Department of Psychology

advertisement
1
Department of Psychology
University of Alberta
Psychology 304
Mid-term examination questions
October 31, 2008
I request that you select two (2) questions from among the following to answer on your
mid-term examination. Please restrict your answers to one-page or so.
1. I decided this summer to orient this course in accord with a particular theme. The
theme I chose can be formulated as a question: “why do we have this strange fear
of consciousness?” After all, we are mindful of ourselves and others, we are a
vital part of the flow of life that surrounds and sustains us, and we are surrounded
by a life larger than ourselves (languages, societies, cultures). Yet what
characterizes our modern age is a kind of ‘theoretical austerity” which commits us
to a minimal theory “as if” we had no mind and we were not conscious, resulting
in a gap between life and theory (knowledge) or between life and reason which
haunts us to the present. Comment.
2. I suggested that the 17th c transformation of human life in the systematization of
the “new science” (e.g., Descartes) was above all made possible by the power of
the human mind (e.g., a mathematical vision of the universe). Not only do we
discover a renewed vision of human freedom but we engaged in formulating
original concepts that were not merely passively found in nature but were
constructed in order to organize our experience of nature. I also suggested that the
emergence of this scientific view of the world quickly gave rise to a paradox:
science versus the ideology of science, or “scientism”. In what is the course of a
remarkable development spanning some 300 years, the dazzling new
science/technology of nature was extended to include the human
mind/consciousness itself reaching the bizarre point, today, where we are in
danger of losing any intelligent grasp on the human mind/consciousness
altogether. Comment.
3. I noted that the founders of the “new science” (e.g., Kepler, Galileo, Newton) felt
little unease with their brilliantly formulated mathematical and mechanistic vision
of the universe. In fact, they deemed this mechanistic view of nature as the way
God managed this universe! But the far-reaching implications of their vision were
noted by philosophers, in an implied metaphysics and epistemology that
Whitehead in the 20th c. called “scientific materialism”: Nature as machine!
Scientific materialism as an epistemology (theory of how we know) held that
nature is not what is appears to be and as a metaphysics (theory of what there is,
“primary qualities”) the mind was not really free but fully determined as part of
the machine of nature. This left the soul sitting precariously on the edge of Nature
as machine, on the edge of matter. Comment.
2
4. The new science opened a universe so unimaginably vast, dislodging the earth,
and humanity, from its privileged position in the cosmos, that it led Blaise Pascal
(1623-1662), considered on of the greatest minds of the 17th c. and a mean
mathematician and believing Christian, to utter “the eternal silence of those
infinite spaces frightens me”. This cosmic alienation is also paradoxical insofar as
Pascal in giving expression to his consciousness of this vastness also recognized
that we are but an infinitesimally small part of this vastness of the universe. The
question that arises is whether human reason can embrace this paradox (undo it),
as, say in Leibnitz’ metaphysics, and so heal our alienation. Comment.
5. The 17th c is often seen as the century of reason (Enlightenment) bringing to
fruition Francis Bacon’ glorious vision of the betterment of humankind. Of
course, in a way this vision of the “new science” would eventually bring about
such “betterment” during the next three centuries. Yet this 17th c ideal was
quickly turned into a telos or ideology of the promise of “endless progress” which
even now has not been fulfilled as is evident in all the tensions, uncertainties, and
malaise of our modern age (or what Psychology has termed the age of “anxiety”).
Indeed, I have alluded to the possibility that perhaps at some time in the future we
may well regret that our minds are not preoccupied with the larger (religious)
questions of “being and meaning”. Comment.
6. It was Descartes (1595-1650) who appreciated that the “new science” brought not
only certainty (of reason/mathematics, e.g., in a Copernican vision of the
universe) but also doubt (of the senses – the universe is not as it appears to be). If
the senses cannot offer certainty, then it must be the “thinking I” that gives us
certainty. However, Descartes’ “I think” was merely a starting point for his
method of systematic doubt which would isolate an absolute starting point for
thinking (“I cannot doubt the I that doubt’s – thinks”). In my criticism of
Descartes, I did not so much criticize his effort to ground certainty in the
“subjective” as I criticized his conception of the subjective “I” as an abstraction.
For Descartes’ “I think” is a “logical move”; it is not the “I” as the embodiment of
our memories, hopes, emotions, etc., living with others in community. Hence,
Descartes’ split within the self between reason (soul-stuff) and body (matter-stuff)
is paradoxically one between the self as reason (subject) and the self as lived
(object) in which both are abstractions. Comment.
7. Leibnitz (1646-1716) clearly saw the problems surrounded Newton’s picture of
the universe-as-machine and he also understood that Descartes’ striving after
certainty in splitting reason off from the body was because Descartes held to the
view of body as extension (mere matter). While Leibnitz’ view of monads (in
place of “bits of moving matter”) may seem far fetched (perhaps less so today
than back then), this radical new metaphysics in spiritualizing the body and soul
in a psychophysical harmony, no longer leaves the soul precariously perched on
the edge of matter, as the body is now spiritualized as a center of energy and
destiny. Remarkably, while we today criticize Descartes mind–body dualism, it
3
was Leibnitz who reminded us that it was not Descartes’ view of mind that is a
problem but especially our view of the body-as-matter that precludes the integrity
of the self. Comment.
8. Leibnitz principle of “sufficient reason” in reply to his question “why is there
anything at all rather than nothing?” reflects two persistent themes that are still
troubling us today: (1) the separation of the self between soul (mind) and body,
(to which Leibnitz’ “monadology” was an answer but which, of course, we longer
accept) and (2) the mind and body as a psychophysical unit or monad in relation
to the Divine (“sufficient reason”). It was Nietzsche who, in the 19th c. settled the
latter when he asserted that “God is dead” leaving us with either an abstract mindbody dualism or materialism. Comment.
9. John Locke (1632-1704) aspires to follow the “plain historical method” in
attempting to understand the mind – how do we and what can we know - in
tracing the operations of the mind from sensations to ideas. Yet Locke also echoes
Galileo’s distinction between primary and secondary qualities and maintains that
only primary qualities are metaphysically real. This distinction results in
empiricism’s bifurcation between the experiential world of life and the empirical
world of science. This bifurcation which implies that the experiential world is
always subordinate to the empirical world and that empiricism (the ideology of
what is metaphysically real) is always an abstraction from experience (as
Descartes’ “I” was an abstraction from the lived self). Comment.
10. Locke’s empiricism led Bishop Berkeley to his audacious claim, in an effort to
recover the genuine experiential that was lost by Locke, that “esse est percipi”
(being is perceiving). But surely reality is not so fickle as to depend on
“perceiving it” (or reality cannot be so fickle as to depend on psychology). We
have here in Berkeley’s opposition to, or better, in drawing out the conclusions of,
Locke’s thesis, another contemporary tension between “experience” and
“empirical” in psychology. Berkeley held that Locke, notwithstanding his claim
that he started in the “plain historical method”, was not truly experiential but let
his empiricism be guided by what was assumed to be real (sensations or
“scientific materialism”) and proposed, instead, that whatever is real is ever only
in the mind. Comment.
11. The atheist David Hume takes theist Berkeley seriously and suggests that the
world is simply given as a set of impression out of which then reconstruct the
world. That is, Hume maintains that knowledge, including knowledge of the
“new science”, is grounded in the co-occurrences (associations) of impressions
and that these, as “habits of mind”, are the basis of our knowing the world. Thus,
for example, cause and effect are nothing but the contiguity of impressions and
hence we are never logically justified in speaking of the world or its explanations
as more than psychological habits. On this view, not only does Hume invite
skepticism (our knowledge can never be certain but only psychological) but he
also rids us of the mind as a mere “ghost in the machine” (there are only
4
impressions and their combinations). I suggested that this is a spectator (3rd
person) view of the world (since obviously none of this is “experienced”) but it is
one that was enormously influential in the 19th and the founding of psychology.
Comment.
12. Immanuel Kant sought to rescue the “new science” from the skeptical
consequences of Hume’s empiricist theory of knowledge. Kant begins from
within, and hence accepts, the certainty of knowledge of the “new science”. He
then separates himself from the dogmatic metaphysics, and theology, of Leibnitz.
We have neither privileged access to what is real (metaphysics) beyond the
phenomenal world nor can we simply leave scientific knowledge with the
skeptical consequences of David Hume’s empiricism. Instead, Kant begins with
the question of what role the mind plays in human life, including scientific
knowledge (assuming that we do lead moral, religious, and scientific lives). In
this way Kant confronts scientific materialism in rationalist metaphysical thinkers
such as Descartes and Leibnitz but also in empiricist thinkers such as Locke and
Hume who would extent the role of reason beyond the limit where Kant thought
reason could possibly be valid (such as to attain knowledge). This is Kant’s
“immanent critique”, namely, given that we do know and that we do act morally
what apriori conditions of possibility must we assume “reason” gives to itself
such that we can justify our knowledge of the world and what is moral. Comment.
13. One consequence of Kant’s critical philosophy is that he distinguishes between
practical knowledge (reason in its practical use) and theoretical knowledge
(reason in its theoretical use) giving priority to practical knowledge. In both kinds
of knowledge Kant held that the subject or self essentially contributes to what is
known, either theoretically or practically. In other words, unlike Descartes who
splits the mind off from the body, Kant splits the human mind itself between our
knowledge of the natural world (“the starry heavens above” in which I function
just as part of the machine of nature) and the moral world (the “moral law within”
in which I function as a free and responsible moral agent). Or, he claims that I am
phenomenally determined but noumenally free (where, as you will recall, I cannot
“know” the noumena but must presuppose it). Or, “what I ought to do” can never
be derived or defined in terms of what “is”. These different ways of formulating
the split with us is never adequately resolved by Kant but his efforts to limit
reason, especially in his rejection of metaphysics, at least made room for the
autonomy of morality (human freedom, and faith) in a world threatened by
scientific materialism. Comment.
14. I suggested that Kant’s critical philosophy was a turning point in modernity,
deeply affecting the course of the next two centuries. Yet Kant’s analysis remains
formalistic and transcendental (apriori conditions of possibility of knowledge)
and so he never comes to grips with the concrete embodied self that underlies the
will that gives itself reason (or reason that gives itself the will). While there are no
free-floating impressions or ideas in Kant (consciousness is always consciousness
of the “transcendental ego”), neither is Kant’s ego “substantial” in the sense that
5
his transcendental ego adheres to the minimalist empiricist assertion that the “I”
must be capable of accompanying reason. The reason is obvious because for Kant
we can never know the thing-in-itself, including the self (it belongs to the
noumenal world), and hence the mind or self cannot be known. Perhaps Kant
pushed the requirements for knowledge too far (giving too much to Hume’s
skepticism) thereby blurring the epistemological demands of knowledge and the
existential demands of life. He tried to heed both but he also fell into the trap of
believing that knowledge must be certain and complete (explanation) or else it is
not knowledge. This either/or position in the 19th century would lead either the
abandonment of mind altogether (scientific materialism or “positivism”) or else to
idealism (Hegel). Comment.
15. Besides our ordinary and scientific knowledge of the world, Kant also claims that
there is practical moral knowledge. But when, for example, we say that “one
ought to tell the truth” we can ask what kind of knowledge this “ought” is
especially as Kant maintains that even if it is an empirical fact that everybody lies
we would still know that we ought to tell the truth. For Kant uncovering what this
knowledge is implies that we must uncover the apriori element of moral law in
making a moral judgment. This moral law which is universal must be grounded in
reason alone, meaning that it must not consider empirical circumstances or
derived from theology. This moral law (“categorical imperative”) is an end in
itself – the objective ground of self-determination – and binding on all rational
beings in willing the good. Hence, the will of every rational being is to make
universal law (in making moral choice) and doing so demonstrates the autonomy
of the will and the sole principle of all morality and duty. In short we should
always act, as rational beings, such that our action could be valid as a principle
making universal law. Comment.
16. Franz Joseph Gall, the discoverer of “organology”, was critical of the empiricist
reliance on sensation and introspection and sought to bring objectivity to our
understanding of the relation between mind and brain. He argued that since the
brain was “organized” (as evidenced by his comparative studies of brains) so
indeed should the mind be organized. Accordingly, he suggested that the faculties
of mind which distinguished people (individual differences) were innate and
corresponded to the developed “organs of the brain”. Thus while the faculties
were common to all people, through individual differences in their use these
faculties would develop very differently and this was evident in the structure of
the organs of the brain as revealed by their appearance on the skull. In this way,
Gall was not interested in the general nature of the mind (as were the empiricists
in their focus on sensation, ideas, attention, and memory) but in individual
differences in conduct, and he was objective in that everyone had these faculties
and they were grounded in the brain. In this way Gall argued for the localization
of function of the brain against the then fashionable “mass action” of brain
function. Comment.
6
17. Electricity was as yet not well understood in the middle of the 18th c when
Benjamin Franklin would begin to use the newly invented Leyden jars to deliver
electrical sparks in service of healing various disorders. Franklin encouraged the
experimental use of medical electricity and found that he was able to eliminate
symptoms of hysteria, melancholia, and general nervous disorders (“lunacy”) by
exiting sluggish nerves juices. Yet in his criticism of Franz Anton Mesmer’s
claim about the existence of “animal gravity”, Franklin remained skeptical and
indicated that perhaps Mesmer’s cures were brought about by “suggestion”. It is
interesting to speculate that just perhaps the efficacy of electricity also had a
suggestibility component. But in the light the Ugo Cerletti (1877-1963) and Lucio
Bini (1908-1964) pioneering efforts with electro-convulsive hock therapy 150
years later, the efficacy of medical electricity seems to be confirmed. But then
who is to say that “suggestibility” is not a form of medical treatment? “Comment.
18. Hegel radically eliminates Kant’s effort of limit the scope of reason such that
Reason becomes Absolute and manifests itself in the realms of nature and spirit
(mind, society, history). He then suggests that the human mind or spirit
participates in the Absolute’s self-knowledge and that this process is a historical
one wherein we can distinguish among different levels of consciousness, or Spirit:
(a) consciousness as standing over and against the sensible object (nature), (b)
self-consciousness as social consciousness (master-slave, or “other
consciousness”), and (c) consciousness as the unity of consciousness and selfconsciousness in Reason. I suggested that it was Hegel’s brilliant insight to
understand social consciousness which is the tension of two consciousnesses that
would threaten to annihilate each other were it not for the fact that freedom
requires recognition of and recognition by the “other”. Hegel notes that we can
escape this dialectic only if we withdraw inwardly in what will become a divided
(unhappy) consciousness. If we are to avoid the latter divided or Stoic
consciousness, then we must overcome the contradiction of self-consciousness
such that we come to recognize freedom both within ourselves and in others. This
recognition is also consciousness of the infinite Spirit (Absolute) wherein we are
bound as finite beings without our differences being annulled. This moral
consciousness is one wherein the will expresses itself in an awareness of
difference. Comment.
LPM/October 21/08
Download