Questions to ask about Contemporary Reactions and Reviews How did Berkeley’s contemporaries understand him? What did they find most interesting about his views? What objections did they raise? Percival’s letter to Berkeley of 26 August, 1710 Those who hear of Berkeley’s immaterialist thesis treat it with ridicule and reject it without thinking it worth the bother of reading what he has said to defend it They assume that Berkeley himself must either be mad (if sincere) or insincere (and merely out to make a name for himself by offering ingenious arguments for false conclusions) Lady Percival’s objection: What are we to make of the creation story if there is nothing but spirits and ideas? Berkeley’s Reply Notwithstanding its agreement with common sense, the immaterialist theory needs to be “introduced with great caution into the world” since it “contradicts vulgar and settled opinion” [!] Rather than say that the book denies the existence of matter, say that it promotes “true knowledge and religion” and offers a new proof of the existence of God and the immortality of the soul. Berkeley’s Reply to Lady Percival The creation consists in making ideas eternally existing in God’s mind perceptible to other finite spirits. [so we perceive ideas that exist in God’s mind rather than our own ideas?] While scripture and reason assure us that there are indeed other finite spirits (and hence ones that might have been around to witness the creation) … … it is “sufficient if we suppose that a man, in case he was then created and existing at the time of the chaos, might have perceived all things formed out of it in the very order set down in Scripture” [so unperceived existence needs to be understood phenomenalistically?] Percival’s Letter to Berkeley of 30 October 1710 William Whiston and Samuel Clarke gave some attention to Berkeley’s Principles They found it clever … …and considered it to be like the works of Malebranche, Norris and [Leibniz?] But both thought it wrong. Whiston did not consider himself to have the philosophical training to answer Berkeley, though he was convinced Berkeley was wrong. Clarke did not consider Berkeley’s position to be worth replying to. Le Clerc’s Critique of Berkeley’s Rejection of Abstract Ideas of Extension While we cannot imagine (form a mental image) of a geometrical figure that has no specific size or colour, … … we can conceive (grasp the concept) of such a thing (grasping a concept is an act of pure intellect, and need not involve the formation of an image [cf. Descartes’s example of the concept of a chiliagon] Tangible extension is no more the object of geometry than visual extension. Both vision and touch supply us only with aids for focusing the mind on intelligible objects. Berkeley’s Reply to Le Clerc i. I don’t know about you, but I don’t have an ability to grasp the concept of a thing apart from forming an image of that thing … …and I can’t even imagine what it would mean. ii. If there were such a thing as pure intellect, it would be the means whereby we know our own soul and other spiritual things [e.g., relations] … … but sensible qualities cannot be conceived otherwise than by forming representations of [particular] sensible things, from which they cannot be separated. iii. Focusing your attention on one quality of a sensible thing is not the same thing as forming a separate, abstract idea of that quality. I can only do the former. The object of geometry need not be an actually touched magnitude … … it could be an object we imagine by combining or dividing ideas of extension previously received from touch. This is still not an intelligible object. The Journal des Sçavans (September 1711) (Keep in mind that you are reading a translation of a review originally written in French of a work written in English.) Berkeley’s thesis is that “neither body nor matter exists, and … there is no being or substance other than spirits.” “Everything else that we take to exist external to us is nothing … but ideas …. They have no existence apart from that of being perceived, and they cease to be or to exist when our mind or some other mind ceases to perceive them.” The first argument that the reviewer mentions as employed to prove “so seemingly strange an hypothesis” is the negative answer to the Molyneux question. Everyone grants that the “accidental qualities” revealed to us by our senses (heat, colour, etc.) are merely sensations that no external thing can resemble. The fact that someone newly made to see would not recognize figures familiar from touch shows that we do not get the same ideas of the primary qualities of bodies from vision that we do from touch. So our senses do not inform us accurately of the primary qualities of bodies either. Note that this argument only establishes the sceptical thesis that we can’t know that matter exists, not the idealist thesis that there can be no such thing as matter. The reviewer cites 2 arguments for concluding that we cannot infer the existence of matter from reasoning about the causes of sensations. The sensations had when delirious are just as vivid as those had when we are calm, though they are not caused by external bodies and so cannot resemble them. Whatever causes our sensations must be endowed with power and volition, which does not conform to our idea of body … … because matter cannot act on spirit … and because an intelligence with no body [and in a world where there are no bodies] could receive all the same sensations we do Though the second of these arguments gives a reason for idealism, the further additions suggest that the reviewer regards it as merely sceptical (a reason for denying knowledge of matter, not its existence) The reviewer cites Berkeley’s arguments for concluding that matter cannot be an instrument or occasion of perception, lists some of Berkeley’s reasons for considering immaterialism to be advantageous, especially a response to scepticism grounded in “veil of perception” arguments takes note of Berkeley’s views on time and consequent view that the soul always thinks, ineptly states his views on space space “is just the ease with which I find I can move what I imagine to be my body” and remarks on his position on infinite divisibility. The reviewer’s summary of Berkeley’s discussion of objections and replies the question of unperceived existence is given pride of place; God’s perception is not mentioned as a solution the question of how the soul could contain extended ideas without being itself extended is mentioned second one of Berkeley’s reported answers is that “extension exists in the soul only as a perception, not as reality” Note that the reviewer makes no comment on the concluding section of the Principles on self-knowledge and proofs for the existence of God and other minds. Mémoires de Trévoux (May, 1713) Uses Berkeley’s work to attack Malebranche Berkeley is represented as someone who has taken Malebranche’s position to its logical, but absurd extreme by actually denying the existence of a material world “it is for those who believe that we see only an intelligible world to prove that this is carrying their principles too far.” Mémoires de Trévoux (December, 1713) (on Three Dialogues) Represents Berkeley as maintaining that “we see bodies only in God, hence it is unnecessary for them to exist outside of God” And as maintaining that the creation “is only the decision that God made to imprint on minds the ideas of bodies” The Journal Litéraire (May/June 1713) Berkeley is someone “more attached to advancing paradoxes and wholly new opinions than to carefully examining the opinions that he refutes” His book does not contain any arguments that a reader will find convincing (“a reading of the book will keep [the reader] from holding what the author holds”) He holds the “strange” view that there are no bodies. What we call bodies are only ideas that cannot exist apart from spirits who have these ideas. Hence that what we call body is a “chimera” “chimera” probably means something cooked up by the mind all on its own Berkeley wastes time trying to prove that “secondary qualities” are merely sensations that cannot exist outside of us. (everyone today accepts that these are sensations arising in us as a consequence of how our nerves and brains are moved by bodies) And he attacks a straw man when attempting to refute this view by saying that it is contradictory to say that sound is a motion. [Berkeley’s point was just that we do not immediately perceive the causes of sounds or colours] The crux of Berkeley’s argument is his attempt to prove that the primary qualities can exist only as ideas. This is a conclusion that he attempts to draw by appeal to various perceptual relativity arguments. But these arguments only prove that we ought to take account of the changing ways in which objects are related to us when determining what their permanent primary qualities really are. Berkeley also tries to argue that since we cannot conceive extension apart from all sensible qualities, it cannot exist apart from those qualities, and since they all exist only in the mind, it can only exist there. But this is tantamount to arguing only that the conception or idea of extension must be an idea in the mind, not that extension itself must be in the mind. The reviewer neglects Berkeley’s challenge to say what else it would mean for extension to exist. Berkeley’s arguments over the second half of Dialogues I and Dialogues II neglect to consider that God, being all powerful, could have made inanimate beings capable of acting on spirits in such a way as to make them have ideas. While it is possible that God could directly impose all our ideas on us rather than use material instruments, to maintain that this is what God actually does is to accuse him of being a deceiver. The reviewer acknowledges Berkeley’s contrary point that we are not compelled to believe in external objects, but does not consider it correct. However, the reviewer continues to neglect Berkeley’s charge that an active, unthinking thing is a contradiction in terms and so not something even God could produce. Berkeley has not in fact preserved common sense opinions concerning the reality of things. While Berkeley may say that things are exactly what he knows them to be, so that the whiteness of a horse is in the horse, he does not mean the same thing that ordinary people mean (he only means that his ideas occur together; they mean something more) And they would hardly agree with his view that the horse exists only in their heads. This is a bad lampoon of Berkeley’s view. Heads are bodies. Ideas exist in minds, not bodies. On Berkeley’s view, each different view of an object is actually a different object (a different collection of ideas) and we merely decide to call different collections of ideas by the same name, so that the unity of these collections is an arbitrary imposition. This means that: the hand that strikes the blow is not the one that was seen to strike the stick used to strike is not the one held in the hand the person who committed the crime is not the one taken to court the person hanged on the gallows is not the one convicted of the crime Another bad lampoon. This one neglects Berkeley’s account of spirits. A Sharp Contrast to the Early Reception: Mill’s Comments on Berkeley Berkeley made three revolutionary philosophical discoveries: i. that much of what we think we immediately perceive is in fact a product of a learned association of signs with things. ii. that there are no such things as abstract ideas. iii. that what it means for an object to exist outside of us is just that groups of sensations occur to us independently of our wills and in accord with inviolable laws. The first of these discoveries is independent of immaterialism, but prepares the way for it. It teaches us that vision is a language (learned by experience) that God uses to tell what tangible objects we are likely to experience next. That observation is one that can be extended to all the other senses, establishing a paradigm for research in the psychology of perception. When it is so extended, each sensible quality or combination of sensible qualities serves as a sign for other sensible qualities. The second discovery is likewise independent of immaterialism, but serves as an important premise in the argument for it. It resolves the long-standing problem of the nature of universals (the conflict between realists and nominalists) The solution consists in realizing that a common name connotes only some of the qualities of an object (and hence all objects that share those qualities), even though the idea actually called up by the name always has more qualities. The additional qualities are accidental and changeable. In the idea, the common qualities are “made artificially prominent” while the accidental ones are “thrown into the shade” An abstract idea is actually a concrete image that changes over time. The third discovery is the immaterialist theory. It is correct when unperceived existence is accounted for phenomenalistically. For an object exist unperceived is just for it to be the case that were someone present, that person would have sensations of the sort that are called by the name for that object. So that an object is really a more or less “permanent possibility” of obtaining a certain sort of sensory experience. (Nothing makes for this possibility — it is just a law of nature that it is there) Unfortunately, Berkeley himself proposed a rather more extravagant account, involving perception of ideas by God. Mill’s account of why people have been deceived into believing that objects exist unperceived. In virtue of learning from past experience, a single sensation of sight or sound comes to serve as a sign for the “potential presence” many others in a complex group. So we form ideas of imagination of those others. Then subsequent experience confirms that those ideas of imagination were in fact good copies of the ideas of sense we get when we move to where experience would lead us to expect those ideas. This leads us to mistake the “potential presence” of the signified sensations for an abiding “latent cause” of those sensations existing in space outside us. In fact, there are no such causes — only regularities in the succession of sensations.