The Precautionary Principle: reaffirming its scientific, ethical and political importance Hugh Lacey Associação Filosófica ‘Scientiae Studia”, São Paulo 15 June, 2012 Our session, ‘Science and technology for social justice and preservation of the earth’, aims to respond to the question: How and by whom should scientific research be conducted, scientific knowledge used, and technologies developed, so as to ensure that the earth is respected, its regenerative powers not further undermined and restored wherever possible, and the well being and rights of everyone everywhere enhanced? I take for granted that reductionist approaches to science are seriously incomplete and that ‘science‘ properly understood, requires the contributions of indigenous and other forms of marginalized knowledge; and that ‘technology’ includes ‘social technologies’ developed in interaction with marginalized communities for the sake of developing effective means for generating social transformation’. This question provokes exploring a positive vision of what science might become, responsive to democratic input and oversight, to inform projects aiming for social transformation that embody the values of social justice and preservation of the earth. It also provides a point of reference for critique of current dominant tendencies of science and technology, in which scientific research has become subordinated to the quest for technoscientific innovations that contribute to economic growth and other interests of current capitalist arrangements – and so: What steps should be taken to counter scientific and technological practices that impede social justice, are destructive of the earth, and threaten massive, irreversible harm to human beings and the environment? Adopting the Precautionary Principle is one of these steps. PP was brought to the attention of a wide public by the Rio Declaration of 1992, and it gained adherents in some policy and regulation making bodies – but its place is far from secure. Here, at Rio + 20, it is important to reaffirm PP creatively: • making clear that its meaning derives from a positive vision 1 • to identify and reject misinterpretations and distortions of it • to define clearly how it should influence, not only public policy about technoscientific innovation, but also the agendas of scientific research and application • to challenge the way in which much of the dominant scientific and technological mainstream incorporates interests and values that are opposed to it. PP should not be identified with a particular version such as the one used in the Rio Declaration, for that is a product of compromises reached in negotiations and subject to renegotiation. The ethics, law and responsibilities of technoscientific innovation (and formulations of PP itself) are not fixed once for all. They develop in response to new exigencies, perspectives, ethical and legal deliberations, and responses to our guiding question. Given the short time available, I will simply state what I take the principal components of PP to be. PP is relevant in situations where available scientific knowledge does not permit definitive conclusions about possible (ethically salient) effects of a technological innovation, their significance and the likelihood that they would occasion harm. In these situations, if available scientific knowledge is consistent with the plausibility of the hypothesis that it could bring about serious (perhaps irreversible) harm to people, social arrangements or the earth, PP proposes: (1) Intervention to avoid the possible harm –– taking into account the possible harmful consequences of the precautionary interventions themselves –– including, when the harm is sufficiently serious, delaying final decisions about permitting or regulating use of the innovation. (2) Such delay is to allow time for appropriate scientific research to be conducted: (i) What is the likelihood of the possible harm occurring in the context of actual use of the innovation? Can it be adequately regulated? When dealing with possible long-term ecological and social harm, what are its socioeconomic mechanisms, as well as its physical/chemical/biological mechanisms? (ii) What are the possibilities and risks of alternative courses of action? 2 (3) Evaluate the seriousness of the possible harm in the light of such values as respect for the full range of human rights, environmental sustainability, equity within and between generations, participatory democracy. (4) Long-term monitoring of the effects of any actually used innovation – so as to enable decisions to be reviewed and reversed should evidence be found that harm is actually being caused. (5) Democratic decision-making, involving all relevant stake-holders, about such matters as the length of the period of delay before making final decisions, the possible harmful effects (and the alternative courses of action) that need to be investigated scientifically, and with what priority. (6) Normally, the burden of proof for the safety of an innovation, and legal liability for any harm that is caused, should be assumed by those who introduce its implementation. PP challenges standard commercial practices of innovation, and it is in tension with regulations of the World Trade Organization which permit innovations provided that there is no compelling evidence available of actually causing harm. Consequently, it is often ignored, belittled, distorted, parodied, subverted, deemed ‘unrealistic’ – and (above all) criticized as a negative influence that slows down ‘progress’, by impeding business interests and the ‘development’ policies of certain countries, and leading to ‘regressive, burdensome regulations’. It is also said to dull the potential for using technoscience to solve ‘humanitarian’ problems (e.g., hunger and malnutrition). Critics also have charged that PP involves the illegitimate intrusion of ethics into scientific research, interfering with the proper autonomy of science. All of this does make sense from the viewpoint of commitment to the values and interests of capital and the market, to the presumption that the subordination of scientific research to these values does not represent an illegitimate intrusion of social and ethical values that interferes with 3 the proper autonomy of science, and to the claim that there are no serious alternatives and aspirations outside of the trajectory of technoscientific innovation for economic growth. In fact, however, PP actually serves to counter intrusions of ethical, social and political values, and special interests that reflect them, that are currently affecting mainstream scientific research and subordinating it to corporate and government interests; and, far from curtailing scientific research, the impetus of PP is to highlight research that responds to our guiding question. The critical role of PP is of great importance: science conducted in response to our guiding question does aim to inform steps that will minimize harm – but its primary thrust is to identify scientific practices that will contribute towards enhancing well being in general. Its critique points positively towards the agenda of social justice and preservation of the earth – it criticizes for the sake of enabling better alternatives to develop [it criticizes transgenics for the sake of gaining space for alternatives (like and including agroecology – and programs for ‘food sovereignty’) to develop. In order to define the research priorities for this agenda, appropriate forums for democratic deliberation will need to be created and be responsive to (what I call) the ‘range of alternatives’ question: In the light of the proposed benefits of a practice [solution to a problem, technoscientific innovation], what is the range of alternatives that might offer comparable or ‘better’ benefits, not limited to alternatives that essentially are involved in technoscientific innovation, but taking into account options that may be informed by methodologies that are not utilized for the pursuit of technoscientific innovation and that may make use of developments of traditional and indigenous knowledge? And which of them, all things considered, is the ‘best’ alternative? The relevant investigation needs to take into account that ‘best’ may be thought of differently in the context of different locations, cultures and value perspectives. E.g., regarding agriculture: What options are available in agriculture – ‘conventional’, transgenic, organic, subsistence, indigenous, agroecological, 4 permaculture, etc, and others adapted for use in urban settings –, and in what combinations and with what locally specific variations, for practices that are (i) highly productive of nutritive foods, environmentally sustainable, not dependent of the use of agrotoxics, and protective of biodiversity (ii) more aligned with, and strengthening of, rural communities and the diversity of their aspirations with place and culture (iii) capable of having an integral role in producing the food needed to feed the increasing world population; and (iv) particularly suited to ensure that rural populations in impoverished regions are well fed and nourished? The range of alternatives question needs to be addressed in as many areas as possible in order to assess the prospects for fruitful research that can inform the agenda of social justice and preservation of the earth. PP needs to be combined with the ‘space of alternatives’ question for its full scientific, ethical and political significance – and the spuriousness of the criticisms made of it – to be apparent. 5