of historicism were Idealism and Romanticism. Germany's great protagonist of philosophical idealism was Immanuel Kant. Both Idealism and Romanticism were reaction against the Enlightenment. Kant rejected the view that knowledge is passively assimilated by the human mind. This was to turn against the sensationalism of David Hume (Butterfield, p. US). The mind is active in the acquisition of knowledge. Ideas (categories) are essential for understanding the world. Therefore, it is Idealism. This is a radical break with Enlightenment Empiricism! Idealism became the strongest concept in German philosophy after the publication of Kant's mature views in 1780. Hegel's philosophy can best be understood as a response to that of Kant. Kant's constructivism opens Pandora's Box of relativistic radical contextualization and ultimately postmodern Revisionism in science, history, etc. Idealism was the characteristic intellectual expression at the turn of the 19th century while Romanticism was the characteristic cultural expression of the epoch. Romanticism was a reaction against 18th century norms. Nature had been conceived as an intricate structure of cause and effect passively awaiting dissection by human reason. Now nature was seen as an organic whole that actively influences human beings. For Wordsworth nature was the "muse, the guide, the guardian of my heart and soul of all my moral being." (Wordsworth from Tintern Abbev. Lyrical Ballads. 1798, lines 1 l0ff, ed. R L. Brett and A.R. Jones (London, 1963), p. 116.) Nature fulfilled the role of God. Its stress on the role of ideas was widely diffused and became axiomatic in historicist thought. History is concerned with ideas. It is not about pure ideas, but about a really whole development that is subject to ideas (Idealism). This view of nature was propounded by Wilhelm von Humboldt, the architect of the Prussian education system, in a lecture "On The Historian's Talk" delivered before the Prussian Academy of Sciences in 1821. The trend of ideas he explained constitutes historical truth. The history of ideas (Geitesgeschichte) became deeply entranced in German historical tradition. Philosophical idealism had a marked impact on the theory and practice of history. The divine was thought to be everything, or to be more precise, in everything. Romantics like Wordsworth and Coleridge in England discerned the divine in the natural world of crags and seascapes, flowers and storms. Their poetry was meant to distill the mystical spiritual experience of those who lived in awareness of the "Wisdom and Spirit of the Universe" (M. H. Abrams, Natural Supernaturalism: Tradition and Revolutions in Romantic Literature (London 1971), p. 68). Romanticism was charged with a sense of the divine abroad in the world. Historicism was a factor within the romantic tide that swept Germany. Goethe, the greatest of German romantics, is quite reasonably treated in the best known German study of the subject as the climax of the rise of historicism (Friedrich Meinecke, Historicism: Use of A New Historical Outlook (1932), translated by I.E. Anderson (London, 1973), pp. 373-495). Goethe shared romantic values—the feeling that the world is impregnated with the divine. Therefore man shares nature with God and history. Ranke illustrates this well in an essay that he wrote "On the Character of Historical Science". "It is not necessary for us to prove at length that the eternal dwells in the individual. This is the religious foundation on which our efforts rest. We believe that there is nothing without God and nothing lives except through God." (Ranke, Theory and Practice, p. 38). All forms of historicism affirm that God works in all "histories" not merely the special history of Israel and Christianity. The pluralism of religious customs give evidence of the manifold wisdom of God. The Germans, French and English all produced learned treatise based in the developments of the aufklarer. These tomes fused hard and fast rational categories and rhetoric to good effect. As historians began to write—on aufklarer principles, they integrated the research method of philosophy with generalizing method of philosophy—as Vico had done in Italy and Gibbon did in England (see especially The New Science of Giambattista Fico. ed. Max H. Fisch and Thomas G. Bergin (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1948); A.D. Monigliano, "Gibbon's contribution to Historical Method" Studies in Historiography (London, 1966). The Gottingen quest for detail emphasized the need to ensure the accuracy of what was written as history. The Gottingen School sought to represent the widespread desire for accuracy that began in the later Middle Ages. Critical standards were employed primarily in philology and 2 genealogy, to the editing of texts. The 18th century German Enlightenment did not produce any monument of historical scholarship equivalent to Gibbon's Decline and Fall of The Roman Empire or Niebuhr's History of Rome. The history of ideas, Geistesgeschichte, became deeply entrenched in German historical tradition. Philosophical ideals had a marked impact on the theory and practice of history. All the Aiifklarer were responsible for developing another feature of romantic thought, a stress on organic development. Like Vico, they were eager to reject a mechanistic worldview. Wolfian atomistic reductionism was on the wane. According to the Aufklarer every event is related to another. Nature was interconnected to every event in history. Herder's rambling work Reflections on The Philosophy of The History of Mankind (1784-1791) fully expressed the spirit of German Romanticism. Herder's pluralism thesis is his chief contribution. This thesis finds ubiquitous voices in postmodern revisionism. All cultures have their own values that cannot justly be compared with the values of other cultures (see especially Berlin, Vico and Herder, p. 153). This cultural relativism thesis is the diametric opposite of the "inevitably of progress" thesis. Progress can only occur within a given nation and cannot be measured on any single or external scale. Each notion contains the "ideal of its own perfection, wholly independent of all comparison with those of others." (p. 206). This is precisely the postmodern revisionist thesis!! The seeds of historicism during the Napoleonic Wars were scattered and historians turned from repairing the materials of history to historiography proper. Perhaps the singly most influential work of the period was the History of Rome (1811) by Reinhold Niebuhr, who blended the fragmentary sources for early Roman history—law codes, inscriptions, poetry, ballad, literature, i.e. Livy’s influence, into a coherent story of a perennial struggle for power between patricians and plebeians. Niebuhr's work was a tour de force, replacing the classical accounts of brief phases of republican history. Niebuhr utilized the standard historicist thesis that poetry and myth express the inner spirit of a nation. He also assumed (following Vico) that all nations go through similar cycles of development. This development finds postmodern fruition in revisionist history. Through Niebuhr the idea of historicism spread beyond Germany. In England a group of scholars with an Oxford background, the so-called "Liberal Anglicans," read Niebuhr avidly. Of this group the best known is Thomas Arnold, Headmaster of Rugby and subsequently Regius Professor of Modern History at Oxford. Niebuhr molded all his thought (Thomas Arnold, Introductory Lectures on Modern History (London, 1845). His inaugural lecture at Oxford is a manifesto of historicist views. Modern history, he argued, is the study of national personality, which is a product of race, language, institutions and religion and persists down the ages (T. Arnold, ibid., p. 25). (See especially Duncan Forbes, The Liberal Anglican Idea of History (Cambridge, 1952) and P.W. Day, Thomas Arnold and The Philosophy of Vico (Aukland, New Zealand, 1964), p. 55). The chief influence of historicism in Britain was not a historian but a novelist, Sir Walter Scott. It was Scott who fired the imagination of Macaulay. The Romantic in British historiography was to be found in its literary expression rather than its intellectual assumption (on Macaulay see Sir Earnest Barker, Age and Youth, pp. 25Iff). Niebuhr influenced Leopold von Ranke. Ranke is surely the example of value-free objectivity. His dictum that the historian must concern himself only with "what actually happened" has become the most common of commonplaces on historical thought. This is actually a distortion of Ranke's view as his phrase "wie es eigentlick gewesen" contains an adverb "eigentlick", which certainly means "actually" in 20th century German usage. In Ranke's own 19th century usage it usually meant 3 "essentially," -"what essentially happened." (Ranke, Theory and Practice, p. xix; editor G. Iggers, Bobbs-Merrill: Indianapolis, 1973) Instead of objectivity, Ranke was expressing the classical historicist belief that institutions enable the historian to divine the essence of the past (note that we are on the way to Marx's "the entire so-called history of the world is nothing but economic and philosophical manuscripts of 1844." The phrase "the materialist conception of history" was first used by Engels in 1859 (Z.A. Jordon, The Evolution of Dialectical Materialism: A Philosophical and Sociological Analysis (London, 1967) p 37n). Ranke's influence was dwindling and a new influence was entering the historical arena, an appreciation of positivist history exemplified by Buckle, yet reaffirmed the central historicist claim that the methods of nature science cannot be applied to history (see especially Igger's German Conception of History: The National Tradition of Historical Thought from Herder to The Present (Middletown, CT: Wesleyan University Press, 1968, revised edition 1983. It contains comprehensive study of historicist mainstream). At the turn of the 20th century, Marx Weber was preoccupied with positivism yet making a distinctive methodological separation between the sciences of man and the physical sciences. The German tradition of historicism was being diluted under Hitler's tyranny in the 1930's. (See esp. Monigliano's "Historicism and Contemporary Thought," Studies in Historiography, p. 227.) In the 1900's many German historians were still defending a method that justified their country's past role in the international arena. Fritz Fisher claimed that Germany must bear the responsibility of the outbreak of World War I (J.A. Moses, The Policies of Illusion: The Fisher Controversy in German Historiography (London. 1975). Wilhelm Dilthey, a Berlin professor who died in 1911, exerted a strong posthumous influence. His lasting contribution was to elaborate the historicist notion of intention. History is to be separated from the physical sciences by different methods. The laws of physics cannot grasp the particular features of any instance of human behavior, charged as it is with intention. Human intention can only be intuited. Dilthey introduced hermeneutics as a bridge between physics and psychology. Dilthey utilized Schleiermacher's principles for interpreting the Bible and recognized that they could be applied to any documents (R.E. Palmer, Hermeneutics and Interpretation Theory in Schleiermacher, Dilthey, Heidegger and Gadamer (Evanston, IL; Northwestern University, 1969), pp. 94ff.). Persons, like historical events, can be studied and understood only by seeing them in relation to one another. At this point we can perceive Dilthey's doctrine of the Hermeneutical circle1: a part must be understood through its setting in the whole; the whole must be understood through recognizing the significance of its parts. Interpretation is therefore a process of allowing part and whole to interact in the mind (H.P. Rickman, ed., W. Dilthey: Selected Writings (Cambridge, 1976), pp. 9ff.). The historicist thesis' influence expands far beyond history. Historicism, fused with Hegelianism, Vico contributed to the greatest intellectual achievement of Italy-the historical philosophy of Benedetto Croce (A.D. Monigliano, "Reconsidering B. Croce 1866-1952”) Essays in Ancient and Modern Historiography B. Croce. History: Its Theory and Practice (editor Douglas Ainslie (NY: Russell and Russell, 1960). In Germany the historicists stress on the corporate personality of the nation formed the foundation of Hitler's "volkisch", Philosophy of life (Michael Oakeshott, The Social and Political Doctrines of Contemporary Europe (Cambridge, 1939), p. 201). 4 Dilthey's idea of intuitive understanding also did much to shape philosophical trends. Dilthey's method was taken up by Martin Heidegger, whose Being and Time (1927) was intended as a preliminary hermeneutic study but became the early classic existentialism. In a chaotic world, according to Heidegger, man must recognize the certainty of death and so steel himself to follow a life of decisive activity. Such ideas were to become popular in the wake of World War II, especially through the writings of Jean Paul Sarte (M.D. Biddiss, The Masses: Ideas and Society in Europe Since 1870 (Hassocks, Sussex, 1977), pp. 249-322f). Human life in the historicisticexistential can be regarded as the redactio adabsurdum of historicism! Human life in existential historicism is not shaped by history, but is reduced to meaninglessness by being part of the flux of events. The only rational thing left for man to do is to accept his place in a world that is absurd and futile. The terminal results of historicism is events of the Counter Culture (Generation X) of the 1960's. Historicism is the result of two centuries of a sustained attempt to grapple with the question of the significance of the historical process. Niebuhr's influence still pervades postmodern revisionism—The Death of History. It also effects revisionism in precipitating the Death of Science, our on-going anti-science debate. (See the article "Science versus Anti-science?" in The Scientific American (January, 1997), pp. 96-101) Yet, the main historicist idea is that human groups are molded by history. To a great extent this is undeniable. But historicism holds that the flux of history eliminates any constancy in man. There is no such thing as human nature, (cf. Gender Bias, Political Correctness, etc. Structure in family, culture, civilization. See my paper "Structuralism in Our Postmodern Revisionism") To deny man-qua-man is to reject the view of men held down for centuries in Western thought and accepted by the philosophers of the Enlightenment. Man has been and remains—in all cultures, languages—the same. Even Hume saw that human beings had similar characteristics whether they lived in ancient Greece or Rome or in modern France or England (G.G. Iggers, New Directions in European Historiography (Middletown, CT, 1975), p. 15, 77ff.). Historicism over reacted against the Enlightenment and its idea of how we obtain knowledge of the past is also questionable. The historian can intuit the mental world of people long dead. Formulating ideas by inference from the evidence of a creative artist. There lies its fundamental weakness. How is an artist to know whether he has created a faithful likeness of the people of the past? Postmodern art denies that is even a possibility. There is no objective criterion for determining how accurately the historian reflects the past. The fundamental problem of historicism is. that is foundationless. The determinate of men’s beliefs, it holds, is in history and history is a constant flux of events with no ordering center. The historical process is only a patchwork of different attitudes in perpetual dialectical tensions with no mediating possibilities, except power, and why power? No one in the historicist mode from Troeltsch forward have proved able to discover an alternative to God's guarantees for judgment of value. (See his book, Historicism and Its Problem (paperback reprint) and Robert Morgan, "Troeltsch and The Dialectical Theology" Ernst Troeltsch and The Future of Theology, ed. J.P. Clayton (Cambridge, 1976), p. 46) Historicism collapsed into historical relativism. There is no ground for preferring one custom to another, one moral code to another, or (even most crucially) to an alternative worldview. Worldviews are in conflict in Postmodern Revisionism, but what 5 does it or can it mean? The whole historicist perspective stands revealed as an arbitrary preference with no objective criterion for selecting alternatives. Another voice for human allegiance in our postmodern cultural wars is Marxist history and Positivistic Historiography. Marxism is a worldview. History is at its heart. The code name for Marxist perspective is historical materialism, a phrase coined by Engels in 1892 as an equivalent for what he had also called "the materialist conception of history" (see Z.A. Jordon, The Evolution of Dialectical Materialism: A Philosophical and Sociological Analysis (London, 1967), p. 37n). This was to reject what Marx dismissed as the idealistic view of history and I believe that ideas are responsible for shaping human destiny. (Marx/Engel, The German Ideology (1845-46), edited by Roy Pascal (London, 1938), p. 28). How men produce their means of subsistence, according to Marxism, is the key to historical change. The heart of the debate centers on blended and codified ideas from Marx, Engels, and Lenin. One pivotal work is his Grundrisse: Foundations of The Critique of Political Erosion (Harmmdsworth, 1973). The context of Marx's views is mid 19th century German historicism fused with the inherent idea of progress. The earlier fusion was the system of George W. F. Hegel, whose all encompassing philosophy was the marvel of Germany in the decade after his death in 1831. Marx's view of history is not understandable without also engaging the whole Hegelian worldview. Hegel's philosophy can best be understood as a response to that of Kant (see Karl Marx, Letters to His Father: Karl Marx: Early Texts, edited by David McLellan (Oxford, 1972), p. 8, l00ff.). In his theory of knowledge, Kant's belief that the mind actively constructs the world of experience led him to conclude that the world of experience differs from the world as it really is, beyond experience. He contrasted the knowable world of phenomena (things as they appear) with the unknowable world noumena (things as they are in themselves). This distinction Hegel emphatically denied. The world that is known as the world phenomena in Kant's sense, Hegel grounded this claim on the belief that the mind is responsible for creating the external world. There can be, according to Hegel, no reality beyond experience. Hegel summed up his view in the dictum, "the real is the rational and the rational is the real." (quoted in G.R.G. Mure's, The Philosophy of Hegel (London 1965), p. 23). He meant that the real world is knowable to the mind; and that the mind is all there is ultimately in the real world. Hegel's stress on the human mind was because he believed that the particular human mind is a manifestation of the eternal mind (Geist) which is the equivalent of God in his thought. Hegel is therefore classified as an absolute idealist. The ideas of the mind are wholly responsible for the eternal world, the medieval family was superceded by the rise of "civil society, which in its commercial individualism, tended to break up the family. The conflict was superceded by the state, which supplied ideal conditions for ethical life by uniting the solidarity of the family with the State. The triadic pattern bears the hallmark of the idea of progress. Marxist freedom is to be understood in the romantic way as self-realization. Yet the idea of progress contributed to the underlying structure of Hegel's understanding of history. The young Hegelians were committed to criticism of Christianity. The young Hegelians used Hegel's categories to assert the truth of atheism (i.e. Marx's 1841 Atheistic Archives). The ultimate outcome of the cultural tension focused more on politics than Christianity. The poor in Prussian lands were not members of groups recognized by the State. These people were threatened by 6 Hegel as a threat to the stability of the State. Hegel's self-fulfilling freedom for all was not a reality." (Heinz Lubrasz, "Marx's Initial Problematic, The Problem of Poverty" Political Studies 24 (1976): pp. 27-34). Marx aimed for democracy--"freedom for all"- yet he generated Communism, where no state survives to neglect or oppress the mass of the people. Marx will soon decry his intellectual independence from Hegel. The heart of Marx's view of history is that man is the maker of his own history. This idea probably derives from his encounter with Ludwig Feuerbach, whose Essence of Christianity (1841) had attempted to show that theology is a mystical form of anthropology. Marx was attracted by Feuerbach's anthropocentricism. Feuerbach never progressed beyond a Lockean view that man is a passive recipient of sense experience. In Marx's third thesis on Feuerbach he declares: "The materialist doctrine of men are products of circumstances and upbringing and that heretofore, changed man are products of other circumstances and changed upbringing, forgets that it is men who change circumstances and that the educator must himself be educated." (Theses on Feuerbach, Marx and Engel, Collected Works 5 (London, 1976) p. 7) The first premise of all human existence and therefore, of all history, is the need to produce food, etc. "The first historical act is this—the production of the means to satisfy these needs, the production of material life itself." (Marx/Engel, "The German Ideology" in Collected Works 5, pp. 41f; W.H. Shaws, Marx's Theory of History (London. 1978). Surely Marx is a fatalistic determinist as both Berlin and Popper claim. Yet Marx declares that the processes of history are determined by no agency other than man. Surely laws in Marx can only mean tendencies. Marx did not deviate from his initial premise that man, not fate or law, is the maker of history. Does historical materialism entail the way people gain their living and mold their ideas? Marxism can hardly explain the timeless appeal of Shakespeare to people with different modes of production. Nor can it explain why artistic achievements took place when they did. Marx's priority given to production as an all embracing explanatory factor is a crucial mistake. The Marxist view of history invites man to an uncertain hope. What is The Meaning of History? Positivism (Idealism/Materialism) derives from the idea of progress and historicism. As Christians we must expose inadequacies of the schools of thought about the historical process that have dominated Western thought over the last two centuries. Both the idea of inevitability of progress and historicism (historical relativism) are fatally flawed. Only Judaeo-Christianity can provide confidence in the future. Its keynote of hope is grounded in the twin beliefs that our creator-redeemer God is moving history forward in a straight line and that it will in due time reach His goal. In the cross and resurrection God "disarmed the principalities and powers and made a public example of them, triumphing over them in this (Colossians 2:15). The outcome of history is, therefore, already assured. His promised purpose will be realized. Christian eschatology affirms divine control of the historical process and guarantees the future. Christianity gives historicists their due without being infected with a lethal virus of historical relativism. God's sovereignty over the historical processes is integral to a Christian worldview. A Christian worldview is concerned with both the general tendency of the historical process and also its ultimate goal (Matthew 10.29f). God pays attention to the minute details of human life and that God intervened in history by becoming man and dying for us as 7 salvation from sin and death—is the essence of the Christian faith. The divine mysteries of incarnation and return of Christ are not contradictions of our Lord's divine interventions. The working of God in certain historical events are not empirically available for positivistic analysis, but the creation, incarnation and resurrection are examinable by scientific analysis (K.S. Latourette, "The Christian Understanding of History" The American Historical Review 54 (1949), p. 270). Is the world—nature/history—under God's control? The ultimate answer lies in The Cross of Jesus. Sin, suffering and death were no match for he one who hung on The Cross and who could not be located within a locked and guarded tomb (II Corinthians 5.7; Revelation 7.17). Christianity and history must draw attention to the operation of a general providence. (Note the entire promise line through both the Old and New Testaments. Looking forward we cannot often tell that God is in control, while looking backward we must see that only a sovereign God is in control of human historical events and epochs.) Human history is a compound of necessity and freedom. History entails simultaneous scrutiny along positive and idealistic lines. God controls history; yet He is not fully known within it. Providence affirms a quality of mystery on the historical process. Creation must not be interpreted as a myth or symbol rather than an event. Creation is the starting point of history. Eschatology is revelation of what comes at the end of time, not merely a sign post to the eternal as set forth in Reinhold Niebuhr's, Faith and History: A Comparison of Christian and Modern Views of History (London, 1949), pp. 62ff.). His neo-orthodox theology precludes a solid foundation for a Christian view of history. The essence of our postmodern historiographical debate is the possibility of a "search for the Jesus of history." (See my paper, "Search for the Wrong Jesus") A Christian view of history must constantly be on guard regarding the risk of being over influenced by postmodern alternatives. Historicism and the idea of progress are not the only pitfalls. Christians must be on guard against being attracted to a worldview blending a Christian concept of history with either a Darwinism process philosophy or cyclical view. The study of comparative religion can lead Christians down a dead end street (see my paper, "From Syncretism to Relativism: Challenge In Our Multicultural Epoch, an analysis of Pike, Hick, Kung, Newbigin and responses to non-Christian religions). This danger is ever present in the works of Arnold Toynbee, and Liberation Theology in the style of Gustavo Gutierrez, who attempts to fuse a Christian view of history with a Marxist view, and especially a Western Marxist view influenced by the Frankfort School. The Christian view of history is in no need of syncretistic supplementation. Yet, the stimulus is given by Ernst Block, a member of The Frankfort School, to Jurgen Moltmann's valuable stress on the importance of hope in a Christian view of history (J. Moltmann, Theology of Hope (London, 1967), p. 16). The scriptures still provide the only defensible norm for any Christian perspective on history. The Christian historian must operate within a Biblical frame of meaning that does justice to the complexities of our postmodern, multicultural global village (see crucial works of Herrahd Parker, editors, Ideas in History (Duke University Press, 1995 and D.W. Babbington, Patterns of History. Inter-Varsity Press, 1979). Dr. James Strauss 8