TAKING THE WRONG TURN Alex Williams (University of East London). For the ‘Planetary Politics After The Human’ Panel Millennium Conference 2012, LSE. This paper presents a critique of what has become known as the ‘post-human’ turn, with a focus on the implications such a critique has in terms of thinking global politics. It will begin by examining the most recent, and most widely celebrated faction within post-humanism, the new materialists, focusing on the work of Jane Bennett and William Connolly. This shift has some definite positive contributions to make to a number of fields within the humanities and social sciences, but it also suffers from some significant and perhaps fundamental flaws that I want to explore. These defects are rooted in the ontological commitments of the movement, and results in some problematic political and normative outcomes. It will be contended that far from a cutting edge materialism, what is offered in their writings is a pre-critical panpsychism. When read into global political situations this results in what might be termed a ‘lava lamp liberalism’, where an ontology valorising flow, the vibrancy of matter, and the agency of all things, leads to a brand of pseudo-religious piety and liberal quietism, incapable of actually analysing the material world such that we might effectively intervene in it. Moreover, this ecstatic animism rests upon a misunderstanding of the potentials of complexity theory, the chief scientific body of knowledge which informs this group of thinkers. I will suggest instead a distinct reading, which rather than invest all matter with panpsychist affect and objectal agency, takes complexity theory in an analytic, non-metaphorical direction, as the scientific-mathematical underpinning of complex global systems analysis. This is all the more crucial in a century facing such complex cataclysms as climate change, resource scarcity, continual financial instability, and the automation-led secular crisis of capitalism. It is precisely this abstract, inhuman planetary-scaled domain which exceeds and confounds any metaphorics. 1. New Materialism As summarised by Diana Coole and Samantha Frost in their recent collection New Materialisms, the turn towards post-human political and social theory arises as an attempt to move beyond the ‘Cultural Turn’.1 This switches the focus from language and discourse, in favour of a return to considering the materiality of things, a ‘new’ materialism in the sense of avoiding a simple return to Marxist economic-productive materialism. Now we might legitimately ask ourselves what the matter in new materialism actually consists of. Given the broad spread of approaches currently being collected under the heading, we must generalise a little brutally here. However, a chief scientific influence, as Coole and Frost outline, is from complexity theory. Whereas reductionist science generally builds from a bottom up stance, complexity science contends that many systems can only be understood as systems, rather than as large agglomerations of tiny particles (or other relatively small entities). As Miguel et al put it in a recent paper “if the goal of particle physics is the ultimate analysis, that of complexity science is the ultimate synthesis.”2. It follows from this that the complexity sciences are integrative, unlike physics, biology, and chemistry, whose analytical methodology implies increasingly tightly defined specialisation. Marking a shift beyond reductive Newtonian approaches, complexity science seeks to explain systems qua systems, drawing on the study of dynamics, non-linear chemistry, cybernetics, the mathematics of deterministic chaos and quantitative network analysis.3 Here systems (such as human economies, metabolic enzyme reactions, colonies of ants foraging for food, computergenerated cellular automata, and weather formations) are modelled as potentially unstable, irreversible, and radically open to perturbation. Key to this field are the concepts of feedback, auto-catalytic, reflexive causality, and emergence, described by the sociologists Smith & Jenks as “the absolute of complexity” 4. Emergence means broadly that, at the level of the system rather than at that of its component parts, new behaviours emerge which are not reducible to the behaviour of those components on their own. The whole acts in a new way, 1 Coole, Frost New Materialisms 2-3 Miguel et al, 2012, 2, emphasis added 3 Mitchell, M. (2009) Complexity, a guided tour. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 4 Smith & Jenks, 2008, 62 2 as often relatively simplistic agent-level interactions generate complex self-organising emergent patterns on a systemic level. In the recent work of Jane Bennett, in particular 2010’s Vibrant Matter, she examines complex assemblages of human and non-human entities, akin to Latourian ‘actants’.5 In a break from the traditional subject-object distinction, Bennett hymns the agentic abilities of all entities, from particles to elephants, skyscrapers to nation states, as a kind of “thing power”. Humans, like all entities, living and non-living, sentient and non-sentient, are composed of the same matter, in an univocal ontology woven into an eco-interdependent web. As Bennett puts it this “sense of a strange and incomplete commonality with the outside may induce vital materialists to treat nonhumans – animals, plants, earth, even artefacts and commodities- more carefully, more strategically, more ecologically”. 6 Human agency, on this account, is an interlocking network of humanity and nonhumanity, with the meshing of the two ever-harder to ignore. For Bennett, matter itself is eulogised as “wonderfully” or even “dangerously” “vibrant”, “lively”, and “vital”7.The vivid biological adjectives which pepper Bennett’s work are instructive, in that they dramatise the philosophical vitalism which forms the theoretical core of her project and her vision of what matter is. Her blending of Latour’s actor-network theory with NietzscheanSpinozan-Deleuzean vitalism creates an ontology of universal agency, arranged in complex assemblages, where each agent is a constant blur of becoming. Bennett is aware that a degree of opprobrium may be the result of such a trajectory, even joking that she deliberately risks “superstition, animism, vitalism, and anthropomorphism” in doing so.8 However, in seeking to defend a kind of strategic anthropomorphism, she argues that the benefits of a more inclusive approach to the kinds of entities social and political theory examines and takes account of is worth the risk. William Connolly’s most recent book, A World of Becoming, shares many features with Bennett’s work, perhaps most importantly in terms of working from a common basis in vitalist 5 Bennett, J 2010 Vibrant Matter Ibid 17-18. 7 Ibid, 13-17. 8 Ibid, 18. 6 process philosophy, with a decidedly mystical, imagistic stylistic bent.9 Connolly defends a similar account of agency to Bennett, emphasising degrees of agency, but his work attempts to knit more closely vitalism with complexity theory in thinking global social and political dynamics. To do so, he strikes up a position akin to William James’ radical Empiricism in seeking to bridge the gap between individualism and holism, a form of ‘connectionism’ where all relations are loose, incomplete, and partial, enabling the titular universal flux to take place. From complexity science he draws the ideas of pre-adaptation, redundant features within an entity or system, that following a radical shift can become decisively important; Poincare resonances, a kind of feedback generating self-organizing tendencies in a time of transition; and open systems, potentially enabling highly improbable conjunctures between different subsystemic components.10 Matter then, for the new materialists, is an all-encompassing vitalist flux of becoming. Whether conceived as interlocking network or ensembles of ‘force-fields’ and resonance, this materialism seeks to take into account the animate and the inanimate, the sapient, the conscious, and the non-conscious, the organic and the artificial. 2. Making The Wrong Turn Having briefly discussed what the ‘matter’ of new materialism is, we must now establish why this is problematic. First, it elides the hard problems of epistemology. Second, in misreading complexity theory, it often cannot explain, only describe. Third, on this basis it generates a quasi-liberal politics which is frequently a poor guide to action. First to epistemology. What Bennett and Connolly share is a focus on the question of what is over the question of how we know what is, or of ontology over epistemology. An epistemological blind spot is certainly not unique to this brand of post-humanism, being exemplified and actively embraced by many of the ontologists they draw upon (especially Deleuze and Latour). Deleuzean ontological univocity, in the form of being-as-difference, 9 Connolly, W. 2011 A World Of Becoming Ibid, ch 1. 10 collapses the distinction between thinking, meaning and being. 11 In suggesting that everything (or perhaps every thing) is real, we find little that enables us to ‘carve reality at the joints’ to engage in the critical task of discovering what is really real. In addition, the total elision of thinking and being logically results in the conclusion that everything which is, to some extent, thinks.12 This pre-critical metaphysics can rightly be described as panpsychist, in that it invests inanimate matter with degrees of cognition, consciousness, and affect. Second, the implications of a pre-critical metaphysical outlook for the role of science and explanation. Within the sciences (including quantitative and computational social sciences) complexity theorists aim to extract general principles about complex systems. In the broadest terms, classical scientific reductionism (of which Newtonian physics is the paradigmatic example) attempts to understand the behaviour of the natural world through gaining knowledge of its smallest possible component parts13. In this sense, classical dynamic systems are no more than the sum of the interactions of their elements. By contrast, complexity approaches seek to understand the behaviour of systems (from galaxies to ant colonies, from chemical reactions to human economies) through a more holistic methodology. In other words, certain kinds of systems exhibit behaviour which cannot be simply reduced to the sum of their components behaviour in a straightforward fashion. This is not to say however that the complexity sciences refuse explanatory reduction since to reduce remains essential to explanation as such, rather than mere description. Instead, this reduction rests upon understanding the mechanism-independent properties of systems-qua-systems, that is to say a relational account of how systems operate. However, this is not always how complexity has been received by the social sciences and humanities. As Connolly puts it, “the arrival of complexity theory in the physical sciences […] moves natural science closer to the concerns of cultural theory, as it surmounts reductionism.”14 What is emphasised in these accounts is precisely the elements of complexity which are most comfortable to the nonscientific scholar, shaped by recent developments in the post-structuralist tradition: the 11 Deleuze, Difference & Repetition Brassier, “Concepts and Objects” in Srnicek et al (ed) The Speculative Turn 13 Coveney & Highfield, 1995 14 Connolly, A World of Becoming, 17. 12 finitude of human knowledge, radical contingency, and the limited purview of human agency and cognition. The most serious problems affecting the world today and for the foreseeable future, are all clearly related to complex dynamic systems. But there is a significant risk involved here. When complexity moves out of a mathematical or scientific domain and into that of the humanities, frequently a set of essentially scientific principles and concepts metastasize into a form of ‘new age’ mysticism. The lack of a mechanistic determinist system has all-too-often been seized upon by those who would seek to obfuscate material reality, in favour of an ontological-linguistic performance of processuality, flow, and becoming, condensing into a mystical quietism, filled with a posthumanist piety for the inanimate and non-human world which is properly speaking mostly utterly indifferent to us. A theoretical architecture developed around metaphor, and indeed a singular, all-encompassing metaphor at that, flattens real differences in the world, occluding the real and proffering an irreductionist methodology in favour of explanatory purchase.15 Third, to the political implications of this. Bennett spends an entire chapter of Vibrant Matter examining a power blackout which occurred in the United States in 2003 which affected more than 50 million people. Whilst she is able to make some interesting observations about the interdependence of humans and their technical systems, her political conclusions are timid, singling out corporate regulation as one area in which political effort should be applied. Moreover, in spite of her apparent emphasis on distributed agency, her approach to human action is often expressed on an individualistic, liberal-ethical basis: do I elect to remain or leave or join a particular assemblage of relations? 16 Above all her political prescriptions, somewhat out of key with the otherwise affirmative lyrical prose of her text, frequently counsel the reader towards caution and hesitancy.17 Cf: Brassier, “Concepts and Objects” in Srnicek et al (eds) The Speculative Turn, 52. Bennett, J Vibrant Matter, 36-7. 17 Ibid, 38. 15 16 Whilst Connolly’s more complexity-infused approach brings together some useful conceptual stimuli, particularly the notions of abstract large-scaled socio-political resonance machines, he similarly, and surprisingly, falls into fairly mainstream liberal politics. His advice on how one might be able to construct an abstract machine to counter the particular patterns of resonance active in the United States at present gives rise to the suggestion to “buy a Prius or a Volt and explain to your neighbours what you did […] ride your bike to work more often; consider solar panels; introduce new topics at your church.” 18 This comes close to the advice of pop network theorists: do good things to those immediately around you and the effects may cascade outwards. There may of course be occasions when such actions might have disproportionately large effects. But the proximity of this counsel to the politics of mainstream, hegemonic entities like the Democrat party in the US, or even the UK Conservative party’s notion of the ‘big society’, ought to give us pause for thought here. Though Connolly is justified in critiquing the pathological negativity of much of the contemporary ‘radical’ left, the failure of the kinds of tactics he outlines makes us aware that feedback operates in multiple directions, capable of reinforcing patterns of behaviour just as much as destabilising and creating flux. Elsewhere, Connolly does examine mass movement politics, arguing that individual cumulative shifts in behaviour can generate new collective transformations, in so doing escalating pressure on corporations, states, and churches, radicalising individuals and collectives to create a new resonance machine.19 Much of this is laudable, but the language of complexity appears somewhat extraneous to a relatively conventional description of the ebb and flow of contentious political movements. This does not mean that we should necessarily reject all of the individual insights which Bennett and Connolly have. Ecological perspectives indeed should be embraced, given that climate change is potentially the most critical threat to the continued existence of humanity in the twenty-first century. But such considerations do not necessarily entail assenting to a panpsychist animism of neospiritual wonder at the flux of creation. Further, an expansive focus on multiple entities, (human and non-human) and the deployment of ideas of feedback from complexity theory are essential components of a political theory better able to 18 19 Connolly, 91. Ibid 144. understand the intricate non-linear dynamics of global change. But to be rendered workable, they require supplementation. 3. A Dark Enlightenment Bennett describes her work as an “enchanted materialism”20 and whilst this is clearly intended as a provocation, perhaps with a brutal economistic Stalinist Marxism in mind, we should consider it an entirely accurate description of new materialism. I have already outlined the difficulties such a process of enchantment entails. In its stead, I propose that we reconsider positively the place of the Enlightenment, not as myth of Westernised progress, but as process of radical dis-enchantment. To recover something useful from Enlightenment thought we will be required to reinterpret it in two directions. In light of the work of the transcendental realist philosopher Ray Brassier, we need to think the process of scientific augmentation of knowledge as a vector of nihilism which profoundly disenchants our perspective on material reality21. Moreover, in order to think a politics adequate to what might be termed the ‘moment of complexity’ we need to refurbish some of the more problematic associations the Enlightenment has taken on, specifically in reconceiving its narrative of mastery. Between these two pincers I propose a dark enlightenment of mastery after humanism. In his 2007 book, Nihil Unbound, Brassier makes two basic arguments. Firstly that the disenchantment of the world brought about by the Enlightenment and scientific investigation is an “invigorating vector of discovery, rather than a calamitous diminishment”, and hence an achievement to be celebrated as a sign of intellectual maturity. Second, that we should abandon the role of philosophy as a kind of feel-good supplement to render an essentially inhospitable, meaningless universe more amenable to our existence. “Philosophy”, writes Brassier, “should be more than a sop to the pathetic twinge of human self-esteem.” As Brassier puts it, “Nihilism is not an existential quandary, but a speculative opportunity” and therefore thought itself “has interests which do not coincide with those of the living.” 22 20 Bennett, J. The Enchantment of Modern Life, Princeton New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 2001. Emphasis added. 21 Brassier, R. Nihil Unbound. Palgrave 22 Ibid, xi We can consider Brassier’s radically nihilistic recasting of the Enlightenment as a rejoinder to the affective, irreductionist vitalism trafficked by the new materialists. Most crucial here is the distinction he draws from analytic philosopher Wilfrid Sellars of the difference between thinking and being. In Sellars’ 1962 paper “Philosophy and the Scientific Image of Man”, a theory of the relationship between the manifest and scientific images of ‘man-in-the-world’ is elaborated. The manifest image, a philosophically refined version of the manner in which “man first encountered himself” is contrasted with the scientific imaging of the human as simply a complex physical system. Whilst Sellars is a strong proponent of the reductionist scientific programme, he thinks that there remains something which cannot be easily reduced. That is to say, the very thing which offers the conditions of possibility for the process of reduction itself to occur, that element of the manifest image which is normative rationality. What Brassier extracts from Sellars is an understanding of the rational subject as a formal, abstract, fundamentally empty process. This is not to assert that humans have a special place in the world. Indeed, this viewpoint might be seen as an extension of those espoused by Connolly when he talks of differences of agentic and conscious degree. But it is one which pays more attention to the specifics of sapience, consciousness, and agency. A human is not privileged, but sapience, the ability to think, probably should be. Whilst various systems are capable of processing information of some sort (DeLanda even claiming that geological processes perform a minimal information processing23) rational thought, whilst instantiated in the same kinds of physical matter (quarks, gluons, atoms, chemicals, proteins etc) has some specific properties which must be considered in detail. Perhaps we might say that there are differences of degree, but some differences have emergent effects which are not reducible simply to degrees. Sapience is no longer the privileged domain of the human, but rather a procedure which can potentially be instantiated in substrates which are not just individual human beings (for example within social assemblages, or socio-technical ones, or even potentially artificial intelligence). 23 DeLanda, M. 1000 Years of Non-Linear History This is not to simply to argue for a traditional Enlightenment conception of the self-initiating free subjectivity of humans. Instead it dethrones the humanist conception, in a manner which is complimentary to similar decentrings from libidinal psychoanalysis to contemporary neurophilosophy such as Thomas Metzinger, as well as in the application of complexity theory in the fields of economics and society. 4. Mastery After The Human This Brassieran intelligence is quasi-autonomous, in the sense of not necessarily being in line with individual human needs. What this means is that rationality and scientific insight disclose a universe which is radically indifferent, if not inhospitable to us. The second use of Enlightenment ideas must come in seeking, within the domain of global politics, to deploy this intelligence towards achieving a new kind of mastery over this inhospitable non-human domain. As opposed to the kind of relatively quietist ethical withdrawal offered by the new materialists, we ought to engage the tools at our disposal to properly think, map, and act within complex non-linear systems. The kind of mastery imagined under a LaplacianNewtonian mechanistic scientific paradigm, an image of a clockwork, entirely deterministic universe where we might potentially predict the behaviour of the total universe and every component in it providing we possessed sufficient information about its initial state, is no longer available to us.24 But this is not to indicate that mastery is off the table entirely. Let us take, for example, the subfield of complexity science which deals in chaotic systems. Far from endorsing the post-modern perspective of the new materialists where contingency reigns and virtually any becoming is possible, instead we find a kind of deterministic chaos. This means that, within deterministically chaotic systems, we do not necessarily know precisely what will occur, but that what does occur will be drawn from a relatively limited range of possible options. Chaos, far from being totally indeterminate, has large-scaled rules. Primary amongst these is what is termed period doubling, as a linear relationship between parameters first oscillates between two values, then four, then eight, in a predictable sequence of bifurcations, until it reaches a point of chaos. At each bifurcation point, 24 Prigogine & Stengers, 1984, 7 deterministic description breaks down and only a statistical or stochastic description is now possible.25 The second large-scale feature of chaotic systems is Feigenbaum’s constant, which holds that each period doubling occurs approximately 4.6692 times faster than the prior one, resulting in a regular asymptotic approach on the way towards becoming chaotic. 26 Here we have a vision of chaos which rather than consisting in the absolutely random, is instead deterministic, giving rise to predictable patterns within an apparently chaotic distribution. Non-equilibirum, rather than delivering unintelligible randomness, actually creates order out of chaos, with occluded regularities hidden within chaotic systems. It is in light of scientific findings like these, (along with others such as Barabási and Albert’s principle of preferential attachment in network theory, Von Neumann’s concept of self-reproduction, and Holland’s notion of balancing exploration and exploitation within complex adaptive systems) that we can begin to conceive a new form of mastery. Gone is the God-like perspective of a mechanistic universe of absolute linear causality. But in its wake have come new ideas which give us the ability to begin to think non-linear interventions, deploying circular causality to generate an emergent mastery. 5. Towards a Collective Self-Mastery To do so, rather than anthropomorphise nature, we must continue along a path of disenchantment made possible by a critical epistemology keen to the distinctions between thinking, meaning, and being, generating a new conception of collective, autonomous rationality which is no longer precisely identified with the liberal humanist understanding of the human as self-initiating will. And rather than bow down before a pagan pantheon of complex forces beyond our control, hymning the boundless wonder of creative flux, we should deploy the findings of complexity science to render our socio-technical reality tractable, both to thought and to political action. In a world increasingly marked by human activity (whether in the rapidly changing climate system or our technospheric computational extended mind) politics faces a choice: shrink back into a quietist withdrawal at the sublime complexity of reality, (in the sense of being both awesome and horrifying) or use the tools which are rapidly 25 26 Prigogine & Stengers, 1984, 177-8 Mitchell, 2008, 24-9 emerging to be at our disposal to intervene within complex global systems, with all the risks and benefits associated. Together, these might begin to give us the basis from which to move beyond a liberal capitalism and towards a collective self-mastery.