Mental Lexicon Running head: SYSTEMATICITY IN THE MENTAL LEXICON Exploring systematicity in the mental lexicon Richard Shillcock*, Simon Kirby*, Scott McDonald*, Chris Brew†, * University of Edinburgh, Scotland † Ohio State University, USA Corresponding author: Dr. Richard Shillcock School of Philosophy, Psychology, and Language Sciences University of Edinburgh 7 George Square EH8 9JZ Tel: +44 131 650 4425 Email: rcs@inf.ed.ac.uk 17,606 words 1 Mental Lexicon 2 Abstract We present a comprehensive analysis of systematicity in the English lexicon. Systematicity is one of the brain's most successful and pervasive representational strategies. We report statistical analyses of a 100 million-word corpus of contemporary English, in which we quantify “semantic” distances between words in terms of context vectors. We then compare these semantic distances between each word and every other word with the corresponding phonological distances, to show significant systematicity in the relationship between form and meaning: words that sound similar tend to have similar meanings, within the constraints dictated by the size of the adult lexicon. We explore the implications for language processing by comparing the systematicity dimension with other dimensions known to affect lexical access, and we develop a new perspective on the role of pragmatically important words that are pivotal to the systematicity of languages like English, both in the normal and the impaired mental lexicon. Keywords: mental lexicon, phonological form, word meaning Mental Lexicon 3 Exploring systematicity in the mental lexicon Why do English words sound the way they do? The sound /k æ t/ evokes the meanings associated with cats, but there is nothing particularly feline about the sound itself; this observation is Saussure’s “arbitrariness of the sign” (de Saussure; eds. Bally & Sechehaye, 1916). The essential arbitrariness of the relationship between sound and meaning goes against the pervasive structure that we find at every level of linguistic description: there is systematic, compositional structure in the phonology, morphology, syntax, semantics and pragmatics of natural languages. It is reasonable to ask whether the words in the monosyllabic, monomorphemic core of the lexicon – cat, think, chair, has, … – are as atomic and arbitrary as they first appear. In this paper we exploit the fact that it is now possible to use very large corpora to define words syntagmatically as points in a high-dimensional space; such definitions of words can be used as semantic definitions in modelling psychological data (Landauer & Dumais, 1997; Lund, Burgess & Atchley, 1995; Lund & Burgess, 1996; McDonald, 2000a) and allow us to specify the “semantic” distance between any two words in the space. We can also specify the phonological distance between any two words in terms of the number of phonological features that must be changed to turn any one word into another. Thus, for the first time, it is possible to explore exhaustively the contours of the quantitative relationship between form and meaning in a substantial part of the lexicon of a particular language. Below, we report the structure that becomes apparent from this perspective, and we assess the psychological implications for theories of lexical storage and lexical access in speech processing1. The question of how words are stored in the mental lexicon – the brain’s repository of lexical knowledge – has attracted a large volume of research in recent Mental Lexicon 4 decades. A number of powerful paradigms have been developed for studying speech production and perception. Several major themes have emerged: (a) The role of phonology. There have been strong claims to the effect that the phonological form of words determines the functional structure of the mental lexicon. For instance, Fay and Cutler (1988) point out that in malapropisms the target word (e.g. monotony) and its erroneous substitute (e.g. monogamy) tend to resemble each other in their initial segments, number of syllables and stress pattern. They conclude that there is a single mental lexicon organised for speech perception and “cross-wired” for production. Thus, the exigencies of spoken word recognition take precedence, being the aspect of language processing that is least under the individual listener’s control. A second claim for the priority of phonological representations comes from those researchers who argue that the point at which a word is first learned – its Age of Acquisition – conditions its processing in adulthood (see, e.g., Brown & Watson, 1987; Gilhooly & Logie, 1982). In this view, the first words to be stored in the mental lexicon’s phonological space are at an advantage compared with later arrivals, which must accommodate themselves to the presence of the earlier words. (b) The role of word meaning. Category specific impairments, in which the processing of a particular semantic class of words such as tools, furniture, or fruit may be disproportionately impaired, perhaps constitute some of the most provocative evidence concerning the organisation of the lexical and conceptual knowledge (see, e.g., McKenna & Warrington, 1993; McNeil, Cipolotti & Warrington, 1994). Connectionist models have been presented in which feature-based semantic representations allow such effects to emerge, either as the result of sparser coding for certain classes of word (Plaut & Shallice, 1993) or because the lexicon organises itself topographically, so that similar Mental Lexicon 5 words are grouped together in a semantically organised physical space (Miikkulainen, 1997). Unlike Fay and Cutler’s earlier proposal for single, phonologically arranged lexical entries, this last proposal involves separate systematic coding of semantic and phonological information. (c) Localist and distributed representations. Earlier models of the mental lexicon typically involved localist lexical representations, in which a word was stored at an individual address or node (Forster, 1976; Morton, 1969). Over the last fifteen years, the lexicon has also been modelled in terms of distributed mappings between orthographic, phonological and semantic representations (Hinton & Shallice, 1991; Plaut & Shallice, 1993; Plaut, McClelland, Seidenberg & Patterson, 1996; Seidenberg & McClelland, 1989). Such connectionist models involve superpositional storage: all the lexical information of a particular type is stored across the same representational substrate. In this sense, an individual word’s role in the lexicon is constrained by all of the rest of the words in the lexicon. The notion of a single linguistic entity being defined in relation to all other such entities also emerged many years earlier in the structuralism developed by Saussure, but without a concern for processing behaviour and without any computational implementation. (d) Lexical neighbours. When researchers have approached the issue of interference or facilitation between lexical representations, the relationships studied have overwhelmingly been between close neighbours in lexical space, such as might exist by changing one segment in a spoken word or one letter in a written word (Coltheart, Davelaar, Jonasson & Besner, 1977; Luce & Pisoni, 1998). Sometimes these neighbours have shared a rime (e.g., Marslen-Wilson, Moss & vanHalen, 1996), a word beginning (Marslen-Wilson & Welsh, 1978), or a sequence of segments representing the whole of Mental Lexicon 6 the smaller word (McQueen, Norris & Cutler, 1994; Shillcock, 1990), but the two words in each relationship have typically sounded similar in a clear, intuitive sense. Demonstrations of interactions between such words have allowed researchers to make inferences about the functional architecture of the mental lexicon. (e) Lexical categories. Words fall into different syntactic categories: noun, verb, adjective, adverb, preposition, pronoun, and so on. These categories themselves fall into two broader types: function words and content words. This latter distinction has attracted a large volume of research built around the observation that function words and content words may be differentially impaired, as in Broca’s aphasia (Goodglass & Kaplan, 1972; Menn & Obler, 1990), and differentially processed in normal speaking and listening (Cutler, 1993) and reading (Chiarello & Nuding, 1987). Such differences may partly depend on physical distinctions between the two word types; in English, function words tend to be shorter, more frequent and less acoustically prominent than content words. However, function words are also seen as being more closely involved in the articulation of syntactic structure (Cann, 2000), and seem to be better processed in the left hemisphere (Mohr, Pulvermüller & Zaidel, 1994). Significant distinctions in typical phonological form have also been observed between different types of content word: for instance, in English, nouns tend to contain more nasals than verbs, whereas verbs tend to contain more front vowels than nouns (Sereno, 1994). All of these differences between lexical categories suggest possible large-scale distinctions in the functional and even the physical architecture of the mental lexicon. (f) Lexical variables. There has been a consistent interest in developing and testing individual dimensions of lexical variation, such as word frequency (Howes & Solomon, 1951; Whaley, 1978, Monsell, 1991), polysemy (Jastrembski, 1981), Concreteness- Mental Lexicon 7 Abstractness, Imageability (Paivio, Yuille & Madigan, 1968), Age of Acquisition (Gilhooly, 1984), Ease of Predication (Jones, 1985), and Contextual Distinctiveness (McDonald, 2000a; McDonald & Shillcock, 2001). The goal in each case has been to demonstrate that the variable in question can account for a unique and significant part of the variance in participants’ performance in lexical processing tasks, and to provide independent motivation for that variable. Word frequency is the paradigm example: typically it accounts for a substantial fraction of the variance in tasks such as visual lexical decision or naming, and can be motivated by the Hebbian notion that a frequently activated representation becomes progressively more securely stored and easily activated (Monsell, 1991). However, word frequency is correlated with the age at which an individual tends to acquire a particular word, and several researchers have proposed that Age of Acquisition is the true cause of the effects previously attributed to word frequency (Brown & Watson, 1987; Morrison, Ellis & Quinlan, 1992). Many of the lexical variables listed above are similarly intercorrelated, often very highly, and there are substantial problems in experimentally disconfounding the roles they may play in processing (Morris, 1981). The way that these variables interrelate remains a subject of continuing research. This brief and partial sketch of research on the mental lexicon has raised a number of themes that bear on our current study. We will explore how very different words might be related in a model that assumes that the whole lexicon may influence the processing of any one word. We will attempt to go beyond the concern with either phonological or semantic representations by considering the relationship between these two kinds of Mental Lexicon 8 representation. We will compare this way of prioritising words in the lexicon with more extensively investigated variables such as word frequency. Assumptions We make a number of critical assumptions, which we discuss in turn, below. (a) The lexicon changes to accommodate cognitive constraints. The lexicon of any human language is constantly changing, reflecting the fact that describing the world is an open problem, always demanding new referring expressions. Some part of language change will be conditioned by the processing demands of the brain. Words must be capable of being easily learned, stored and accessed for speech recognition and production. It follows that we should be able to detect, to whatever small extent, the processing signature of the brain in the statistical structure of the lexicon. If we know the processing preferences of the brain, then we should find some reflection of those preferences in the structure of the lexicon of an individual language like English. (b) The brain prefers systematicity in representations. Topographic mappings are pervasive in mammalian brains. They preserve structure between representations at different levels and in different locations. In the human brain we see numerous topographic maps in the visual system, for instance, in which the spatial relations of the image falling on the retina are preserved in successive sub-domains of visual processing. There are several different claims regarding the adaptiveness of topographic mappings (see, e.g., Knudsen, du Lac & Esterly, 1987), but it is clear that the systematicity of such mappings is a powerful representational principle, facilitating learning, categorisation and generalisation. If structural relations within and between real-world stimuli are preserved in the representation of those stimuli in the brain, then Mental Lexicon 9 the brain retains the option of performing further, analogically based inferences on various aspects of those stimuli: a systematic representation brings with it a lot of inference “for free”. Because the brain often recycles the solutions to evolutionarily simpler problems, we might expect such a principle to be in evidence at all levels of representation in language processing; indeed, in the auditory cortex there is tonotopic mapping from the cochlea onwards (Mazza, de Pinho & Roque, 1999), and in other brain areas words belonging to different semantic categories cause location-specific activity (Perani, Schnur, Tettamanti, Gorno-Tempini, et al., 1999). If we extend this principle to the contents of the lexicon, then we might expect a systematic relationship between phonological form and meaning: meaning should be derivable from form, to some extent, and form from meaning – similar sounding words should tend to have similar meanings. Thus, if we were designing the ideal lexicon of a natural language we might begin by thinking, for instance, that all of the words for edible things should start with /tß/, all of the words for pleasant things should contain /ˆ/, all of the words for deep-fried things should contain the segment /p/, and so on. Such a systematic lexicon would be maximally easy to learn and to organise for lexical access, and novel words could be coined by speakers and interpreted by listeners using transparent analogy with existing words. (For some of the early interest in this notion, see Wilkins, 1668.) However, there are clearly severe limits to such a project. Speakers and listeners need to refer to tens of thousands of different entities, using words that are not prohibitively long. A compromise might be to save systematicity just for some important core of the lexicon, and allow the principle to be replaced by different criteria for the rest of the words. We might, for instance, find systematicity in the monosyllabic, monomorphemic words or perhaps in a subset of these words, such as the words that Mental Lexicon 10 need to be learned first, or the most communicatively salient words. In contrast, the polymorphemic words have a thoroughgoing, explicit compositional structure: they are constructed from two or more morphemes, which contribute to the overall meaning in a predominantly predictable way and adult speakers of the language are aware of many of the apparent rules. In sum, we might expect to find some relationship between phonological form and meaning, albeit a small one. Indeed, it might be surprising if the lexicon had resisted such an apparently fundamental organising principle of the brain. (c) Superpositional nature of lexical representation. There are many ways of theorising about the lexicon and the nature of lexical representation. In symbolic computational terms we can model words as single addresses in some system, so that the activation of any one word is relatively unaffected by the presence of the rest of the words in the lexicon. For instance, in Forster’s (1976) search model of lexical access the address of a word is reached more or less quickly depending on the number of intervening addresses, but once reached its activation is independent of the state of the rest of the lexical representations. Alternatively, the level of activation of any one lexical representation might be directly affected by that of one or more other words; for instance, in the Interactive-Activation Model of visual word recognition (Rumelhart & McClelland, 1981; McClelland & Rumelhart, 1981), and in the related model of spoken word recognition TRACE (McClelland & Elman, 1986), there are mutually inhibitory connections between word nodes. At the other extreme of the modelling spectrum from symbolic or localist models are models in which words are represented in a distributed fashion, and in which superpositional storage ensures that the activation of any one lexical representation is intimately influenced by the state of all the others that the Mental Lexicon 11 architecture sustains. In a model like that of Seidenberg and McClelland (1989), this relationship between one word and every other word is opaque, being expressed in the hundreds of weighted connections that mediate the mapping between orthography and phonology (and semantics in later developments of this type of model). We will assume that the models towards the distributed end of the spectrum are more psychologically realistic, and that there are constraints of some kind on the parallel activation of more than one word; that is, the activation of any one word is contingent to some degree on the state of all of the rest of the words in the lexicon. This assumption reflects the nature of the computational models of lexical processing which currently provide the best coverage of the human data, but it should be noted that each word could still be influenced by every other lexical representation without assuming superpositional storage. (d) The relationship between form and meaning. Although we have cited Saussure’s claim that signs are arbitrary, ever since Plato there have been arguments for a departure from such an arbitrary relation between form and meaning within individual languages. These claims take the form of anecdotal or descriptive accounts of “sound symbolism”. Thus, for instance, Ultan (1978) has claimed that there is a relation between vowels and the semantics of size. Following work by Tsuru and Fries (1933), there have been a number of studies demonstrating that subjects with no knowledge of a particular language (Japanese, in the initial studies) can still guess the polarity of antonyms such as “hot” and “cold” in that language at a level greater than chance. Finally, there are etymological claims that semantically and phonologically related clusters of English words, such as glint, gleam, glimmer, glisten, glister, glow, glare, glance, gloom, gloaming and hump, lump, slump, bump, plump, rump, dump, clump owe their Mental Lexicon 12 existence to common origins in a putative proto-Indo-European language and subsequent traffic between related languages. Thus there are apparent departures from an arbitrary relation between form and meaning in particular languages, but no comprehensive quantitative exploration of the phenomenon and no demonstration that such observations are even statistically significant in the context of a large sample of the lexicon of a particular language. In summary, we hypothesise that there will be a significant relationship between phonological form and meaning. To some limited extent, words that sound similar should tend to have similar meanings. For any two words, the phonological distance between them should tend to be related to the semantic distance between them. Thus, if we can calculate these two types of distance, this Relatedness of Form and Meaning (RFM) Hypothesis states “There should be a significant correlation overall between all of the phonological distances and the semantic distances between the words in the lexicon, even when explicit compositional morphology and sound symbolism are excluded”. A corollary of this hypothesis is that such systematicity should be adaptive, that it should be possible to find processing advantages that facilitate communication between speakers and listeners. We now turn to the precise calculation of the phonological and semantic distances in the studies we describe below. Measuring phonological distance We calculated the phonological distances between words as edit distances – the number of changes necessary to turn one word into another, lead into gold for instance. The phonological representations of words were taken from the Festival Speech Synthesis Mental Lexicon 13 System2 and were based on distinctive features. Festival uses eight features: one distinguishes consonants from vowels; four classify vowels by length, height, frontness and lip rounding; three classify consonants by type (taking the values of stop, fricative, affricate, nasal, lateral and approximant), voicing and place of articulation. Using these features we created a mismatch function assigning a penalty to each pair of two phones. Vowel features, such as length, are naturally scalar. For these we assigned a penalty of 1 for a small mismatch, and a penalty of 2 for a large mismatch. Consonant features, such as voicing, were treated as nominal variables: all mismatches attracted a uniform penalty of 1 on each dimension. Pairs involving one consonant and one vowel were assigned an additional penalty of 10. This penalty schedule was created on the basis of phonetic knowledge alone, without considering specific words and without knowledge of the semantic distance between any pair of words. It was never varied in the studies reported below after its initial creation. The procedure produced a set of phone-phone distances. Distances between words were generated by applying the Wagner-Fischer edit distance algorithm (Wagner & Fischer, 1974), using the penalty schedule described above, augmented with a uniform penalty of 5 for deletions and insertions. We adopted this simple metric of phonological distance because it is relatively transparent. To illustrate some of the implications of the measure we took a random sample of 40 monomorphemic, monosyllabic, four-phone words and created the tree structure shown in Figure 1, in which the adjacent “leaves” of the tree are the phonologically most closely related words in the sample. In the set of 1733 monosyllabic, monomorphemic words used in the main study below, the two words with the greatest phonological distance between them were lea and prompt. Mental Lexicon 14 Thus, we created a measure that allowed us to specify the phonological distance between any two words. The measure is one that is motivated by speech science and does not incorporate any hidden assumptions from detailed psycholinguistic theories about how words might be stored and accessed. The fact that the basic phonological representations were taken from a state-of-the-art speech synthesis system is evidence that they are sufficient for the recognition of spoken words drawn from a large vocabulary. The edit distance algorithm was already in existence and was not developed with current issues in mind. The phonological edit distances generated were thus independently motivated and constitute a conservative test of the RFM Hypothesis. Measuring semantic distance With the availability of large electronic corpora of text and transcribed speech, together with fast computers, it has been possible in recent years to characterise words by the contexts in which they occur in very large volumes of language (Lund & Burgess, 1996; McDonald & Shillcock 2001; McDonald, 2000a). These syntagmatic, distributional definitions of words have been equated with their meanings for the purpose of modelling psychological data (Landauer & Dumais, 1997; Lund, Burgess & Atchley, 1995; McDonald, 2000a,b; McDonald & Shillcock 2001), echoing philosophically based arguments that word meaning should be defined by usage (Wittgenstein, 1958; Cruse, 1986). Several researchers have shown that distances within such highdimensional spaces can accurately predict a variety of semantic priming data observed with human subjects (McDonald & Lowe, 1998; Lund, Burgess & Atchley, 1995; McDonald & Brew, submitted; Monaghan, Shillcock & McDonald, submitted); perhaps counter-intuitively, these context-based measures can also predict visual lexical decision Mental Lexicon 15 times for words presented in isolation (McDonald & Shillcock, 2001). Throughout the current work we will refer to the distances measured in the high-dimensional space we construct as “semantic” or “meaning” distances, with the implicit understanding that there are aspects of word meaning, as construed by linguists, philosophers and normal adult speakers of the language, that such an approach cannot capture. For instance, such a semantic definition of chair cannot directly capture what a chair looks like, or what it feels like to sit in a chair. Furthermore, although we do not employ detailed configurational information in the construction of the semantic distances, they will nevertheless also embody syntactic information3. The best alternative to such a context-based definition of word meaning has been a feature-based approach in which, for instance, human subjects generate collections of features for each word (see, e.g., MacRae, de Sa & Seidenberg, 1993, 1997), or the modeller stipulates a range of features for the classification of each word (see, e.g., Plaut & Shallice, 1993). Feature-based approaches involve arbitrary assumptions about the number and identity of the features, quite apart from raising more fundamental philosophical questions about their adequacy. The corpus-based calculations we describe below provided us with semantic distances between each word and every other word. A feature-based approach would require human judgements to be made on a sufficient number of features to capture something of the meaning of all 1733 words we use in our main study, even the function words like of and the, and yet still represent differences between closely comparable words such as chair and stool. For a set of 1733 words, this task would be an unfeasibly large undertaking. An alternative to the hand coding of semantic features is to employ a semantic distance measure based on an existing electronic dictionary (see, e.g., Harm & Seidenberg, 2001, submitted); however Mental Lexicon 16 such an approach still involves the subjective judgements of the lexicographers, and in that respect is inferior to the objective corpus-based approach we have used. Furthermore, such an approach typically cannot code function words and content words in the same terms. In the procedure we adopted, the same criteria are applied to all words and any differences between word types are emergent differences, as opposed to having been stipulated in the initial representations. We constructed a high-dimensional space from the distributional information contained in the 100 million words of contemporary English comprising the British National Corpus (BNC)4 (Burnard, 1995). Within the corpus we replaced inflected words by the corresponding lemma (e.g. walks was replaced by walk). Lemmatisation preserves the meaning shared by the inflectional variants of a word yet reduces the sparseness of the distributional data. To create a context vector representation for a given lemma, we recorded the frequency with which each of 500 “context” words occurred within a window of five words before and five words after each token of the lemma. Thus, each word type was represented by a 500-dimensional context vector. However, the reliability of such vector representations diminishes with word frequency (McDonald, 2000b); hence we computed context vectors for only the 8000 most frequent words in the BNC. We defined the semantic distance between any two words in the resulting high-dimensional semantic space as (1 - cosine of the angle between the vectors). Word pairs that have similar distributional properties (i.e. they each occur to a similar extent with the same set of words) received a low semantic distance score, whereas the semantic distance was larger between words that have divergent distributional properties. Figure 2 shows the random sample of 40 words represented in Mental Lexicon 17 Figure 1, but this time mapped according to their semantic distances from each other to show the intuitive plausibility of the measure. In summary, we calculated the semantic distance between every possible pair of words. This approach to measuring semantic distance was independently motivated: closely similar measures have been successfully used to model a range of language processing behaviours. Further, explorations of the various parameters used in such modelling (e.g. number of context words, size of the context window, type of distance measure) have shown that the approach is robust (Levy & Bullinaria, 2001); modifying the basic parameters typically has only small, predictable, quantitative consequences. The same semantic distance metric – developed prior to the current studies, and without recourse to the phonological descriptions of the words – was used throughout the studies described below. The relationship between semantic and phonological distance We tested the RFM Hypothesis, which predicts that we should find a significant correlation between phonological form and meaning even in the simplest words (know, work, man, …) that intuitively seem to embody the claim that the relationship between form and meaning is arbitrary. Our two distance measures were independently motivated and independently developed, and thus constitute a conservative test of the hypothesis. We excluded complex words (e.g., dis-claim, steer-age) from the test set (lemmatisation only affected inflectional variants); such words have an explicit, compositional structure and, despite semantic drift between derivationally related words (as in steer and steerage, for instance) it would not be surprising to find these words Mental Lexicon 18 collaborating in a relationship between form and meaning. However, even words judged to be monomorphemic by current intuitions might still have morphologically complex origins that are implicit in their form. Thus circle and circuit are currently perceived to be monomorphemic, in that they do not contain morphemes that are productive in the contemporary lexicon of English, but it would be surprising if there were no historical relationship at all between them. Similarly, a quasi-morphological relationship between meaning and form may also exist in the proto Indo-European clusters that we have referred to above and which have monomorphemic, monosyllabic members: e.g., the “pejorative” group slime, slut, slug, slag, slut, slush or the “nasal” group snore, sneeze, snot, snort, snout, sniff. In addition, within the function words there are groups that seem to constitute small paradigms, such as who, when, where, whom, which, what, or could, would, should. It is not possible to control for the histories of all the words we wished to test – reliable histories are not known for most of them – and once we have excluded currently productive morphology it is not possible to say which lexical regularities may or may not be a legitimate part of the phenomenon we wish to explore. We opted for an initial compromise: we excluded all the polysyllabic words, on the grounds that – like the circle and circuit example – they are perhaps more likely than monosyllabic words to have morphologically complex histories that are of less interest in our current study. (However, we shall return below to the relationship between form and meaning for longer, complex words.) We chose the monosyllabic, monomorphemic words in the CELEX lexical database (Baayen, Pipenbrock & Gulikers, 1995), using that database’s criteria for classifying the words. We restricted the generation of semantic representations from the BNC to the 8000 most frequent words, so as to avoid the sparse data problem attendant Mental Lexicon 19 on the less frequent words. Of this set, only 1733 were both monosyllabic and monomorphemic. Although this sample is only a fraction of an adult speaker’s lexicon, it still accounts for 63% of word tokens in the transcribed speech of the BNC – a very substantial proportion of the English in normal use. We tested the RFM Hypothesis: there should be a relationship between the phonological and the semantic distances between each word and every other word in the 1733-word set. This use of all of the available data is a critical aspect of our analysis. Previous studies of the structure of the mental lexicon have tended to restrict themselves to the near neighbours of words. This restriction is largely motivated by the coarsegrained nature of the data available from reaction time experiments with human subjects, in which it is not feasible to investigate interlexical relationships as delicate as the ones we study in the current approach. Restricting the study of interlexical effects to relations between neighbours that are one segment different from the critical word in fact ignores 99.8% of the available data. By analysing all of the available data we therefore see the structure of the mental lexicon from a new perspective – that of a comprehensive, quantitative analysis. The global relationship between form and meaning We calculated Pearson's r correlations between the phonological and semantic distances for each possible pair of words in the 1733-word sample – 1,500,778 pairs of distances. This calculation generated a correlation of r = 0.061: semantically similar words tend to be closer together in phonological space5. We have already seen that any systematicity within the lexicon of a natural language can only be very small. The systematicity we have revealed accounts for only a minute part of the total phonological and semantic Mental Lexicon 20 variation in the 1733 words we have considered. However, we will demonstrate, below, that further exploration of the lexicon yields measures of systematicity that are an order of magnitude larger than the overall figure of r = 0.061, reported above. We will also show that such measures of systematicity can account for significant amounts of the variance in behavioural data. First, though, we tested the hypothesis that the overall level of systematicity is statistically significant. We used a randomisation test (Cohen, 1995). First, each word was randomly assigned a single, unique partner in the set. Second, the correlation was calculated using each word’s own semantic context vector and its partner’s phonological form, thereby bijectively randomising the relationship between the two distances. This procedure was repeated to generate the distribution, over 1000 iterations, of correlation coefficients expected by chance. The veridical value of r was an outlier on this distribution (z = 4.2, p < .001 (one-tailed)). We have revealed a relationship between form and meaning in the monomorphemic core of the English lexicon, as predicted in the RFM Hypothesis, and we have quantified that relationship. We now consider other aspects of this overall relationship between form and meaning. In Figure 3 the bar chart represents the distribution of phonological distances within the 1733 words. This distribution is predictably bell-shaped: there are relatively few very large or very small distances and the modal phonological distance between two words is 12 feature-level edits, as defined by the edit-distance algorithm. Consider only that subset of phonological distances in which the two words were four edits apart. We plotted the distribution of the corresponding semantic distances, that is, all the semantic distances between the pairs of words in the four-edit subset. This distribution was also bell-shaped; there were Mental Lexicon 21 relatively few very large or very small semantic distances. The mean of this set of semantic distances was calculated, and is one of the points plotted in Figure 4. Similarly, for all of the phonological distances of each length, the mean of the corresponding semantic distances was calculated and plotted in Figure 4, which shows in summary form the relationship between the phonological and semantic distances. The relationship is strikingly linear, and all but monotonic across the range of phonological distances, only becoming noisier at the extremes of the distribution where the data are sparse. The more phonologically disparate two monosyllabic words are, the more semantically disparate they tend to be, regardless of the absolute phonological distance between them. Phonologically dissimilar words tend to be semantically dissimilar, but even more phonologically dissimilar words tend to be even more semantically dissimilar. In summary, we have quantified the overall relationship between form and meaning in a substantial part of contemporary spoken English. We have tested the principal prediction of the RFM Hypothesis, and shown that even at a global level there is a tendency towards coherence, in that greater phonological disparities between words tend to be associated with greater semantic disparities. In the further analyses we present below, we will analyse what lies beneath this overall relationship. We will begin by partitioning the set of 1733 words into coherent subsets. The relationship between form and meaning in a partitioned lexicon We began to identify the origins of the correlation by partitioning the set of 1733 words by the syntactic category and frequency information found in CELEX, and by word Mental Lexicon 22 length. We then used the randomisation test described above to determine the significance levels of the correlation within each subset of words. Controlling for syntactic category excludes some of the effects of known phonological cues to syntactic category (Kelly, 1996). The distinction between content words and function words is perhaps the profoundest distinction in the English lexicon; it has formal, physical and processing dimensions. We tested the hypothesis that the content/function distinction might be responsible for the observed systematicity; there are typical phonological and semantic differences between content words and function words, and we might therefore predict a significant correlation when such measures span the category distinction. However, there should not necessarily be a significant correlation between form and meaning within the two categories. We used CELEX’s noun category to designate a large subset (1509 words) of content words; note that a proportion of these nouns can occur as other syntactic categories too. In contrast, there were 99 word types designated by CELEX as function words. Table 1 shows that the correlation is significant within both categories. It is clear that the function/content difference is not solely responsible for the overall formmeaning correlation. The correlation found within the noun category shows that a relationship between form and meaning exists in that part of the English lexicon that might seem to contain the most atomic entities – monosyllabic, monomorphemic nouns. The presence of a significant correlation between form and meaning is perhaps less surprising in the function word category, given that several subsets of function words are phonologically relatively distinct: the word-initial voiced dental fricative /∂/, as in the or there, is particular to function words; in addition the wh-initial words and the -ould words seem Mental Lexicon 23 to constitute small paradigms. Against this apparent structure within the set of function words, their relatively small number militates against a high correlation. Overall, the correlation within the function words category is highly significant. If syntactic category does not drive the form-meaning correlation, then phonological length – also a salient difference between words – seems to be a good candidate for the cause of the correlation. We tested the hypothesis that the correlation was caused by length differences, in which case there should be no significant correlation within subsets defined by phonological length. To control for a possible interaction with syntactic category, we used only the large subset of nouns in the analysis in terms of length. As Table 2 shows, the correlation is predictably non-significant for nouns of lengths 1 and 2. There are only a very small number of the former, and the degrees of freedom for producing different words is very limited in the latter. However, the significance levels increase for the correlations found within the nouns of length 3, 4 and 5. There was predictably no significant effect for the five words of length 6. There is no evidence that phonological length is mainly responsible for the correlation between form and meaning. The best interpretation of the data in Table 2 is that a significant correlation exists within any subset of words of the same length that contains sufficient numbers of words, and that longer words provide more scope for such a correlation. Word frequency is a further important difference between words; it is itself associated with differences in length and with the function/content distinction, and it has processing implications. Word frequency is intimately connected with any contextbased measure of meaning, in that the more frequently a word occurs in a corpus, the Mental Lexicon 24 more opportunity it has to appear in different contexts. We tested the hypothesis that word frequency would be a significant dimension in explaining the correlation between form and meaning. When a frequency-ranked list was split at the median, the correlation in each half was significant, but the effect was stronger in the less frequent set, as is seen in Table 3. The data in Tables 2 and 3 may both reflect the fact that less frequent words tend to be longer. Longer words may provide more scope for the correlation to occur. Note that even though all the words in this study were monosyllabic, there were differences in the complexity of the onset and the coda – as evidenced in the maximum edit distance observed, that between lea and prompt. We tested the frequency-based hypothesis more stringently by dividing the words into narrower frequency bands. When the 1733 words were ranked according to frequency and divided into eight 200-word sets from the top, the correlations between form and meaning were as shown in Table 4. For the first time, we see a sporadic structure in the appearance of the correlation between form and meaning. If the relationship between form and meaning were adaptive, perhaps facilitating language processing, then we would expect to find greater systematicity within the most frequent words. These words are in a routine state of being activated and deactivated within short periods of time in normal language use, and should have the most to gain from any processing benefits. A failure to find systematicity in this important part of the lexicon would embarrass any claim that lexical systematicity is adaptive. The significant correlation within the set of the most frequent 200 words supports our claim that lexical systematicity is adaptive, and is perhaps all the more remarkable in that we have already seen, in Table 2, that the form-meaning correlation tends to be strongest in the longer Mental Lexicon 25 words. Frequent words tend to be short, yet we see a highly significant correlation in the most frequent subset. The sporadic pattern of correlations shown in Table 4 indicates that word frequency is potentially relevant to understanding the overall correlation between form and meaning. In the frequency subsets below the most frequent one, we see a trend in which the correlation becomes stronger for the less frequent words: of the three next most frequent subsets (201–400, 401–600, 601–800) the first two are little different from zero, and the third is in the predicted direction, whereas in the three least frequent subsets (1001-1200, 1201–1400, 1401–1600), two are highly significant and the other is in the predicted direction. This trend may be best interpreted in terms of the previous observation that longer words tend to exhibit the correlation between form and meaning more strongly. The significant correlation within the set of the 200 most frequent words suggested that the effect might be solely due to function words, which dominate the high frequency range. We tested this claim by dividing only the nouns into frequency sets. Table 5 shows the same profile of significance levels as Table 4, although the levels are reduced in both of the more frequent sets. The systematicity observed in the most frequent words was not due to the function words alone. Given that this systematic relationship between form and meaning seems to be pervasive in the lexicon of English, what can we say about its origins and the way in which it is mediated? We tested the possibility that the observed systematicity was due to the way in which we calculated the semantic distances. Because we defined the meaning of a word in terms of the identity of the other words that appeared in close Mental Lexicon 26 proximity to it, we may have also been implicitly recording phonological constraints on which words are likely to occur with other words; for instance, there may well be a phonetically-based predisposition against alliteration, so that tongue-twisters are avoided. If pick were one of the 500 context words, we might perhaps expect it to occur less in the context vector representations for peck, pit and pun, calculated over the adjacent words; thus, the phonological similarity between peck, pit and pun might lead to an apparent semantic similarity. This issue is not straightforward to resolve. It is not possible simply to replace the context-vector approach to calculating semantic distances, in favour of a measure that does not reflect nearby words. No other measure of semantic distance provides the coverage and possesses all the advantages of the context vector approach. It is possible to generate large-scale coverage of the words in question by deriving a distance measure from WordNet (Miller, 1990) based on the number of intervening nodes between two words, but this approach only produces relatively coarse-grained semantic distances which ultimately reflect the judgements of the lexicographer, and which are particularly inconsistent in the case of the function words. It is possible to require human participants to make judgements of semantic similarity, but this approach would only be feasible for a tiny proportion of the distances required, and would often involve psychologically bizarre judgements. The best test of the hypothesis that our reported form-meaning relationship was actually a form-form relationship is to assume that phonological constraints are stronger for words that are closer together, and to recalculate the semantic distances based on a context window that excludes the words immediately adjacent to the word being defined. We carried out this test, using a five-word window that began two words away from the word being defined. The resulting overall correlation between form and meaning fell to 0.0323, but Mental Lexicon 27 remained significant (p = .012). The fall in the size of the correlation is predicted by the fact that a word’s immediate neighbours typically have the strongest semantic relationships with that word. The survival of the correlation between form and meaning is less easily explained as a purely phonological phenomenon for this version of the semantic representations. We carried out a further study to compare the size of the form-meaning correlation for a set of 2397 polysyllabic words for which reliable semantic representations were available. These words included derived forms and debatably related words (circle and circuit), but not inflected variants. The overall correlation increased to r = .0845. This increase was predicted because the polysyllabic words embodied compositional relationships between productive or historically productive morphemes. This increase is most straightforwardly attributable to the inclusion of compositionally related words in the set: revise and return contain a clear form-meaning correspondence, as do circle and circuit. In summary, the correlation between form and meaning could be observed in relatively small subsets of the set of 1733 words. The correlation seemed to be partly predictable from the length and the frequency of the words, although the effect appeared at the high and low ends of the word frequency spectrum, possibly reflecting the fact that systematicity is adaptive, and that there is more scope for systematicity in longer words, respectively. The correlation between form and meaning was not due solely to the content/function distinction. Importantly, the correlation could not be explained by putative phonological constraints operating over the four words immediately adjacent to Mental Lexicon 28 the words when they appeared in a large corpus of English. Finally, the correlation increased predictably when the study was extended to polysyllabic words. Individual words and the rfm ranking In order to understand further the nature of the overall correlation between form and meaning, we analysed each word’s individual contribution to that correlation. For each word we took the 1732 pairs of distances between that word and every other word and calculated the correlation between the two types of distance. This procedure gave each word its individual meaning-form correlation, rfm. The words were then ranked by their rfm values. For 1732 pairs of data points, the value of Pearson's r required to reach the p < .05 significance level was approximately .037, and that for the p <.01 level was .055 (1-tailed). Figure 5 shows rfm plotted against rank position. The largest value of rfm was .189, for oh; the distribution passes 0, approximately at the word plea, and falls as low as -.115, for frank. Appendices A and B contain the first and last 50 words of this ranked list, together with the value of rfm for each word. As the graph illustrates, some 798 words have a significant (p < .01) positive value of rfm, and some 62 words have a significant (p < .01) negative value of rfm6. When the level of significance is dropped to p < .05, these two numbers rise to 985 and 118, respectively. In summary, around half of the words in our 1733-word sample possessed a significant positive value of rfm (we return below to the issue of the negative values of rfm). The exact ranking we obtained reflects the parameters chosen in defining the phonological and semantic distances; changes to these parameters will produce some reordering of the rfm ranking. In line with the rest of our study, we present an analysis of the single rfm ranking obtained with our initial parameters; a more comprehensive investigation of the parameter space would Mental Lexicon 29 probably reveal related rankings in which the behaviours of interest emerge even more clearly than in the single ranking we present here. Viewed from the perspective of the rest of the lexicon, we may think of the positive rfm value of a particular word as the rest of the words in the lexicon conspiring to reinforce the relationship between the phonological form and the meaning of the word in question. For instance, the word we is eleventh in the ranked list; it therefore has one of the strongest positive correlations between the phonological and semantic distances from itself to the rest of the words in the lexicon. If either the form or the meaning of we were discretely erased from the mental lexicon of an adult speaker of English, then the one could be partially inferred from the other in conjunction with the rest of the words in the lexicon. Thus a word, like we, with a large positive value of rfm is relatively firmly embedded within the language. In contrast, the rest of the lexicon provides no support for inferring form from meaning, or meaning from form, for the word plea, which has a near zero value of rfm. The word friend has a significant negative value of rfm, which we may interpret as the rest of the words in the lexicon tending to constrain the meaning of friend, given the form, (or the form, given the meaning) to be somewhat different to what is actually the case. That is, for the words at the bottom of the ranking, there is pressure from the rest of the lexicon for phonological change or semantic drift. In summary, although the overall correlation between form and meaning in our set of words was small and therefore accounted for only a tiny proportion of the total variation in form and meaning, when we look at the distribution of the effect and at the contribution of individual words, we see that the effect is not confined to the margins of Mental Lexicon 30 the lexicon. Around half of the rfm values were significant, and the overall effect was significant in qualitatively different partitions of the lexicon. A cursory inspection of the top of the ranked list shows that certain categories of words are prominent in that part of the list. We discuss some of the most prominent categories prior to suggesting a characterization of the ranking. The distribution of these four categories in the rfm ranking is shown in Figure 6. Editing terms. Filled pauses and editing terms, used by speakers to interrupt or to hold onto the turn, are prominent: oh (1), er (3), ah (5), eh (13), ah (44), hey (86). These words are derived almost exclusively from the 10% of the BNC that consists of transcribed speech. In many studies of lexical processing such items are marginalised as paralinguistic “noise”, devoid of conventional semantic meaning. However, their communicative importance in managing turn-taking has been acknowledged in other studies (see, e.g., Clark, 1994, 1996). Swear words. The paradigm English swear-word, fuck, appears 16th in the list – within the top 1% – to be closely followed by the other high-affect swear words shit (18th position) and bitch (25th position). Because of their affective force such words are communicatively important. Van Lancker & Cummings (1999) present a comprehensive review of research on swearing, in which the authors cite 25 monosyllabic, monomorphemic swear words. Only 16 of these words (with very minor modifications to allow for comparison with a British English corpus) appeared in our set of 1733 words, the remainder being too low frequency. Appendix C lists the words and their values of rfm, showing that 12 of the 16 words (down to and including arse) occurred in the top half of the ranking. Within the list of the 16 swear words, those with Mental Lexicon 31 higher affect tend to appear closer to the top of the list, and those with frequent nonexpletive meanings tend to appear closer to the bottom of the list. Personal pronouns. The personal pronouns cluster at the top of the rfm ranking, all but one falling in the top decile: you (2), we (11), it (12), me (15), I (24), us (26), he (40), she (43), they (82), him (114), them (167), her (641)7. Even the archaic pronouns ye(6) and thou (126) pattern with the rest of the category. (Note, in this respect, that our semantic distance measure effectively normalises for frequency; it is the degree to which the context vector is populated that is important in the measure, rather than the total number of occurrences of each context word.) It is instructive to compare the relative positions of thou (126) and the (713) in the ranking. We might perhaps have expected that the two words would both occur close together and high in the ranking because they are phonologically similar function words, or we might have expected that the very frequent the would be higher in the ranking than the less frequent thou. In fact, the occurs close to the middle of the ranking. Overall, any initial prediction that the function/content distinction would determine the position of words in the ranking is not borne out. Instead, the personal pronouns – a subset of the function words – are clearly seen at the top of the rfm ranking. Proper names. The unambiguous proper name mick appears in 7th position. Figure 6 shows the distribution of all of the words in the 1733-word set that are frequently used as names, either in their own right (e.g. john) or as contractions of longer, generally polysyllabic names (e.g. ken, tom). Many of these names are homophonous with simple content words (e.g. nick, frank); we do not distinguish between the different meanings of homophones in our analyses. The distribution of names is skewed towards the top of the rfm ranking. Mental Lexicon 32 In summary, this brief, qualitative, post hoc analysis has shown that in the upper half of the rfm ranking a number of clearly defined categories of words stand out: editing terms, swear words, personal pronouns and proper names. We have seen in the previous analyses of subsets of the 1733 words that the correlation between form and meaning exists in both the content words and the function words. The four subsets we have identified bear out the fact that there is no simple content/function distinction between the top of the ranking and the rest of it. Rather, the relevant distinction seems to involve the pragmatic force of the words in question. The four sets of words share the property of being pragmatically important: the editing terms help manage the conversational interaction, the swear words add affect to the interaction, and the personal pronouns and proper names both have pragmatically important referential functions. This observation concerning the communicative importance of the four sets of words considered returns us to the key question, which we presented as a corollary to the RFM Hypothesis: is the form-meaning structure, revealed in the rfm ranking, an adaptive one? On the basis of our informal, post hoc analysis of categories of words appearing near the top of the rfm ranking, we provisionally conclude that there is circumstantial evidence that the formmeaning correlation is adaptive. A word near the top of the list accrues the support of the rest of the lexicon in occupying a stable form-meaning position. It is adaptive, in terms of acquiring and processing spoken words, for communicatively important words to occupy such a position. This interpretation would be falsified by a language in which these sorts of words possessed a phonological form that placed them in the lower reaches of the rfm ranking; for instance, a version of English in which these pragmatically important words possessed elaborate onsets, nuclei and codas. Mental Lexicon 33 There are severe limits to such a post hoc approach to testing the claim that the form-meaning correlation is adaptive. We therefore turn to the relationship between the form-meaning correlation and a number of clearly quantifiable variables that researchers have associated with lexical processing. We will then return to the question of whether or not the correlation is adaptive. The rfm ranking and other lexical variables An informal comparison of the first and the last 50 words in the ranked list suggests a number of factors, other than pragmatic or communicative importance, that might be implicated in the ordering of the words: for instance, word frequency and length appear to differ markedly between the two ends of the ranking. We analysed the relationship between rfm and the following widely studied lexical variables taken from the MRC Psycholinguistic Database (Coltheart, 1981): age of acquisition (AOA) (Gilhooly & Logie, 1980), spoken word frequency (BFREQ) (Brown, 1984), concreteness (CONC) (Gilhooly & Logie, 1980; Pavio, Yuille & Madigan, 1968; Toglia & Battig, 1978), written word frequency (overall frequency (KFFREQ), “number of samples” (KFSMP), “number of categories” (KFCAT)) (Kucera & Francis 1967), familiarity (FAM) and imageability (IMAG) (Pavio, unpublished; Gilhooly & Logie, 1980; Toglia & Battig, 1978), number of letters (NLET), meaningfulness (CMEAN) (Colorado) (Toglia & Battig, 1978), meaningfulness (PMEAN) (Paivio, unpublished), number of phonemes (NPHN), and written word frequency (TLFREQ) (Thorndike & Lorge, 1944). Word length. There was a robust correlation between rfm and word length: NLET (r = .455, p < .001, N = 1732) and NPHN (r = -.522, p < .001, N = 1666). Words with a larger, positive value of rfm tended to be shorter. Mental Lexicon 34 Word frequency. There was a further robust correlation between rfm and the various measures of frequency, with the exception of KFCAT: BFREQ (r = .189, p < .001, N = 1132), KFSMP (r = .175, p < .001, N = 1685), KFFREQ (r = .081, p <.001) and TLFREQ (r = .121, p < .001, N = 1650)8. Words with a larger, positive value of rfm tended to be more frequent. In summary, objective measures of word length and frequency correlate strongly with rfm in the directions visible in Appendices A and B, although only word length accounted for a substantial part of the variance. We now report the relationships with the various subjectively rated lexical dimensions. Age of acquisition. AOA emerged as the subjective variable with the strongest correlation with rfm (r = -257, p < .001, N = 466). Words with a larger, positive value of rfm tended to be those words that people judge to be acquired earlier in life. Concreteness. Concreteness was significantly correlated with rfm: CONC (r = -.066, p < .012, N = 1180). Words with a larger, positive value of rfm tended to be less concrete. Familiarity. Familiarity correlated significantly with rfm: FAM (r = .166, p < .001, N = 1215). Words with a larger, positive value of rfm tended to be words that are judged to be more familiar. Imagability. Imagability correlated significantly with rfm: IMAG (r = -.079, p < .003, N = 1209). Words with a larger, positive value of rfm tended to be less imagable. Meaningfulness. Meaningfulness was correlated significantly with rfm, but only marginally so for one of the two measures: CMEAN (r = -.092, p < .002, N =993) and PMEAN (r = .105, p = .093, N = 159). Words with a larger, positive value of rfm tended to be less meaningful. Mental Lexicon 35 In summary, the subjectively rated variables all correlated with rfm. The rfm measure is objectively determined and succeeds in capturing some of the variance from the range of subjective variables. In order to provide a further basis for discussing the relationship between rfm and the other variables, we assessed how well rfm predicted published data from large-scale studies of visual lexical decision (Balota, Cortese & Pilotti, 1999) and word naming (Balota & Spieler, 1998; Spieler & Balota, 1997). Modelling word naming. We tested the extent to which rfm captured the naming data from groups of young (YOUNGNAMRT) and older (OLDNAMRT) participants, as reported by Balota and Spieler. Naming time was significantly correlated with rfm for both groups: YOUNGNAMRT (r = -.205, p <.001, N = 1589) and OLDNAMRT (r = .142, p < .001, N = 1589). The higher in the rfm ranking, the faster the word was named. Across the board, the effects were typically smaller for the older participants compared with the younger ones, although the patterns of significance were similar; consequently, we only report the analyses of the data from the younger participants. Of the other variables considered, the objective variables of length, NLET (r = .365, p < .001, N = 1589) and number of segments, NPHN (r = .265, p < .001, N = 1545) were good predictors of naming time. Partialling out NHPHN reduced the correlation between rfm and YOUNGNAMRT, but showed that rfm still accounted for a unique part of the variance (r = -.091, p < .001, N = 1542). Several of the word frequency measures were also predictors: BFREQ (r = -.065, p < .018, N = 1047), KFCAT (r = -.184, p < .001, N = 1577), and KFSMP (r = -.147, p < .001, N = 1577). Partialling out KFCAT did not affect the portion of the variance accounted for by rfm (r = -.210, p < .001, N = 1574); partialling out rfm showed that KFCAT and rfm accounted Mental Lexicon 36 for independent parts of the variance. In contrast, the spoken word frequency variable BFREQ did not account for a significant part of the variance independent of rfm: Of the subjective variables, AOA was the best predictor of naming time (r = .286, p < .001, N = 447), followed only by FAM (r = -.224, p < .001, N = 1155). Partial correlations showed that neither of these variables subsumed rfm, which continued to be significantly correlated with naming time when AOA and FAM were each partialled out (r = -.188, p < .001, N = 444; r = -.195, p < .001, N = 1152, respectively). Modelling visual lexical decision. The rfm variable’s robust role in accounting for naming time variance contrasted with its relationship with the lexical decision data. The rfm variable did not correlate significantly with either the data for the young or the older participants reported by Balota et al. (1999) (r = -.010, p = .342, N = 1598; r = .008, p = .382, N = 1599, respectively). Other variables tested, such as AOA (r = .411, p < .001, N = 451), KFCAT (r = -.391, p < .001, N = 1584) and FAM (r = -.462, p < .001, N = 1162), showed significant correlations. Discussion We have shown that the correlation between form and meaning in the English lexicon can be seen as a dimension of lexical variation that can account for reaction time data in the naming task. A substantial part of the psycholinguistic literature is devoted to the competing claims made for dimensions such as word frequency and age of acquisition, in support of different processing accounts of lexical access. This issue is complicated by methodological problems. As we have shown in the analyses we have reported of naming time and lexical decision data, a number of different variables correlate significantly with the observed behavioural data. In principle, their independent Mental Lexicon 37 contributions can be shown using factorial experimental designs or linear regression analyses. In practice, it is often problematic to fill all of the cells of a factorial design with plausible stimulus material; for instance, in comparing age of acquisition and word frequency, it is not straightforward to find low frequency words that are acquired early, and high frequency words that are acquired late. De Jong (2002) has argued, on the basis of Monte Carlo simulations, that regression studies are likely to be more successful than factorial experiments in resolving this issue. However, regression studies encounter the problem that the independent variables being compared may themselves be highly intercorrelated; in the studies we have reported here, age of acquisition correlated -.420 with concreteness (CONC), -.641 with familiarity, and -.529 with imagability, for instance. One response to this dilemma is to prioritise the different variables according to a priori theoretical principles. We suggest four such principles, below, and discuss each in turn. (a) Objectivity. We can draw a distinction between variables derived from objective measurements, such as word frequency, and those that are subjective evaluations, such as familiarity and age of acquisition. The experimenter has little control over the factors that contribute to the relatively non-intuitive judgement of, for instance, the age at which a particular word might have been acquired. Although subjective judgements of age of acquisition behave in a similar way to objective observations of when words enter children’s vocabularies, in predicting object naming speed (Ellis & Morrison, 1998), there is a danger that ill-defined factors such as the perceived importance of a word in the culture might complicate the measure, while simultaneously allowing it to Mental Lexicon 38 account for more reaction-time variance. The rfm variable is defined objectively, and may therefore be more transparently incorporated into a theory of lexical processing. (b) Generality. Some of the proposed predictors of lexical processing behaviour are less general than others. Thus, the concept of “meaningfulness” is potentially problematic to apply equally to the words table, being, and and. The principal division within the lexicon is that between function words and content words. Although there are deep distinctions between these two classes of word, both in formal linguistic analyses and in psycholinguistic terms (see Cann (2000), for a review), these two types of word are intimately blended in spoken language and the default assumption must be that there is the maximal possible shared processing before the necessary divergence occurs between the two classes. Priority in theorising should go to a variable that accurately predicts processing behaviour in all categories of words, compared with a variable that predicts processing in only one category. The rfm variable is attractive in that a value can be generated for any word – from transcribed fillers like oh and er to concrete nouns like priest or clerk – in exactly the same way. (c) Integral nature of language. Just as it is preferable for a theoretical construct in a theory of lexical processing to be able to refer, across the board, to all categories of word, it is also desirable for such a construct to embody the fact that human language has both semantic and phonological dimensions. The explanatory value of, for instance, the dimension of concreteness is necessarily limited to particular aspects of semantic processing and representation. Similarly, the dimension of word length is limited to those aspects of spoken language processing and representation in which it is appropriate to talk about the number of segments that a word contains. The dimension of age of acquisition is relevant to issues of access and storage. In contrast, the rfm Mental Lexicon 39 variable expresses the degree to which a particular word participates in the overall systematicity that characterises the mental lexicon. Phonological descriptions and semantic descriptions of words abstract away from the function of language, which is to allow speech to cause meaning to be shared by the interlocutors. The rfm dimension represents the reality of the relationship between form and meaning rather than the abstract ends of that relationship. As such, it should be accorded theoretical priority over variables that do not reflect the full domain of language processing. (d) Pre-eminence of speech. Human language emerged exclusively as a spoken phenomenon; widespread literacy is a recent cultural phenomenon, and even for most highly literate individuals the mental lexicon is more frequently accessed by speech than by text. People learn to speak and listen before they learn to read and write, and the latter activities can be expected to be parasitic on the former in a variety of ways. Accordingly, we should expect the exigencies of speech processing to have a central role in a model of language processing. The rfm variable predicted behaviour in the naming task, but not in the lexical decision task. This clear interaction by task is an important result, as it separates the rfm variable from the other predictors of lexical processing speed that we investigated, and situates the effective domain of the rfm variable in the spoken modality. It supports our claim that the rfm variable embodies the phonological and semantic role of a particular word within the whole of the lexicon, and is not reducible to other variables such as age of acquisition. Differences between lexical decision and naming predictors are typically interpreted, in the literature, as reflecting the fact that a correct lexical decision can sometimes be based on orthotactic criteria, whereas a correct naming response frequently requires the participant to have uniquely identified the word and to have individuated its phonological form. Despite the Mental Lexicon 40 fact that recognizing a visually presented word may well activate its phonology, there is clearly a less central role for phonology in visual lexical decision than in naming. In summary, we have explored the relationship between rfm and several of the variables that have been proposed in the psycholinguistic literature as dimensions along which lexical processing might be organised. They are correlated with rfm to a greater or lesser extent, and in relatively predictable directions, but the results have enabled us to argue for the rfm dimension as an important psycholinguistic variable in its own right. rfm and the neuropathologies of language The words at the top of the rfm ranked list resemble the output often observed in severely impaired dysphasics. Van Lancker and Cummings (1999) reproduce the results of a five-minute interview by N. Geshwind of EC, a right-handed adult who underwent a left-hemispherectomy. He generated practically no propositional speech, spontaneously producing the words one, three, I, no place, well, as, together with what Lancker and Cummings refer to as “pause fillers” – un, boy, well, uh, no, eh, ah, nah, um, mm, oh yes – and copious swearing in the form of the words goddammit and shit. We propose a parsimonious processing-based explanation of such behaviour, in which the lexical entries in the dysphasic brain are compromised across the board. This general decrement in lexical processing reflects an overall hypoactivation in one or both hemispheres, due, for instance, to cortical hypoperfusion (see, e.g., Hillis, Wityk, Barker, Beauchamp, Gailloud, Murphy, Cooper & Metter, 2002). This assumption is a minimal one regarding the physical location of impairment in the damaged brain. In this state, with all of the lexical entries functioning sub-optimally, it is those entries that Mental Lexicon 41 receive the greatest support from the rest of the lexicon that are able to achieve enough coherence between form and meaning to be used. Thus, particular words do not necessarily survive or become lost to use because of their physical location in the brain, or because of their connection to particular processing pathways. Rather, the whole lexicon is compromised, to whatever degree, and it is the sum of intra-lexical relationships that determines the relative sparing of particular words. It is precisely the editing terms – oh, er, eh – and other pragmatically important words that appear to survive because their form-meaning coherence is reinforced by every other word’s form and meaning, even though these other lexical entries may themselves be compromised. A partial example of such survival has been reported by Shillcock and Hackett (1998), who showed that non-fluent dysphasics retain the capacity to exploit the generalization that only function words have word-initial /∂/ in English (Campbell & Besner, 1981); even though the participants in the experiment were impaired in a way that is classically defined in terms of a compromised function word lexicon, they were still able to recruit orthographic and phonological information, in concert with the meaning of a sentential context, to pronounce a nonword, like thap, in the same way as matched normal participants. We claim that the active vocabulary following damage tends to be reduced so as to favour the words that fall at the very top of the rfm ranked list. The other words’ forms and meanings may survive in a compromised state that does not reach the required level of coherence for them to be reliably accessed, produced, or deployed. Coprolalia – copious swearing – occurs widely in the various neuropathologies of language. Frequently the swear words are among the earliest words to return to fluent production after damage of one sort or another to the language processor, and they may Mental Lexicon 42 continue to be used more prolifically after damage than before. A substantial proportion of individuals presenting with Tourette’s syndrome over-produce swear words, often with poorly produced articulation and prosody, in the context of normal speech. Van Lancker and Cummings (1999) review the relevant data and theories of coprolalia in both dysphasia and Tourette’s syndrome, concluding that an account of swearing in both conditions might involve the dysfunction of the limbic system, which – among other functions – mediates certain emotional behaviours and activities. They agree with Nespoulous and Lecours (1987) in this account of coprolalia. Thus, they claim, in Tourette’s syndrome there is a hyperactive production of what Van Lancker and Cummings call “the overlearned and emotive vocal-motor “gestures”” (p. 99) of swearing, and in aphasia the individual still has access to the vocalisations mediated by the limbic system (and possibly also facilitated by the right hemisphere of the brain). We suggest an independent, processing-based contribution to a theoretical account of coprolalia, in which the swear words have the same status as the other pragmatically important words that are preserved in the neuropathologies of language. The swear words fuck and shit appeared in 16th and 18th positions, respectively, in the 1733-word rfm ranking. Van Lancker and Cummings cite these two words as figuring in both aphasic and Tourette’s syndrome coprolalia; they also state that in other languages the equivalents of these two words appear in all groups. Thus, the paradigmatic swear words involved in neuropathologies of language appear at the top of the rfm list. These and other swear words at the top of the rfm ranking are made more salient by the rest of the contents of the lexicon. In our account of coprolalia, a generalised activity (i.e. a “tic”) in the lexicon could result in the swear words being pronounced, as a result of the salience they possess in their form and meaning relationships with all of the rest of the Mental Lexicon 43 lexicon. It is important to note that it is not just swear words that individuals with Tourette’s syndrome produce; indeed coprolalia occurs in some 25–50% of Tourette’s subjects. Fernando (1976) reports a case of an English Tourette’s subject with French parents who produced maman. Note the ma and mum occur in our ranked list in positions 8 and 23 respectively. Thus, we claim that it is a more parsimonious account of the vocal tics that characterise Tourette’s syndrome to say that they are pragmatically important words that have high salience in the systematic structure of the lexicon, rather than to concentrate on the coprolaic nature of a minority of vocal tics. In summary, the words produced by individuals with pathologically impaired language may be characterised in terms of the correlation between form and meaning. This conservative, processing account is based on the emergent behaviour of the compromised lexicon; it is more inclusive than existing theories that are restricted to coprolalia, or that ignore the broader pragmatic nature of the words that are most freely produced, although it may naturally co-exist with such accounts. rfm and proto Indo-European What is the status of the Proto-Indo-European clusters of words, such as that containing street, strip, stream, stripe, strap and stroke, which might be taken to share aspects of the meaning “long, thin”? Intuitively these words seem to be the prime candidates for a motivated connection between form and meaning in the lexicon. However, when we inspect the rfm ranked list we find that far from being the main contributors to – or beneficiaries of – the relationship between form and meaning in the lexicon, these words are spread throughout the ranking and tend to appear more in the lower half of the list. Figures 7 and 8 show histograms in which the str- and –ump (implying “curved, Mental Lexicon 44 semi-circular shape”) clusters respectively are identified by decile. These two groups are perhaps the clearest examples of putative proto Indo-European clusters of words in the 1773-word set. To the extent that such groups of words tend to be defined by shared consonant clusters, it is predictable that these longer words should appear more towards the bottom of the rfm ranked list. Our first conclusion with respect to proto Indo-European clusters in the English lexicon is that they are a marginal special case in the more general systematicity involving form and meaning. They are a special case because they are visible to the ordinary linguistic intuitions of language users. They are marginal because the number of clear groups of this kind is relatively small, and such groups as there are rarely contain double-figure numbers of words. Nonetheless, their position towards the bottom of the rfm ranking deserves comment. The words at the very bottom of the ranked list have a negative correlation between their phonological and semantic distances to other words. If a positive correlation can be seen as cementing the relationship between form and meaning for a particular word, then a negative relationship is a tendency to destabilise this relationship. Those words at that bottom of the ranked list would thus be prime candidates for the relative dissociation of form and meaning; such words should show a tendency towards changes in the phonological form of the word, and/or towards semantic drift, with the principal meaning changing and acquiring other senses. These tendencies may be offset for a particular word if it belongs to a group of words that share some aspects of form and meaning. Thus, a largely archaic English word like gloaming may only be interpretable for many English speakers because of its related words gleam, glow, glare, … (implying “concerning light qualities”). Being in a small, but appreciable group may confer some stability on a word. Mental Lexicon 45 We might interpret these data as two complementary tendencies in the relation between form and meaning in the mental lexicon: frequent words tend to rely on a very large number of other, unrelated words to reinforce their relation between form and meaning, whereas infrequent words tend to rely on a very small number of other closely related words to sustain their meaning-form relationship. Discussion and Conclusions We have presented a novel approach to understanding some of the psychologically relevant structure of the mental lexicon of English. This approach complements behavioural experiments, etymological studies, and formal analysis directed to understanding the mental lexicon, and it extends the corpus-based computational study of language in a new direction by returning to the Saussurean idea that each word is defined in opposition to all of the rest of the words in the lexicon. However, in our approach we have replaced the notion of “opposition” with psychologically and linguistically motivated representations of meaning and form, underwritten by the claim that systematicity is an organizing principle fundamental to the human brain. Our approach complements the connectionist cognitive modelling approach to understanding the mental lexicon. The connectionist enterprise is based, in large part, on the notion of superpositional storage. Despite the evidence of a degree of localisation in lexical processing in the brain (see, e.g., Pulvermüller (1999) for a recent review), it is nevertheless still true to say that any one word is typically associated with widespread activity in many regions of the brain: the same processing substrate serves the representation of many different words, and superpositional storage in connectionist modelling has been seen as reflecting that fact. Our own approach has captured the Mental Lexicon 46 aspect of superpositional storage in which the processing of each word is contingent on the processing of all the rest of the words. However, the measures and the statistics we have used have allowed us to see more clearly how each word may be embedded within the lexicon, its form being implied by the rest of the meanings in the lexicon, and its meaning being implied by the rest of the phonological forms in the lexicon. We have not explored the range of possible phonological representations. The ones we have used embody minimal assumptions about how the brain deals with phonological representations of words. There have been claims in the literature for the facilitatory influence of shared rimes (see, e.g., Radeau, Morais & Segui, 1995; Slowiaczek, McQueen, Soltano & Lynch, 2000) and for the inhibitory effect of shared onsets (Hamburger & Slowiaczek, 1996; Slowiaczek & Hamburger, 1992), both of which suggest that the temporal nature of speech is critical to an understanding of the processing of spoken words. In this study, in which we have been predominantly concerned with monosyllabic, monomorphemic words, we have ignored the temporal structure of words. Crucially, we have found significant systematicity in the mental lexicon using our first and only measure of phonological distance. We predict that measures of phonological distance that are more psychologically informed will yield a clearer picture of this systematicity, with higher correlations. Psychologically more realistic measures of phonological distance may be needed for the study of systematicity in polysyllabic words. Similarly, in this initial study we have not sought to explore the measure of semantic distance. Context-based measures of semantic distance appear to be relatively robust, but it is undoubtedly true that manipulation of parameters such as the number and identity of the context words or the size of the context window would reveal a Mental Lexicon 47 quantitative improvement in the behaviour of the measure of semantic distance, and a subsequently clearer view of the systematicity in the mental lexicon. Although Saussure’s observation concerning the essentially arbitrary relationship between words and meanings is not threatened by our studies, there is nonetheless more structure than we might initially have expected in the relationship. We have shown that there is a tendency, at the level of simple words, towards the compositionality that we take for granted at higher levels of linguistic structure. On closer inspection, this compositionality is expressed as a systematicity that operates over dimensions such as word length, complexity, and phonological content, even at the level of monosyllabic, monomorphemic words. We have identified categories of frequent, pragmatically important words as beneficiaries of this systematicity. The sequence of words in spoken English approximates to a rapid alternation between these (and similar) words and the paradigmatic content words (the nouns, verbs and adjectives). We suggest that this structure is adaptive. The core task in spoken communication is to create shared semantic representations in the brains of the interlocutors. Punctuating the movement between two content words with a word with a high ranking in the systematicity of the lexicon effectively “resets” the mental lexicon, returning its overall state to a relatively neutral position. Thus, it might be seen as adaptive to alternate between content words and words towards the top of the rfm ranked list, compared with stringing together several content words in succession. We might expect to find this same mechanism on the smallest, simplest scale when two open class words are coordinated to produce a compound, using a linking morpheme (see Krott, Baayen & Schreuder, 2001, for a recent discussion). In English, we see this in the archaic device for joining together two Mental Lexicon 48 content words with the functor morpheme /s/, as in woodsman, marksman and spokesman, but the mechanism is productive in languages such as Dutch and German. Before listing the conclusions we draw from the studies we report here, we consider the cross-linguistic implications. Our prediction is that the systematicity within the core of the mental lexicon should be a universal feature of human language. Initial studies with Spanish, not reported here, suggest a quantitatively very similar relationship between form and meaning. Our conclusions are as follows. (a) In methodological terms, we have demonstrated that it is possible to investigate the structure of the mental lexicon by analysing the relationship between form and meaning, applying conventional statistics to all of the word-level semantic and phonological data points in the mental lexicon. (b) Although the relationship between form and meaning is essentially arbitrary, we have shown that for any one monosyllabic, monomorphemic word that relationship is likely to be influenced by the rest of the lexicon. (c) In terms of the functional architecture of the lexicon, we have demonstrated a level of coherence with respect to semantic and phonological distances across the whole of the monomorphemic, monosyllabic lexicon of English. This coherence suggests a functional architecture in which the whole of the lexicon may be more or less involved in the processing of any particular word, as implied by the notion of superpositional storage. (d) The mental lexicon has developed in line with the brain’s preference for systematicity, exemplified in the many topographic maps used in solving evolutionarily earlier problems. The lexicon of English has accommodated itself to the structural and Mental Lexicon 49 processing requirements of the brain over many generations and we can detect the effects in the relationship between form and meaning. (e) The requirements of human communication also assert themselves in the structure of the lexicon. Thus, subsets of communicatively important words seem to reap the advantages of the systematicity in the mental lexicon. (f) The proto-Indo-European clusters of words that have long been taken to be examples of a structured relationship between form and meaning are less significant than the general systematicity we have revealed. (g) A measure showing how much each word individually participates in this systematicity represents a principled and modality specific psycholinguistic processing variable, that is a predictor of naming time. (h) A general lowering of activation across the whole, systematically structured lexicon provides a maximally parsimonious model of the impaired mental lexicon, and one that predicts some of the qualitative effects of that impairment. (i) The rapid alternation between high rfm and low rfm words in spoken English may itself be adaptive for switching quickly between (typically low rfm) content words. On the basis of these conclusions, we claim that the type of analysis of the lexicon we have described represents a productive strategy for future research in further exploring the general systematicity that we have revealed in the mental lexicon. Mental Lexicon 50 References Baayen, R.H., Pipenbrock, R. & Gulikers, L. (1995). The CELEX Lexical Database (CD-ROM). Linguistic Data Consortium, University of Pennsylvania, Philadelphia, PA. Balota, D.A., Cortese, M.J., & Pilotti, M. (1999). Item-level analyses of lexical decision performance: Results from a mega-study. In Abstracts of the 40th Annual Meeting of the Psychonomics Society (p. 44). Los Angeles, CA: Psychonomic Society. Balota, D. A., & Spieler, D. H. (1998). The utility of item-level analyses in model evaluation: A reply to Seidenberg and Plaut (1998). Psychological Science, 9, 238-240. Brown, G.D.A. (1984). A frequency count of 190,000 words in the London-Lund Corpus of English Conversation. Behavioural Research Methods Instrumentation and Computers, 16, 502-532. Brown, G.D.A. & Watson, F.L. (1987). First in, first out: Word learning age and spoken word frequency as predictors of word familiarity and word naming latency. Memory & Cognition 15, 208–216. Burnard, L. (1995). Users Guide for the British National Corpus. British National Corpus Consortium, Oxford University Computing Service. Campbell, R. & Besner, D. (1981). THIS and THAP – Constraints on the pronunciation of new, written words. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 33, 375-396 Mental Lexicon 51 R. Cann (2000). Functional versus lexical: a cognitive dichotomy. In R. D. Borsley (ed.) The Nature and Function of Syntactic Categories. Academic Press. Chiarello, C. & Nuding, S. (1987). Visual Field Effects for processing content and function words. Neuropsychologia 25, 539–548. Clark, H. H. (1994). Managing problems in speaking. Speech Communication 15, 243– 250. Clark, H. H. (1996). Using language. Cambridge University Press. Cohen, P. R. (1995). Empirical methods for AI. MIT Press, Mass. Coltheart, M. (1981). The MRC Psycholinguistic Database. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 33A, 497–505. Coltheart, M., Davelaar, E., Jonasson, J.T., & Besner, D. (1977). Access to the internal lexicon. In S. Dornic (Ed.), Attention and performance, VI (pp.535-555). New York: Academic Press. Cruse, D.A. (1986). Lexical Semantics. Cambridge University Press. Mental Lexicon 52 de Saussure, F. (1916). Cours de Linguistique (eds. Bally & Sechehaye) Générale. Paris: Payot. Cutler, A. (1993). Phonological cues to open- and closed-class words in the processing of spoken sentences. Journal of Psycholinguistic Research 22, 109–131. de Jong, N.H. (2002). Morphological families in the mental lexicon. MPI series in psycholinguistics. Ponsen & Looijen, Wageningen. Ellis, A.W., & Morrison, C.M. (1998). Real age of acquisition effects in lexical retrieval. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory & Cognition, 24, 515-523. Fay, D.A. & Cutler, A. (1977). Malapropisms and the structure of the mental lexicon. Linguistic Inquiry 8, 505–520. Fernando, S.J.M. (1976). Six cases of Gilles de la Tourette’s syndromje. British Journal of Psychiatry, 128, 436–441. Forster, K.I. (1976). Accessing the mental lexicon. In E.C.J. Walker and R.J. Wales (Eds.), New approaches to language mechanisms. Amsterdam: North Holland. Mental Lexicon 53 Gilhooly, K.J. & Logie, R.H. (1980). Age of acquisition, imagery, concreteness, familiarity and ambiguity measures for 1944 words. Behaviour Research Methods and Instrumentation, 12, 395-427. Gilhooly, K.J. (1984). Word age-of-acquisition and residence time in lexical memory as factors in word naming. Current Psychological Research and Reviews 3, 24–31. Gilhooly, K.J. & Logie, R.H. (1982). Word age-of-acquisition and lexical decision making. Acta Psychologica, 50, 21–34. Goodglass, H. & Kaplan, E. (1972). The Assessment of Aphasia and Related Disorders. Lea & Febiger, Philadelphia. Hamburger, M. & Slowiaczek, L.M. (1996). Phonological priming reflects lexical competition. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 3, 520-525. Harm, M.W. & Seidenberg, M.S. (2001). Are there orthographic impairments in phonological dyslexia? Cognitive Neuropsychology 18, 71–92. Harm, M. W. & Seidenberg, M. S. (submitted). Division of labour in a multicomponent connectionist model of reading: I. Computing the meanings of words. Mental Lexicon 54 Hillis, A.E., Wityk, R.J., Barker, P.B., Beauchamp, N.J., Gailloud, P., Murphy, K., Cooper, O. & Metter , E.J. (2002). Subcortical aphasia and neglect in acute stroke: the role of cortical hypoperfusion. Brain, 125, 1094–1104. Hinton, G.E. & Shallice T. (1991). Lesioning an attractor network: Investigations of acquired dyslexia. Psychological Review 98, 74–95. Howes, D.H. & Solomon, R.L. (1951). Visual duration threshold as a function of word probability. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 41, 401–410. Jastrzembski, J.E. (1981). Multiple meanings, number of related meanings, frequency of occurrence, and the lexicon. Cognitive Psychology 13, 278–305. Jones, G.V. (1985). Deep dyslexia, Imageability, and Ease of Predication. Brain and Language 24, 1–19. Kelly, M.H. (1996). The role of phonology in grammatical category assignments. In (J.L. Morgan & K. Demuth, eds.) Signal to syntax: Bootstrapping from speech to grammar in early acquisition. Erlbaum, Mahwah, NJ. Knudsen, E.I., du Lac, S. & Esterly, S.D. (1987). Computational maps in the brain. Annu. Rev. Neurosci. 10, 41–65. Mental Lexicon 55 Krott, A., Baayen, R.H. & Schreuder, R. (2001). Analogy in morphology: modeling the choice of linking morphemes in Dutch. Linguistics, 39, 51–93. Kucera, H. & Francis, W.N. (1967). Computational Analysis of Present-Day American English. Providence: Brown University Press. Landauer, T.K., & Dumais, S.T. (1997). A solution to Plato’s Problem: The latent semantic analysis theory of acquisition, induction, and representation of knowledge. Psychological Review 104, 211–240. Levy, J. P. & Bullinaria, J.A. (2001). Learning lexical properties from word usage patterns: Which context words should be used? In (Eds. Robert M. French and Jacques P. Sougné) Connectionist Models of Learning, Development and Evolution: The 6th Neural Computation and Psychology Workshop, Liège, Belgium. Springer. Luce, P.A. & Pisoni, D,B. (1998). Recognizing spoken words: The neighbourhood activation model. Ear and Hearing 19, 1–36. Lund, K. & Burgess, C. (1996). Producing high-dimensional semantic spaces from lexical co-occurrence. Behav. Res. Methods, Instrum. & Comput., 28, 203–208. Lund, K., Burgess, C. & Atchley, R.A. (1995). Semantic and associative priming in high-dimensional space. In (Eds. J.D. Moore & J.F. Lehman) Proceedings of the Mental Lexicon 56 Seventeenth Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society; Erlbaum: Hove, UK. pp 660–665. McClelland, J. L. & Elman J. L. (1986). Interactive processes in speech perception: the TRACE model. In D. E. Rumelhart & J. L. McClelland (eds.) Parallel Distributed Processing, Vol. 2., 58–121, Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press. McClelland, J. L. & Rumelhart, D. E. (1981). An interactive activation model of context effects in letter perception: Part 1. An account of basic findings. Psychological Review 88, 375–407. McDonald, S. (2000a). Environmental determinants of lexical processing effort. PhD thesis, University of Edinburgh. McDonald, S. (2000b). Corpus-derived correlates of semantic similarity. In F. J. Ruiz de Mendoza Ibáñez (Ed.) Panorama actual de la Lingüística Aplicada: Conocimiento, procesamiento y uso del lenguaje (Proceedings of the XVI Congreso Nacional de la Asociación Española de Lingüística Aplicada). Logroño, Spain: Universidad de La Rioja. McDonald, S. A. & Brew, C. (submitted). A distributional model of semantic context effects in lexical processing. Mental Lexicon 57 McDonald, S. & Lowe, W. (1998). The direct route: Mediated priming in semantic space. Proceedings of the 22nd Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society, 675–680. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. McDonald, S. & Shillcock, R.C. (2001). Rethinking the Word Frequency Effect: The neglected role of distributional information in lexical processing. Language and Speech, 44, 295–323. McDonald, S. & Shillcock, R.C. (in press). Contextual Distinctiveness: A new lexical property computed from large corpora. Behavior Research Methods, Instruments and Computers. McKenna, P. & Warrington, E.K. (1993). The neuropsychology of semantic memory. In F. Boller & J. Grafman (Eds.), Handbook of neuropsychology (Vol 8, pp. 193–214), Amsterdam: Elsevier. McNeil, J.E., Cipolotti, L. & Warrington, E.K. (1994). The accessibility of proper names. Neuropsychologia 32, 193–203. McQueen, J. M., D. Norris & A. Cutler. (1994). Competition in spoken word recognition: spotting words in other words. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition, 20, 621–638. Mental Lexicon 58 McRae, K., de Sa, V. R., & Seidenberg, M. S. (1997). On the nature and scope of featural representations of word meaning. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 126, 99-130. McRae, K., de Sa, V. R., & Seidenberg, M. S. (1993). Modeling property intercorrelations in conceptual memory. In Proceedings of the Fifteenth Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 729-734). Hillsdale NJ: Erlbaum. Marslen-Wilson, W., Moss, H.E. & vanHalen, S. (1996). Perceptual distance and competition in lexical access. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 22, 1376–1392. Marslen-Wilson, W.D. & Welsh, A. (1978). Processing interactions and lexical access during word recognition in continuous speech. Cognition 10, 29–63. Mazza, M.B., de Pinho, M. & Roque, A.C. (1999). Biologically plausible models of topographic map formation in the somatosensory and auditory cortices. Int. J. Neural Syst. 9,265–271. Menn, L. and Obler, L. K. (1990). In Agrammatic Aphasia : a Cross-language Narrative Sourcebook, Vol. 2, L. Menn and L. K. Obler (Editors), pp. 1369–1388 John Benjamines, Amsterdam. Mental Lexicon 59 Miikkulainen, R. (1997). Dyslexic and category-specific aphasic impairments in a selforganizing feature map model of the lexicon. Brain and Language 59, 334–366. Miller, G.A. (1990). WordNet: An on-line lexical database. International Journal of Lexicography, 3, 235–312. Mohr, B., Pulvermüller, F. & Zaidel, E. (1994). Lexical decision after left, right and bilateral presentation of function words, content words and non-words: Evidence for interhemispheric interaction. Neurosychologia 32, 105–124. Monaghan, P., Shillcock, R. & McDonald, S. (submitted). Hemispheric asymmetries in the split-fovea model of semantic processing. Monsell, S. (1991). The nature and locus of word frequency effects in reading. In D. Besner and G.W. Humphreys (Eds.) Basic Processes in Reading: Visual Word Recognition. Lawrence Erlbaum: Hove, UK. Morris, P.E. (1981). Age of acquisition, imagery, recall, and the limitations of multiple regression analysis. Memory & Cognition 9, 277–282. Morrison, C.M., Ellis, A.W. & Quinlan, P. T. (1992). Age of acquisition, not word frequency, affects object naming, not object recognition. Memory & Cognition 20. 705– 714. Mental Lexicon 60 Morton, J. (1969). Interaction of information in word recognition. Psychological Review 76, 165–178. Motter, A. E., de Moura, A. P. S., Lai, Y.-C. & Dasgupta, P. Topology of the conceptual network of language. Physical Review E, 65, 065102, (2002). Nespoulous, J.-L. & Lecours, A.K. (1987). Copralalique chez le patient atteint du syndrome de Jule de la Tourette. Aspects formel et functionnels. Rev. Neurol. 143, 220–224. Paivio, A., Yuille, J.C. & Madigan, S.A. (1968). Concreteness, imagery, and meaningfulness values for 925 nouns. Journal of Experimental Psychology Monograph 76(1, pt. 2). Perani, D., Schnur, T., Tettamanti, M., Gorno-Tempini, M. et al. (1999). Word and picture matching: a PET study of semantic category effects. Neuropsychologia 37, 293– 306. Plaut, D.C., McClelland, J.L., Seidenberg, M.S. & Patterson, K. (1996). Understanding normal and impaired word reading: Computational principles in quasi-regular domains. Psychological Review, 103, 56–115. Plaut, D. C., Shallice, T. (1993). Deep dyslexia: A case study of connectionist neuropsychology. Cognitive Neuropsychology 10, 377–500. Mental Lexicon 61 Pulvermüller, F. (1999). Words in the Brain’s Language. Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 22, 253–336. Radeau, M., Morais, J., & Segui, J. (1995). Phonological priming between monosyllabic spoken words. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 21, 1297–1311. Rumelhart, D.E. & McClelland, J.L. (1981). An interactive activation model of context effects in letter perception: Part 2. The contextual enhancement effect and some tests and extensions of the model. Psychological Review 89, 60–94. Seidenberg, M. S. & McClelland, J. L. (1989). A distributed, developmental model of word recognition and naming. Psychological Review 96, 523–568. Sereno, J.A. (1994). Phonosyntactics. In (Eds.) L. Hinton, J. Nichols and J.J. Ohala. Sound Symbolism. C.U.P. Cambridge. Shillcock, R. C. (1990) Lexical hypotheses in continuous speech. In Cognitive models of speech processing: psycholinguistic and computational perspectives (Ed. G. T. Altmann), Cambridge Mass., MIT Press. Mental Lexicon 62 Shillcock, R.C. & Hackett, K. (1998). Intact higher-level constraints on the pronunciation of new written words by nonfluent dysphasics. Brain and Language, 61, 143–156. Slowiaczek, L.M. & Hamburger, M. (1992). Prelexical facilitation and lexical interference in auditory word recognition. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition, 18, 1239-1350. Slowiaczek, L.M., McQueen, J.L., Soltano, E.G., & Lynch, M. (2000). Phonological representations in prelexical speech processing: Evidence from form-based priming. Journal of Memory and Language, 43, 530–560. Spieler D. H., & Balota, D. A. (1997). Bringing computational models of word naming down to the item level. Psychological Science, 6, 411-416. Stevens, S. (1956) The direct estimation of sensory magnitudes – loudness. American Journal of Psychology 69, 1–25. Thorndike, E.L. and Lorge, I. (1944). The Teacher's Word Book of 30,000 Words. New York: Teachers College, Columbia University. Toglia, M.P. & Battig, W.R. (1978). Handbook of Semantic Word Norms. New York: Erlbaum. Mental Lexicon 63 Tsuru, S. & Fries, H.S. (1933). Sound and meaning. Journal of General Psychology, 8, 281–284. Ultan, R. (1978). Size-sound symbolism. In J. Greenberg (Ed.) Universals of Human Language, vol. 2: Phonology, Stanford University Press. Van Lancker, D. & Cummings, J.L. (1999). Expletives: neurolinguistic and neurobehavioral perspectives on swearing. Brain Research Reviews 31, 83–104. Wagner, R.A. & Fischer, M.J. (1974). The string-to-string correction problem. J. Assoc. Computing Machinery 21, 168-173. Whaley, C.P. (1978). Word-nonword classification time. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behaviour 17, 143–154. Wilkins, J. (1668). An Essay towards a Real Character and a Philosophical Language. London, Sa. Gellibrand and John Martyn. Wittgenstein, L. (1958). Philosophical investigations. Oxford: Blackwell. Zipf, G.K. (1949). Human behavior and the principle of least effort: an introduction to human ecology. Cambridge, MA: Addison-Wesley Press. http://www.cstr.ed.ac.uk/projects/festival/ Mental Lexicon 64 Acknowledgements The first author was supported by ESRC fellowship R/000/27/1244. The second author was supported by a British Academy fellowship. The third author was supported by Wellcome Trust grant GR064240AIA. Mental Lexicon 65 Author Note Richard Shillcock, Department of Psychology and Institute for Adaptive and Neural Computation, Division of Informatics, University of Edinburgh. Simon Kirby, Department of Theoretical and Applied Linguistics, University of Edinburgh. Scott McDonald, Institute for Adaptive and Neural Computation, Division of Informatics, University of Edinburgh. Chris Brew, Department of Linguistics, Ohio State University Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to Dr. Richard Shillcock, Department of Psychology, 7 George Square, Edinburgh, EH8 9JZ, or to the authors at rcs@cogsci.ed.ac.uk, simon@ling.ed.ac.uk, scottm@cogsci.ed.ac.uk, cbrew@ling.ohio-state.edu, respectively. Mental Lexicon 66 Footnotes 1. A summary of some of the data presented in this paper was presented to the DiSS ’01 Disfluency in Spontaneous Speech ICSA workshop, August 2001, Edinburgh. 2. http://www.cstr.ed.ac.uk/projects/festival 3. Throughout, our usage of the word “meaning” with reference to the analyses we present might be replaced by a more conservative phrase such as “how the words are used in context”. 4. http://info.ox.ac.uk/bnc/index.html 5. The choice of Pearson’s r, with its assumption of an interval scale, was motivated by our strategy of using all the available data in our analyses. As we make clear below, we wish to test the strong claim that the phonological and semantic distances we have measured do indeed behave in an approximation to interval scales. All statistical significances were calculated using randomisation tests, thus avoiding those constraints on the use of r that are concerned with significance testing. 6. Note that, since we are actually carrying out 1733 statistical tests at this point in the analysis, we would expect some 17 of the correlations to be significant at p < .01 by chance alone. 7. The position of her, the personal pronoun that occurs lowest in that category, may reflect the fact that our analysis took no account of phonological reduction, which might turn the citation form /h\\/ into /\\/. 8. All correlations reported are one-tailed unless specified otherwise. Mental Lexicon 67 Table 1. Analysis of the correlation between semantic distances and phonological edit-distances, partitioned by syntactic type (nouns and function words). word set N r value z-value probability (1-tailed) all words 1733 .061 4.2 .001 nouns 1509 .066 4.3 .001 function words 99 .13 2.5 .006 In Tables 1–5 z-values are for 1000 randomisations, and p values are calculated directly from the modelling. N.B. N is the number of words in each set, but correlations are calculated across all the possible pairs of distances within that set. Mental Lexicon 68 Table 2. Analysis of the correlation between semantic distances and phonological editdistances, for nouns partitioned by phonological length word set N r value z-value probability (1-tailed) 1 phone 10 -.33 -1.6 ns 2 phones 164 .002 0 ns 3 phones 780 .04 1.6 .05 4 phones 463 .032 1.9 .03 5 phones 88 .18 3.1 .001 6 phones 5 .025 .1 ns Mental Lexicon 69 Table 3. Analysis of the correlation between semantic distances and phonological editdistances, for all words partitioned by word frequency (median split). word set N r value z-value probability (1-tailed) Most frequent 866 .037 1.9 .03 Least frequent 867 .069 3.4 .001 Mental Lexicon 70 Table 4. Analysis of the correlation between semantic distances and phonological editdistances for all words, divided into sets ranked by word frequency. Word set N r value z-value probability (1-tailed) 1-200 200 .13 3.3 .001 201-400 200 .0067 .2 ns 401-600 200 -.003 -.1 ns 601-800 200 .037 .9 ns 801-1000 200 -.0022 0 ns 1001-1200 200 .11 2.4 .008 1201-1400 200 .027 .7 ns 1401-1600 200 .14 3.2 .001 Mental Lexicon 71 Table 5. Analysis of the correlation between semantic distances and phonological editdistances for the nouns ranked by word frequency. word set N r value z-value probability (1-tailed) 1 – 200 200 .069 1.7 .04 201 – 400 200 -.017 -.37 ns 401 – 600 200 +.028 .60 ns 601 – 800 200 -.009 .18 ns 801 – 1000 200 .097 2.2 .01 1001 – 1200 200 .045 1.1 ns 1201 – 1400 200 .15 3.3 .001 Mental Lexicon 72 Figure 1. Dendrogram constructed from the application of hierarchical cluster analysis to the pairwise phonological distance matrix for 40 randomly selected four-phone words. Figure 2. Dendrogram constructed from the application of hierarchical cluster analysis to the pairwise semantic distance matrix for the 40 randomly selected four-phone words shown in Figure 1. Figure 3. The distribution of phonological edit distances of different length between each word and every other of the 1733 words. Figure 4. The relation between mean semantic distance and phonological edit-distance, connected by a single line for clarity. Figure 5. Individual words’ value of rfm plotted against rank position. The curve is displaced from 0, reflecting the overall positive correlation between form and meaning. Figure 6. The distribution, plotted by decile in the ranking by rfm, of (a) editing terms, (b) words that often serve as proper names for people, (c) swear words, and (d) personal pronouns. Figure 7. The distribution of the str-initial words, plotted by decile. Items that do not currently seem to belong to the string-type category are marked with a question mark. Mental Lexicon 73 Figure 8. The distribution of the ump-final words, plotted by decile. Items that do not currently seem to belong to the ump-type category are marked with a question mark. Mental Lexicon Figure 1. 74 Mental Lexicon Figure 2. 75 Mental Lexicon 76 Figure 3. Number of occurrences 200000 150000 100000 50000 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 Phonological distance Mental Lexicon 77 Figure 4 0.7 Semantic distance 0.65 0.6 0.55 0.5 0.45 0.4 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 Phonological distance Mental Lexicon Figure 5. 78 Mental Lexicon Figure 6. 79 Mental Lexicon 80 Figure 7. 14 strike (?) strong (?) straw strict (?) stress strive (?) strange (?) number of str- words 12 10 8 street stroll (?) string stripe 6 4 2 stretch strip stream strap stroke straight strain strand stride streak stray (?) 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 decile 7 8 9 10 Mental Lexicon 81 Figure 8. number of -ump words 5 4 pump (?) plump bump slump 3 dump lump jump (?) 2 1 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 decile 7 8 9 10 Mental Lexicon Appendix A The top 50 items in the 1733 words ranked by rfm. 1 oh 0.18926 2 you 0.18192 3 er 0.17949 4 and 0.17792 5 ah 0.17712 6 ye 0.17648 7 mick 0.17502 8 ma 0.17387 9 yeah 0.17118 10 off 0.17081 11 we 0.16932 12 it 0.16895 13 eh 0.16789 14 e 0.16511 15 me 0.16494 16 fuck 0.16487 17 do 0.16485 18 shit 0.16312 19 aye 0.16206 20 if 0.16114 21 hook 0.1602 82 Mental Lexicon 22 is 0.16003 23 mum 0.15841 24 I 0.15769 25 bitch 0.15769 26 us 0.15703 27 dear 0.15594 28 jay 0.15583 29 word 0.15546 30 cook 0.15519 31 bit 0.15489 32 chuck 0.15427 33 nick 0.15416 34 kick 0.15362 35 up 0.15322 36 know 0.15254 37 wee 0.15157 38 miss 0.15135 39 would 0.15121 40 he 0.15034 41 bye 0.15021 42 zoo 0.1483 43 she 0.14748 44 ha 0.14744 45 bet 0.14739 83 Mental Lexicon 46 stretch 0.14701 47 what 0.14691 48 u 0.14582 49 flick 0.14515 50 tick 0.14427 84 Mental Lexicon Appendix B The last 50 items in the 1733 words ranked by rfm. 1683 plague -0.061419 1684 waist -0.061565 1685 clash -0.062143 1686 pledge -0.062543 1687 hold -0.062664 1688 prime -0.063273 1689 grand -0.063387 1690 bloke -0.063425 1691 stress -0.063509 1692 stage -0.065427 1693 round -0.065508 1694 script -0.065714 1695 quite -0.065901 1696 tribe -0.066213 1697 plan -0.066658 1698 spoil -0.066804 1699 ground -0.066818 1700 drought -0.066843 1701 please -0.067156 1702 crime -0.069045 1703 bolt -0.069167 1704 blunt -0.069376 85 Mental Lexicon 1705 trade -0.069684 1706 blast -0.070118 1707 blame -0.070786 1708 prompt -0.071472 1709 fold -0.071703 1710 proud -0.072214 1711 quote -0.072302 1712 claim -0.072448 1713 cold -0.073592 1714 priest -0.07459 1715 glance -0.075296 1716 twice -0.076163 1717 drunk -0.076982 1718 price -0.07772 1719 prince -0.078744 1720 blind -0.079789 1721 plight -0.081207 1722 clerk -0.081327 1723 plus -0.081978 1724 state -0.084518 1725 wind -0.088635 1726 trust -0.090494 1727 strive -0.090784 1728 franc -0.09411 86 Mental Lexicon 1729 strange -0.104583 1730 bounce -0.106148 1731 friend -0.110286 1732 twelve -0.113266 1733 frank -0.114982 87 Mental Lexicon Appendix C. The swear words of the corpus and their values of rfm. fuck .165 shit .163 bitch .158 dick .137 piss .132 cock .132 hell .111 god .108 come .100 damn .095 screw .066 arse .053 ball(s) .033 lay -.025 shaft -.035 crap -.045 88