106736873 The Scientific Revolution: Some Key Changes Heliocentrism The most well-known change is the switch from a geocentric (earth-centered) to a heliocentric (sun-centered) conception of the universe. It was first propounded in modern times by the Polish astronomer Nicolas Copernicus (1473-1543) in his posthumous book De revolutionibus orbium coelestium (On the revolutions of the heavenly spheres) in 1543. As Copernicus himself admitted, the idea was not entirely new. It was indeed known to Aristotle. The astronomer-philosopher Aristarchus of Samos had proposed a heliocentric model with an orbiting earth around which the moon orbited – the correct model! But it never caught on. It is not too surprising that it didn’t. It doesn’t feel as if the Earth is moving. It was Galileo who solved this puzzle by developed the concept of relative motion. When you are on a ship moving away from shore, you are moving relative to the shore but not to the ship. Indeed, you could feel yourself at rest on a moving ship. But, importantly, not easily. Only today do we have forms of transport that move us so comfortably that we can fail to notice we are moving. For someone riding a horse, running or on the deck of a pitching ship, motion most definitely is something you feel. On top of this, there was scripture. Joshua commands the sun to be still during a battle to give his people continued daylight enough to kill off the enemy. You can hardly command a sun to stand still if it is not moving in the first place. Based on his observations and the recorded observations of previous astronomers, notably Ptolemy himself, Copernicus realised that a simpler model of the heavens was gained with the sun at the centre. The Heavens From the earliest pre-historic star-gazers to Copernicus, all astronomers shared the same tool for studying the heavens: their eyes. It was Galileo who first pointed a telescope of his own invention up to the skies.i He discovered that the moon had mountains and craters and was not a perfect sphere, as Aristotle had taught. He discovered that Jupiter itself had four moons, thus providing further evidence that not everything revolves around the Earth; that Venus had phases like the moon; and that the sun had dark ‘sun spots’ on it, showing that it too was not a perfect object. (Diehard Aristotelians were not convinced and tried to blame the telescopes for producing misleading images.) A further challenge came in the form of supernovae observed in 1572 and 1604 and studied by astronomers Tycho Brahe and Johannes Kepler respectively. A supernova is an exploding star that shines with intense brightness, being visible even in the daytime. Since the stars were supposed to be a fixed background, the appearance of new stars was a problem. Matter There was a return to various forms of atomism or ‘corpuscularianism’ (‘corpuscle’ = ‘small body’) in the 17th century; a return, that is, to the idea of Greek atomism. Page 1 of 5 106736873 Ordinary objects are composed of lots of small atoms and it is the properties of the atoms and how they compose the larger object that determines the physical properties of the larger object. Matter is therefore not infinitely divisible. Not everyone agreed; Descartes, notably, rejected atomism in favour of infinitely divisible matter. What united Descartes and atomists was the idea that matter was primary. Aristotle regarded matter as a kind of general stuff out of which objects were composed with the form of the object being that which explained the features of the object. The matter is just ‘filling’. Descartes and others rejected the forms and chose the scientific view that remains with us today, namely that the properties of bigger things are to be explained in terms of the properties of their parts. Elements The Aristotelian four-element theory disappeared with the development of atomism. Natural philosophers – scientists, as we would now call them – started identifying other substances, such as water, iron and sulphur, as atomically basic or as elemental. (It would take until the 19th century with Dalton to think of elements as composed of atoms.) Motion Aristotle said that objects need a constant force to remain in motion. This view had been opposed before. The atomist philosopher Lucretius said that the natural state of matter was to be in motion. Galileo (1564-1642) developed the concept of inertia which was refined by Newton in his laws of motion. ‘Inertia’ means ‘resistance to change’. The thought was that an object will remain in the state it is in unless acted upon. Whether it be moving or stationary, the default behaviour of an object is to remain the same. There is therefore no need for a force to keep ‘pushing’ a moving object. Galileo also discovered that falling objects accelerate at a constant rate instead of moving with uniform speed. He wrote that if two cannonballs of different weights were dropped from a height, they would both hit the ground at the same time. This appears not to hold true of all objects; try dropping a feather and a cannonball, for example. Galileo explained that this was because the air provided resistance, not because the feather was special. The legend (and it is only a legend) is that the two-cannonball experiment was performed from the Leaning Tower of Pisa. Aristotle’s law of uniform motion was also something that had been questioned before. Indeed, one of Aristotle’s successors as head of his school, the Lyceum, gave two clear reasons for opposing it. First, if one observes a continuous stream of water falling from a roof, one observes that it does not remain continuous but breaks up into drops that become further apart as they accelerate. Second, the force imparted on impact is clearly proportional to the distance dropped: a stone dropped a metre will make less of an impact than one dropped from a hundred metres. This is hard to explain if one assumes constant velocity and a natural connection between motion and degree of ‘oomph’ that is familiar from horizontal motion: e.g. if you want to break a door down, it is easier to pick up a lot of speed. Force Aristotle’s distinction between the terrestrial and celestial spheres with its two types of motion was dismantled. The Earth and the heavens are part of the same universe. Page 2 of 5 106736873 The ‘natural’ form of motion, Newton argued, was rectilinear. Objects move in nonrectilinear paths as a result of forces acting on them. The planets’ move not in circular but elliptical orbits because of gravitational forces. (It was the German astronomer Kepler (1571-1630) who discovered that the planets have elliptical orbits; Newton showed that the planets should move in elliptical orbits if his laws of motion were correct, thus vindicating them.) Newton’s concept gravitational force was revolutionary and extremely controversial. For Newton was proposing that two objects could attract one another without anything between them pulling them together. Scientists and philosophers alike found it very hard to give up the principle of no action at a distance. Indeed, it took until the 19th century before the concept of a force finally became an accepted physical concept and until the 20th century for a deeper explanation of gravity. Space The two fundamental questions about space were whether it is finite or infinite and whether it is full or has pockets of emptiness: vacua. In antiquity, opinion was divided over the first question but pretty much agreed on the second. There cannot be vacua. How could a pocket of nothing exist? The view was widespread later amongst scholars in the Islamic world and in Christendom. How could nothingness exist in the divinely-created totality that was the universe? The existence of vacua was finally established in the 17th century with the invention of the barometer. (Earlier, evidence for vacua was provided by the suction pump, which was invented at the start of the 13th century but they were never powerful enough to clinch the case.) Torricelli and Pascal showed that a glass cylinder filled with mercury, open at one end, turned upside down in a basin of mercury left an empty space between the top of the closed end and the surface of the mercury. Nevertheless, the experiment was contested. Descartes did not believe in vacua and argued that the cylinder must have tiny holes that let in matter to fill the gap. Descartes held the (standard) view that space was a plenum: entirely filled. (A third and related question that become the subject of vigorous dispute in the 17th century was whether space was absolute or relative. Two of the greatest minds of the time, Newton and Leibniz took opposing views. Newton took the view that space was absolute. This means that space was a something – an infinitely big something – that existed independently of the matter in it. In theory, there could be an empty universe. Leibniz argued for the relativist view. There is no such thing as space. There are objects with three-dimensional bulk, so to speak. Space is, in a sense, created by objects. To put it more accurately, space is a way of talking about the arrangement of objects.) Mathematics: Quantitative and Qualitative Galileo famously wrote that the book of nature is written in the language of mathematics. His point was some key properties needed to explain natural phenomena were quantifiable. For example, mass is a quantifiable property as there are different amounts of mass that can be represented by a numerical scale: e.g. a scale of mass in grams. Also quantifiable are temperature, length, depth, breadth, density and velocity, for example. By contrast, colour and flavour are not quantifiable. There is no property of colour that comes in degrees that can be mathematically represented. Page 3 of 5 106736873 Where properties are quantifiable, laws can be stated that relate degrees of the properties. In other words, you can write equations such as distance = velocity x time. This leads us to… Primary vs. Secondary Qualities Very roughly speaking, the primary/secondary distinction is to capture the idea of the difference between the way the world really is and the way it appears to us thanks to the particular creatures we are. The shape of a red cube is a paradigm primary quality. The shape results from the way the matter is arranged. The redness is a paradigm secondary quality. It appears red because it causes us to have a sensation of a certain sort. Other animals that are not sensitive to that part of the electromagnetic spectrum might not see it as red. But no creature could perceive the cube as anything other than cubic. Secondary qualities are thus observer-dependent whereas primary qualities are not. The view was that science should look for and deal with the primary qualities. The secondary qualities are mere decoration that result from the interaction of our sensory organs with the world. They are irrelevant to physics. The colour of a cube has no bearing on how fast it moves if thrown; the mass does. Primary qualities are quantifiable whereas secondary qualities are not. The mass of a cube can be represented with a numerical value (relative to a scale); the colour cannot be. Mechanism The resulting scientific world-view came to be known as mechanism. Stripped of its familiar sensory qualities, the universe is a collection of bits of stuff with certain primary qualities, such as masses and shapes. These bits of stuff move in ways determined by laws of motion, collide and react, be it by combining or bouncing off or smashing each other into smaller bits. Precisely happens depends on the primary qualities. The reactions are determined by laws of nature. There is no room for chance or choice: if two bits of stuff collide in the same way twice, the same thing will happen. In short: nature is a lot of bits of stuff colliding with one another in fixed ways. Why mechanism? A mechanism such as a watch or an engine is a collection of bits of stuff that perform a function by ‘colliding’ with one another – by exerting forces on one another. In short, Aristotelian physics explained the behaviour of things in terms of their teloi. Mechanism is non-teleological. Things behave as they do because there are laws of nature that they ‘blindly’ obey. To put things in a slight longer way that will become clearer when we turn to his metaphysics, Aristotle’s physics sees a world of very many different substances with their distinctive qualities. To explain natural phenomena, we look to the distinctive qualities of the substances in question and ask after the goals they define. The mechanistic world view cuts down on the number of substances. There is just one type of stuff – physical stuff out of which all the distinct Aristotelian substances are composed. It may be composed of different types of atoms but this is irrelevant. For natural phenomena are explained by reference to a small class of primary properties common to all types of atom, such as shape and mass. These properties are quantitative properties rather than qualitative. There are mathematical relationships Page 4 of 5 106736873 between them that are the laws of nature that govern their behaviour without reference to any purpose or function. Descartes’ Views (A Summary) Descartes favoured heliocentrism. He rejected the theory of the spheres and the fixed stars. He thought space was a plenum: entirely full of matter. Matter is infinitely divisible. Nevertheless, we can speak of large objects being made out of smaller atomic-like clumps of matter called corpuscles; where atoms genuinely cannot be divided, corpuscles can. Descartes was a mechanist. The physical world is matter in motion. It is the size, shape and matter of the parts that determines the organisation and function of the whole. These are the primary qualities that science should deal in. The secondary qualities of material objects trigger innate sensory ideas in us. The physical world obeys strict laws of nature. i Galileo did not invent the telescope. Credit goes to a Dutch lens-maker, Hans Lippershey. The telescopes he made had a low magnifying power (x3) and were being sold as toys. When Galileo came across an example in 1609, he saw its potential and made a better one within a day. He soon managed to make one with a twenty-fold magnifying power. (His improvements were in part owed to an alteration of design. Lippershey had combined two convex lens in a tube; Galileo combined a concave and a convex lens. This had the added benefit of keeping the image the right way up.) To say that Lippershey was a lens-maker of course implies that the idea of lenses used for magnification was already known. Lenses were known in Ancient Greece but used as devices to concentrate the sun’s rays to start fires. The first discussion of lenses as magnifying devices and, importantly, the optical theory to explain their function is by Ibn al-Haytham (a.k.a Alhazan) (965-1038) in his Kitab al-Manazir (Book of Optics). Spectacles were invented in the 13th century in Europe. It is of interest to note that was known over a thousand years earlier , Seneca (1 B.C.–65 A.D.) observes in his Natural Questions that a glass filled with water had a magnifying effect that made letters bigger and easier to read. Page 5 of 5