The Emergence of the European Constitutional Law

advertisement
The UK Approach to the Emergence of European Constitutionalism
Repositioning the Debate: Departure from Constitutional Ontology and the
Introduction of the Typological Discussion
Report to the XVIIth International Congress of Comparative Law, July 2006
Patrick Birkinshaw and Costas Kombos*
Readers are reminded that this work is protected by copyright. While they are free to use the ideas
expressed in it, they may not copy, distribute or publish the work or part of it, in any form, printed,
electronic or otherwise, except for reasonable quoting, clearly indicating the source. Readers are
permitted to make copies, electronically or printed, for personal and classroom use.
1.
Introduction
In the seminal decision in Les Verts1 the European Court of Justice (ECJ) stated that
the European Community (EC) “is a Community based on the rule of law, inasmuch as
neither its Member States nor its institutions can avoid a review of the question whether
the measures adopted by them are in conformity with the basic constitutional charter, the
Treaty”.2 Nonetheless, the preceding confirmation of the existence of a constitutional
charter at the EC level only served the purpose of generating a persistent and intense
debate within the European legal academia that focuses on whether the EC constitutes
a constitutional order that conforms to the national constitutional models.3 The theme
* Professor Patrick Birkinshaw, Director of the Institute of European Public Law, University of Hull.
Dr. Costas Kombos, Lecturer in Law, University of Hull.
1
Case 294/83 Parti Ecologiste Les Verts v European Parliament [1986] ECR 1339, at para. 23.
2
See similar statements in Opinion 1/76, 'On the Draft Agreement establishing a European laying-up
fund for inland waterway vessels’ [1977 ECR I-741, at para. 12 (“internal constitution of the
Community”); Case C-314/91, Beate Weber v European. Parliament [1993] ECR I-1093, at para. 8;
Case C-2/88, Imm. Zwartfeld and Others [1990] ECR I-3365, at para. 16; Opinion 1/91, “On Draft
agreement between the Community, on the one hand, and the countries of the European Free Trade
Association, on the other, relating to the creation of the European Economic Area [1991] ECR I-6079,
at para. 21.
3
Maduro, M., “How Constitutional Can the European Union Be? The Tension Between
Intergovernamentalism and Constitutionalism in the European Union”, in Weiler, J. and Eisgruber, C.
(eds.), Altneuland: The EU Constitution in a Contextual Perspective, Jean Monnet Working Paper
5/04, <http://www.jeanmonnetprogram.org/papers/04/040501-18.html; Craig, P., “Constitutions,
Constitutionalism and the European Union”, (2001) 7 European lawJournal,125; Grimm, D., “Treaty
or Constitution?”, in Eriksen, E., Fossum, J. and Menendez, A., Developing a Constitution for Europe,
(Londom: Routledge 2004); Walker, N., “ Postnational Constitutionalism and the Problem of
Translation”, in Weiler, J. and Wind, M. (eds), European Constitutionalism Beyond the State (CUP
2003); Eleftheriadis P., “Aspects of European Constitutionalism”, (1996) 21 European Law Review 32;
Eleftheriadis P., “Begging the Constitutional Question”, (1998) 36 Journal of Common Market Studies
255.
1
Electronic Journal of Comparative Law, vol. 10.3 (December 2006), http://www.ejcl.org
of the debate proved to be popular, yet perplexed, due to the gradual introduction of
different parameters that constantly reposition the discussion.4 Therefore, the issue of
whether the EU can have a constitution5 has been supplemented with questions
pondering whether there is actually a need for such a constitution,6 whether there are
alternative constitutional models that exist beyond the State paradigm7 and finally
what is the relationship between different constitutional models that practically
coexist in Europe.8
Within the preceding analytical context, the task of a reporter on the emergence of a
European constitutional law as perceived from the national level is bound to be
performed in an idiosyncratic manner that reflects deeply rooted national
constitutional theories.9 The crucial matter is to balance those pre-existing perceptions
with the experiences gained from participating in the legal development of different
supranational systems (EU and the ECHR) that operate in parallel with national legal
orders.10
4
See for example the discussion prompted by the Draft Constitution: Kumm, M. and Ferreres-Comella,
V., “The Future of Constitutional Conflict in the European Union: Constitutional Supremacy after the
Constitutional Treaty”, in Weiler and Eisgruber, eds., Altneuland: The EU Constitution in a Contextual
Perspective, Jean Monnet Working Paper 5/04,
<http://www.jeanmonnetprogram.org/papers/04/040501-15.html>; Abromeit, H. and Wolf, S., “Will
the Constitutional Treaty Contribute to the Legitimacy of the European Union?”, in: European
Integration online Papers (EIoP) Vol. 9 (2005) No. 11, <http://eiop.or.at/eiop/texte/2005-011a.htm>;
Wiener, A., “Evolving Norms of Constitutionalism in Europe: From 'Treaty Language' to
'Constitution'”, in Weiler, J. and Eisgruber, C. (eds.), Altneuland: The EU Constitution in a Contextual
Perspective, Jean Monnet Working Paper 5/04,
<http://www.jeanmonnetprogram.org/papers/04/040501-06.html>.
5
Mancini, F., “The Making of a Constitution for Europe”, (1989) 26 Common Market Law Review
5933. Common Market Law Review 5933; Mancini, F., “Europe: the Case for Statehood”, (1998) 4
European Journal 29; Pernice, I., “Multilevel Constitutionalism in the European Union”, (2002) 27
European Law Review 511.
6
Weatherill, S., “Is constitutional finality feasible or desirable? On the cases for European
constitutionalism and a European Constitution”, Constitutionalism Web-Papers (ConWEB), University
of Manchester, Paper No 7/2002; Piris, J-C., “Does the EU Have a Constitution? Does it Need One?”,
Jean Monnet Working Paper 5/00, < http://www.jeanmonnetprogram.org/papers/00/000501.html>;
Grimm, D., “Integration by Constitution”, (2005) 3 ICON 193; Habermas, J., “Why Europe Needs a
Constitution”, (2001) 11 New Left Review 5.
7
Shaw, J., “The emergence of postnational constitutionalism in the European Union”, (1999) 6 Journal
of European Public Policy 579; Shaw, J., “Process, Responsibility and Inclusion in EU
Constitutionalism”, (2003) 9 (1) ELJ 45; J.H.H. Weiler, “In Defence of the Status Quo: Europe's
Constitutional Sonderweg”,in Weiler, J. and Wind,M. (eds.), European Constitutionalism Beyond the
State (Cambridge: CUP, 2003), p.7.
8
Haltern, U., “Pathos and Patina: The Failure and Promise of Constitutionalism in the European
Imagination”, (2003) 9 European Law Journal 14; Weiler, J., “Europe: the case against the case for
statehood”, (1998) 4 European Law Journal 43.
9
Preuss, U., “The Constitution of a European Democracy and the Role of the Nation State”, (1999) 12
Ratio Juris 4; Nicolaidis, K., “The New Constitution as European Demoi-cracy?”, The Federal Trust
Constitutional Online Paper 38/03, 2003, <http://www.fedtrust.co.uk/uploads/constitution/38_03.pdf>;
Huber, P., “Europäisches und nationals Verfassungsrecht”, VVDStRL 60 (2001) 194, at p. 198 et seq.
10
Birkinshaw, P., European Public Law, (London: Butterworths, 2003); Schwarze, J., European
Administrative Law, 1stRevised Edition, (London: Sweet and Maxwell, 2006); Birkinshaw, P., “A
Constitution for the European Union? - A Letter from Home”, (2004) 10 (1) European Public Law 57.
2
Electronic Journal of Comparative Law, vol. 10.3 (December 2006), http://www.ejcl.org
The starting point for reaching a balanced approach about European
constitutionalism11 is the realisation that a stage of maturity has been reached enabling
the acknowledgement of the realities of constitutional pluralism12 and constitutional
coexistence in Europe.13 Our experience with the rather different English and UK
constitution has helped to form the argument stating that it is time to consider whether
the discussion about European constitutionalism needs modification.
The nature of the proposed alteration is founded on the idea that the discussion about
the ontology of European constitutionalism is outdated and simplistic. For purposes of
terminological clarity, ontology is defined as the discussion focusing on whether a
post-national European constitutional law has emerged, either in the form of the EU
or the ECHR or something broader. It is accepted that the ontological discussion
operated as a bridge enabling the constitutional lawyer to move from the national side
to the post-national side.14 The growing familiarity with both sides makes the
exclusive projection of municipal constitutional stereotypes on our perceptions of
supranational constitutional phenomena mono-dimensional. Therefore, it is submitted
that the attention should turn beyond ontology and towards typology that is defined as
the systematic study of types of constitutions that share functional characteristics.15
From the perspective of typological analysis, the report concentrates on different
types of constitutions in Europe that are united by the fact that they share that basic
feature of being non-static and evolving.16 In American constitutional theory this
characteristic has been accurately described as ‘living constitution’17 that implies the
constant evolution of constitutional law in order to ensure its responsiveness to the
altering social needs. From that starting point, it can be concluded that a second
common characteristic is shared by European constitutions and it refers to the integral
role of the judiciary construing constitutional texts and principles. Therefore, the
judicial role can be perceived as that of a catalyst that maintains the living element of
constitutions.
For an excellent analysis of the phenomenon of constitutionalism see Weiler, J., “The Reformation of
European Constitutionalism”, (1997) 35 Journal of Common Market Studies 97; Weiler, J. and
Trachtman, J., “European Constitutionalism and Its Discontents”, (1997) 17 Northwestern Journal of
International Law and Business 354.
12
Walker, N., “The Idea of Constitutional Pluralism”, (2002) 65 MLR 317; La Torre, M., “Legal
Pluralism as an Evolutionary Achievement of Community Law”, in Snyder, F. (eds), The
Europeanisation of Law: The Legal Effects of European Integration, (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2000),
p. 125.
13
Weiler, J., “Why Should Europe Be a Democracy: The Corruption of Political
Culture and the Principle of Toleration”, in Snyder, F. (eds), The Europeanisation of Law: The Legal
Effects of European Integration, (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2000), p.213.
14
Similar to what Walker defines as “migration of constitutional ideas” in Walker, N., “The Migration
of Constitutional ideas and the Migration of the Constitutional Idea”, in Choudhry, S. (ed), The
Migration of Constitutional Ideas (Cambridge UP forthcoming), available at
<http://cadmus.iue.it/dspace/bitstream/1814/3324/1/law0504.pdf#search=%22%20S.%20Choudhry%20(ed)%20The%20Migration%20of%20Constitutional%20I
deas%20(Cambridge%20UP%20forthcoming)%22>.
15
On functionality see Tsatsos, D., Die Europäische Unionsgrundordnung, 2002, at p. 29.
16
See Birkinshaw, P., “Constitutions, Constitutionalism and the State”, (2005) 11 (1) European Public
Law 31; Birkinshaw, P., (2005) “Supranationalism, “The Rule of Law and Constitutionalism in the
Draft Union Constitution”, Yearbook of European Law, vol. 23 (2004) 199.
17
See Rehnquist, W., “The Notion of a Living Constitution,” (1976) 54 Tex. L. Rev. 693.
11
3
Electronic Journal of Comparative Law, vol. 10.3 (December 2006), http://www.ejcl.org
Approached from the aforementioned perspective, the task of this paper is to offer an
account of those constitutional developments taking place in the United Kingdom that
have an impact on the perceptions about European constitutionalism. At the same
time, the methodological approach is to reflect on those national constitutional
developments based on the influence that European constitutional law has had on
domestic constitutional law.
2.
Different Types of Constitutions and Constitutional Essentials: A European
Constitution and European Constitutional Law
2.1 The EU’s Constitution: A Ghost Constitution?
Much of the UK rapporteur’s work over the last fifteen years has centred on the
emergence of European Public Law.18 The authors take this to mean the influence of
European legal thought (EC, EU, CHR and ECHR) on domestic law.19 But the process
works the other way. Domestic law can influence European law. This may then mean
that European law, as influenced, can itself influence domestic systems so that separate
domestic systems may influence legal development in other domestic systems. It is not
likely to occur through direct influence of one domestic system on another domestic
system, although there may be odd examples of this.20 Indeed, the great historian of the
common law, Professor Plucknett, wrote about the European influence on the English
Magna Carta.21 Clearly, droit administratif has had an enormous influence on systems
of public law throughout Europe through invasion and conquest and further afield, but
the likelihood today of such direct dramatic influence is less than likely. The
opportunity for decisions in one jurisdiction to influence decisions on points of law in
another is extremely limited.22 Rather, the analysis concentrates on the cross
fertilisation of ideas and concepts.23 Compared with continental jurisdictions, English
law (and one may add Scottish and Northern Irish law) is idiosyncratic. Public law
involves both constitutional and administrative law in the English common law system.
These fields are not as differentiated as they may be in some continental traditions.
Public law itself is a recent addition to the lexicon of English law.
The concentration of European Public Law in its early years was on judicial principles
of review and liability.24 The next development was on European influence on domestic
constitutional law: specifically, to what extent was national constitutional law
influenced by European legal orders?25 The approach remained fairly general: it is easy
18
Birkinshaw, op. cit., note 10.
Ibid., at pp. 3-4. See also Birkinshaw, P., “Does European Public Law Exist?”, Queen's Papers on
Europeanisation, 2001, vol. 9/2001 Available online at <http://digbig.com/4fbqt>.
20
See e.g. R (Pretty) v DPP [2002] 1 AC 800 HL and Cf. with Pretty v UK (2002) 35 EHRR1 (decision
by ECtHR).
21
Plucknett, T., A Concise History of the Common Law, (London: Butterworth, 5th ed., 1956), at p.25.
22
See for example the decision A-G v Ibrahim [1964] Cyprus L Rep 195 (Cyprus Supreme Court) and
the therein extensive reliance on other jurisdictions and academic writings in relation to the doctrine of
necessity in constitutional law.
23
See op. cit., note 14.
24
Jowell, J. and Birkinshaw, J., “English Report” in Schwarze, J. (ed), Administrative Law under
European influence (London: Sweet & Maxwell, 1996), p.273.
25
Birkinshaw, P., “British Report” in Schwarze, J. (ed.), The Establishment of a European
Constitutional Order: The Intermingling of National and European Public Law & the Constitution 19
4
Electronic Journal of Comparative Law, vol. 10.3 (December 2006), http://www.ejcl.org
to exaggerate the claims for convergence, mutual influence and overspill, while it is
also common to exaggerate the impenetrability of divergence.26
The present questionnaire directs its attention towards a Constitution for Europe. It
reasons that because the ECJ has referred to the Treaties as a constitution or a
constitutional charter27 we now have a European constitution.28 The literature is replete
with arguments to similar effect,29 while there are even examples of national courts
accepting the constitutional character of the Community.30 Moreover, the ECHR and
the jurisprudence of the ECtHR are further referred to as constitutional law.31
Nonetheless, these judicial statements attributing to their respective legal systems a
constitutional status have been countered on the basis of a line of reasoning based on
the ‘constitutional fundamentals’.32
There is always a danger of falling into the traps of nominalism and essentialism here.
A constitution may be described as the product of essentialism when it takes the form
of one binding written document that is given special -usually a higher and entrenched status within a legal system. Therefore, it has been argued that without such a
document, no constitution can exist33 especially in the absence of a state entity and a
people.34 On this basis, those constitutions that possess the fundamental elements,
according to orthodox constitutional theory, of statehood, people and a written
document, may be referred to as formal constitutions. A constitution may be accused of
being the product of nominalism when it refers to laws, practices and conventions that
are not in one document but which nonetheless represent basic standards of behaviour
that are respected and followed by governments and actors within government to
govern both their own relationships and those over whom they exercise their powers.
Die Entstehung einer europaischen Verfassungsordung: Das Ineinandergreifen von nationalem und
europaischem Verfassungsrecht, (Nomos Verlagsgesellschaft: Baden-Baden, 2000), p. 205.
26
Birkinshaw, P., “Does European Public Law Exist?”, Queen's Papers on Europeanisation, 2001, vol.
9/2001 Available online at <http://digbig.com/4fbqt>.
27
Case 294/83 Parti Ecologiste Les Verts v European Parliament [1986] ECR 1339, at para. 23;
Opinion 1/76, 'On the Draft Agreement establishing a European laying-up fund for inland waterway
vessels’ [1977 ECR I-741, at para. 12 (“internal constitution of the Community”); Case C-314/91, Beate
Weber v European. Parliament [1993] ECR I-1093, at para. 8; Case C-2/88, Imm. Zwartfeld and
Others [1990] ECR I-3365, at para. 16; Opinion 1/91, “On Draft agreement between the Community,
on the one hand, and the countries of the European Free Trade Association, on the other, relating to
the creation of the European Economic Area [1991] ECR I-6079, at para. 21.
28
Birkinshaw, P., “A Constitution for the European Union? - A Letter from Home”, (2004) 10 (1)
European Public Law 57.
29
Pernice, I., “Europäisches und nationales Verfassungsrecht”, VVDStRL 60 (2001), 148, at p. 153;
Thym, D., “European Constitutional Theory and the Post-Nice Process”, in Adenas, M. and Usher, J.,
The Treaty of Nice and Beyond, (Oxford: Hart, 2003), p. 147, at p.166.
30
German Constitutional Court, BVerfGE 22, 293, 296: “the Treaty quasi (sic) constitutes the
constitution of this community”; German Constitutional Court, BVerfGE 89, 155, 204.
31
Loizidou v. Turkey, 310 Eur. Ct. H.R. (ser. A) at 27, 31 (1995): “the Convention is a constitutional
instrument of European public order”.
32
Grimm, D., “Braucht Europa eine Verfassung?”, JZ 1995, 581, at 586.
33
Koenig, C., “Ist die Europäische Union verfassungsfähig?”, ZEIReport, October 1999, 8 at p.8;
Koenig, C., “Anmerkungen zur Grundordnung der Europäischen Union und ihrem fehlenden
Verfassungsbedarf”, NVwZ 1996, 549, at p. 549.
34
Möllers, C., “Verfassunggebende Gewalt,Verfassung, Konstitutionalisierung”, in von Bogdandy, A.,
Europäisches Verfassungsrecht. Theoretische und dogmatische Grundzüge, (Heidelberg: Springer
Verlag, 2003), p.1 at p. 19.
5
Electronic Journal of Comparative Law, vol. 10.3 (December 2006), http://www.ejcl.org
This is not a formal but a functional constitution.35 The latter may be referred to as a
self referential constitution following the explanation offered by Neil MacCormick.36
What MacCormick means by this phrase is that one cannot look to a single document
but one can glean what constitutional rules are by examining laws, conventions and
practices that help to determine what should be done constitutionally. A set of rules
exists, either legislative or precedent based, that establishes a sense of unity and fit and
which guide and constrain the actions of officials such as judges or administrators in the
governance of the institutions of government.37
In the UK we have no constitution in the formal sense. But we nonetheless have a
constitution -- a functional and self referential one. The reason for this is that in the UK,
the following inherently constitutional questions would be resolved by an examination
of legislation, precedent or convention. What happens if the Queen fails to assent to a
Bill passed by Parliament? Or no one party achieves a majority in Parliament after an
election? What happens if there is a clash between a directly effective EU Treaty
provision and domestic legislation, or a clash between Westminster and Holyrood
(Scottish Assembly) on matters of devolved government? In the UK we possess ways
of dealing with such matters and coming to a legal and authoritative answer even
though we possess no single written constitutional document. It would be preposterous
to argue that we have no constitution in the UK. But locating its sources may require
more patience than where it is contained in one single document. It may superficially
appear messy but we know where to turn for authoritative and determinative answers.
Conversely, many have pointed out that in a written constitution a great deal of
constitutional practice and living law are not contained within the written document.38
In this looser sense of a self referential constitution it may be argued that by analogy
there is a European constitution for the EU as represented by the treaties and the acquis.
But not every item within the treaties and acquis. A European constitution would cover
those treaty articles and case law that deal with essential organisational, structural and
relational arrangements. Further similarities to the British constitution reside in the fact
that, like the British constitution, there is no developed separation of powers within the
EU. It may also be seen that the ECJ has engaged in exercises akin to constitutional
adjudication when it has given expression to the powers of the treaties which the
treaties’ existence presupposes. A very recent example comes from case law where the
ECJ decided that the EU has power under the first pillar to require MSs to establish
criminal sanctions for breaches of EU requirements. As this competence was in the first
pillar, it was unlawful to invoke the third pillar to make a Framework Directive in this
area.39
Müller-Graff, P.C., “Europäische Verfassungsordnung – Notwendigkeit, Gestalt und
Fortentwicklung”, in Scheuing, D., Europäische Verfassungsordnung, (Baden Baden, 2003), p.1 at p.
21.
36
MacCormick, N., Questioning Sovereignty (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999); MacCormick,
N., “Risking Constitutional Collision in Europe”, (1998) 18 (3) OJLS 517, at p. 529.
37
For a valuable discussion of self-referentiality within systems, see Teubner,G., Law as Autopoetic
System (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993) at pp. 3-12; Maher, I., “Community Law in the National Legal
Order: A Systems Analysis” (1998) 36 (2) Journal of Common Market Studies 237.
35
38
39
Rehnquist, W., “The Notion of a Living Constitution,” (1976) 54 Tex. L. Rev. 693.
Case C-176/03, Commission v Council, [2005] All ER (D) 62.
6
Electronic Journal of Comparative Law, vol. 10.3 (December 2006), http://www.ejcl.org
More important in a way than written constitutions and unwritten constitutions is the
question of constitutionalism - the concept that informs constitutions and which
involves features such as institutional balance, separation of powers and personnel,
control and accountability for the exercise of power in the process of governance,
equality, liberty, protection of human rights, collective welfare. Our belief is that this
concept underlies the real interest of this report. How is the question of collective
power dealt with within an institutional framework?
It has been forcefully argued that we possess constitutional statutes in the UK
(although the emphasis was English) that are of a higher order than ordinary statutes
and this status has legal consequences.40 Justice Laws held that:
we should recognise a hierarchy of Acts of Parliament: as it were “ordinary” statutes and
“constitutional” statutes. The two categories must be distinguished on a principled basis. In my
opinion a constitutional statute is one which (a) conditions the legal relationship between citizen
and State in some general, overarching manner, or (b) enlarges or diminishes the scope of what
we would now regard as fundamental constitutional rights. (a) and (b) are of necessity closely
related: it is difficult to think of an instance of (a) that is not also an instance of (b). The special
status of constitutional statutes follows the special status of constitutional rights. Examples are
the Magna Carta, the Bill of Rights 1689, the Act of Union, the Reform Acts which distributed
and enlarged the franchise, the HRA, the Scotland Act 1998 and the Government of Wales Act
1998. The ECA clearly belongs in this family.41
Therefore, according to the ruling in Thoburn the European Communities Act 1972 is
one such constitutional statute. The question of whether such measures enjoy a higher
legal status is not conclusively decided yet. The judicial engagement on this question is
an example of common law development. Although some statutes are clearly
constitutional in nature and have long been accorded a special respect technically they
were seen to be of no higher status legally than the Bees Act. Arguments that the Bill of
Rights 1689 or Act of Settlement 1701 could be impliedly repealed by a later
contradictory statute (a standard rule of statutory interpretation in English common law)
would meet with short shrift because of the respect those measures command.42
In the very recent House of Lords judgment in Jackson43 the question was asked
whether Parliament could override the constitution by, for instance, abolishing the
House of Lords without the consent of the Lords and specifically whether this could be
done under the provisions of the Parliament Act 1911 as amended. This Act allowed
bills to go forward for Royal assent even though the House of Lords had not agreed to
the measure. The 1911 Act removed the veto power of the House of Lords. For present
purposes, several of the judges had difficulty accepting that the pristine doctrine of
Parliamentary sovereignty had not been modified by the realities of political and legal
development. Parliamentary sovereignty means the sovereignty of the Crown in
Parliament as a legislator; there is no superior legislator and no one Parliament can
entrench laws binding on a future Parliament.
40
Thoburn v Sunderland City Council [2002] 4 All ER 156, at para. 62.
Ibid.
42
Lord Woolf, “Droit Public—English Style” (1995) P.L. 57, at p. 68; Laws, “Law and Democracy”
(19950) PL 80, at p. 84; Sir Stephen Sedley, “Human Rights: A Twenty-First Century
Agenda” (1995) P.L. 386; T.R.S. Allan, “The Limits of Parliamentary Sovereignty” [1985] P.L.
614; T.R.S. Allan, “Parliamentary Sovereignty: Law, Politics, and Revolution” (1997) 113 L.Q.R. 443.
43
R (Jackson) v Attorney General [2005] UKHL 56.
41
7
Electronic Journal of Comparative Law, vol. 10.3 (December 2006), http://www.ejcl.org
The former - the political development - refers to the fact that Parliament represents,
most importantly the electorate as well as historically the other estates of the realm and
must not abuse that representative position. The latter - the legal - had to take on board
the membership of the EU where the ECJ had spelt out the implications of membership
in several cases and where our sovereignty in relation to membership meant that Acts of
Parliament were no longer inviolable where they clashed with Community law.44
Consistent with ECJ case law this modification of sovereignty would apply to those
measures identified as constitutional within the UK.
Furthermore, our membership of the ECHR was not like any other traditional multilateral treaty, believed Lord Steyn in the same case who stated that the Convention had
created “a new legal order”.45 Devolution of powers within the UK had probably
modified the doctrine in terms of political reality. Sovereignty was a product of the
common law. It was subject to judicial interpretation. On abuse of power through
Parliament, Lord Steyn added: “It may be that such an issue would test the relative
merits of strict legal with constitutional legal principle in the courts at the most
fundamental level.”46 It was “[n]ot unthinkable that circumstances could arise where the
courts may have to qualify a principle established on a different hypothesis of
constitutionalism.”47 “Parliamentary sovereignty is no longer, if it ever was, absolute”
said Lord Hope.48 The ‘English theory’ is being qualified. “The rule of law enforced by
the courts is the ultimate controlling factor on which our constitution is based.”49 The
House of Lords differed from the Court of Appeal, however, insofar as the latter
believed that constitutional bills seeking fundamental change could not be affected by
the Parliament Act. Such bills would require the consent of both Houses, the Court of
Appeal believed. The fluid nature of an unwritten common law constitution and how it
can develop, quite profoundly, are both illustrated by this case.
The point is that neither the UK nor the EU contains a document that is formally
described as a constitution. But the UK has a constitution, of that there is no doubt. To a
British eye, the description of the EU treaties and acquis as a constitution may well
appear little more surprising than the description of our own self referential experience
as a constitution. The ECJ has also engaged in decision-making which is akin to the
nature of constitutional decision-making. This is clear in its judgments in Costa v
ENEL50 and Van Gend en Loos51 often referred to in the Marbury v Madison52 lineage
of constitutional case law.
44
Factortame (No 2) [1991] 1 All ER 70 (ECJ & HL) and EOC v Secretary of State [1994] 1 All ER
910 (HL).
45
R (Jackson) v Attorney General [2005] UKHL 56, at para. 102.
46
Ibid., per Lord Steyn para. 101.
47
R (Jackson) v Attorney General [2005] UKHL 56, at para.102.
48
Ibid., at para. 104.
49
Ibid., per Lord Hope at para. 108.
50
Case 6/64, Costa v. ENEL [1964] ECR 585.
51
Case 26/62, Van Gend en Loos [1963] ECR 1.
52
5 US 137 (1803). 5 US 137 (Cranch).
8
Electronic Journal of Comparative Law, vol. 10.3 (December 2006), http://www.ejcl.org
Furthermore, we cannot speak with authority on what the experience has been on the
continent but in the UK we refer to all sorts of rule-books setting out rules for an
institution as ‘constitutions’.53 It is not restricted to the rules of state institutions’
behaviour and the term covers clubs, trade unions and private societies. However there
is a clear dichotomy between those types of constitutions and constitutions of political
bodies. In relation to the EU, the description of existing treaties as a constitution may
well be received by those who are opposed to the expansion of i) the union or ii) the
powers of the union, as a complete misnomer. It will assume an immediate spectre of a
federal relationship within a federal state -- the very thing the DTC was at pains to
avoid. Powers are conferred by the states and not by the Union, they will remind us.54
In this wider sense a ‘constitution’ is a basic set of rules about governance and the
institutions of governance within a society. That society does not have to be formally
identified as a state. More usually constitution is the term used to identify the basic law
of the state. It is generally a reasonably short and concise document. Different traditions
may regard the expression more jealously and exclusively, as something which should
only be used for the nation state. This seems unavoidably associated with nationalism
or perhaps national consciousness and understandings of political concordats that are
determined to embrace and encapsulate -- and give meaning to -- the state.
As an interim conclusion, the different objections raised by the supporters of orthodox
constitutional theory aiming to establish that the EU does not have a constitution and
could never have one on the basis of current arrangements, must be countered as
outdated obsessions with rigidness and formalism. It is submitted that these arguments
are rooted in the ontological reasoning and are heavily influenced by projections of
national constitutional stereotypes on the understanding of constitutional theory. The
key for balancing the traditional constitutional theories with the pragmatic existence of
legal entities that do not fit in the state paradigm is to acknowledge the existence of
types of constitutions that share certain basic characteristics. The functional approach is
one component of the process of identification of those fundamental criteria that must
be present in constitutional phenomena and it can be concluded that the EU clearly
passes the functional yardstick. Moreover, the identification of the constitutional
criteria extends beyond functionalism to include sources of legitimisation and elements
of origins of the legal system under scrutiny. In other words, the fact that a legal system
provides for the organisation, distribution and legal scrutiny of powers is not a
conclusive piece of evidence that the system is a constitutional one. What is also
needed is an interpretation of the essence of that system that points to the existence of a
prevailing element of legitimacy associated with constitutions. In other words, the legal
system needs to be, and needs to be seen to be, legitimate in the sense that it is
associated with national expressions of the fundamental principle of the Rule of Law.
Therefore, in terms of legitimisation what is the main rule of recognition for a
constitution is whether it can be perceived to be establishing a Rechtsstaat or a system
under the Rule of Law.
See the rather unfortunate comparison by Straw, J., “Opinion: A Constitution for Europe”,
Economist, October 10th 2002, available at < http://lists.infodrom.org/jef-verfassung/2002/att-0101/01jackstraw.pdf#search=%22Golf%20Clubs%20too%20have%20constitutions%20straw%22>, at p. 4.
54
Supra, note 34.
53
9
Electronic Journal of Comparative Law, vol. 10.3 (December 2006), http://www.ejcl.org
2.2 The Draft Constitution: A Treaty, a Constitution or Both?
We turn now to the Draft Treaty establishing a Constitution for Europe (DTC)55 and
whether it provides support for the argument that the Union has a constitution that is
going to be strengthened when the DTC is ratified. The question of a constitution for
Europe was deferred when the French and Dutch rejected the draft EU Constitution in
the spring of 2005. Many commentators believe that the term constitution was
misplaced in that document.56 That it was not a constitution but a treaty, they argue, as
witness the fact that it had to be formally agreed by all member states of the union
unlike a constitution which normally is agreed by a majority of constituent parties or
bodies. The remark has been made that had the term constitution not been used in the
DTC the chances of approval in France and Netherlands would have improved
immeasurably. We leave others to comment.
In a way it is possible to argue that the rejection by two member states of the DTC and
the period of reflection that has been forced upon the Union has weakened the case for
referring to the existing treaties as a constitution and to its laws, and the case law of the
ECJ, as constitutional law. If we needed to agree a ‘constitution’ then can it be said that
we have one now? This is clear from the fact that the DTC spelt out relationships of a
constitutional nature between the Union and MSs according to the principles of
conferral of powers, subsidiarity and proportionality.57 Powers and their divisions were
set out reasonably coherently; the law-making processes were clarified and simplified.
The legal structure of the Union was simplified. The institutions were all spelt out as
legal entities including the European Council, the existence and present operation of
which bore some striking similarities to the UK Cabinet in its informality and complete
lack of legal or formal constitutional recognition/identity. Many of the aims and
objectives (rhetoric as some would have it) in Part I of the DTC can be found in the
TEU Title I and Part I of Title II but legal primacy is established by the DTC (Art I-5a).
Fundamental rights are recognised in Part I (Art I-7). This provides for recognition of
the rights in Part II under the EU Charter for Fundamental Rights (CFR) incorporated
as fully binding rights within the EU. Furthermore, the DTC must seek accession to the
ECHR binding its institutions to the Convention and the CFR within international law.
Fundamental rights, as guaranteed by the ECHR and ‘as they result from the
constitutional traditions common to the MSs, shall constitute general principles of the
Union’s law.’ (I-7(3)) Part II of the DTC includes the EU Charter of Fundamental
Rights-- a much broader framework for rights than in the ECHR. Access to justice, both
within the EU courts and member state courts is addressed in Parts I and II as
constitutional and fundamental rights.58 Finally, as well as matters relating to the
budget, Freedom, Security and Justice and foreign affairs and defence policy, the
55
Treaty Establishing a Constitution for Europe, 16 December 2004/OJ C310/01,
http://europa.eu.int/eur-lex/lex/JOHtml.do?uri=OJ:C:2004:310:SOM:EN:HTML
56
For Birkinshaw’s view on the correctness of that term for the EU document, see Birkinshaw, P.,
“Constitutions, Constitutionalism and the State”, (2005) 11 (1) European Public Law 31. See also
Huber, P., “Europäisches und nationals Verfassungsrecht”, VVDStRL 60 (2001), 194, at p. 234;
Tsatsos, D., Die Europäische Unionsgrundordnung, 2002, at p. 29.
57
For an excellent overview of the Draft Constitution see Tridimas, T.,“The ECJ and the Draft
Constitution: A Supreme Court for the Union?”, Federal Trust Constitutional Online Paper 05/04,
www.fedtrust.co.uk/uploads/constitution/05_04.pdf.
58
Kombos, C., “The Recent Case Law on Locus Standi of Private Applicants under Art. 230 (4) EC: A
Missed Opportunity or A Velvet Revolution?”, European Integration online Papers (EIoP) Vol. 9
(2005) N° 17, < http://eiop.or.at/eiop/pdf/2005-017.pdf>.
10
Electronic Journal of Comparative Law, vol. 10.3 (December 2006), http://www.ejcl.org
democratic life of the Union is addressed in Part I and includes transparency and
openness within its provisions. These are also contained within Part II as fundamental
rights and also within Part III. Under the treaties, human rights have had a chequered
history within the EC/EU.59 The story is well known and need not be repeated. The
position of such rights would be immeasurably strengthened by the EU constitution and
the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights.
We make a personal statement. The DTC strengthened the case for constitutionalism
and the rule of law within the EU.60 The existing provisions pale by comparison. The
DTC builds significantly upon the existing edifice and adds considerably to it. In
addition to the features in the preceding paragraph, consider the DTC’s protocols on the
role of national parliaments and on subsidiarity and proportionality.61 A significant
development is inevitable, given that the present structures are fifty years old, have
developed from an economic community with limited aspirations and have acquired an
ever increasing range of competences incrementally and sometimes haphazardly. The
structure has many -- but not all -- the powers of a nation state. It is a surprise that the
EC/EU has been as successful as it has. Nonetheless, to call the existing treaties a
constitutional charter creating a self referential body of constitutional law is
understandable.
We mention objections to the DTC very briefly. That it is badly drafted – that is a
matter of opinion. That it is far too large and cumbersome—there is something in this,
perhaps. Should Part III be within the constitution. These are the operative laws of the
Union; they are subservient within the framework of the constitution. Free-marketeers
would like to see a huge evisceration of everything that is not economic -- assuming
one can limit ‘economic’ in that fashion. How feasible, one might ask, is that? The
objective of such individuals is to remove all that would denote a constitution; but to
repeat, the seeds of much of the EU’s constitution are in the existing treaties.
Moreover, if the DTC is approached from the perspective of the debate examining
whether it establishes a constitution (ontological discussion), the same indeterminacy
that characterises the comparable discussion about the Treaty structure would be
present. The issues of legitimisation and of the sources of that legitimacy would be
exactly the same, even if the process of ratification through referenda in some member
States could partly counter the traditional theory’s argument of pouvoir constituent
originaire. The added complication in relation to the DTC is to be found in the chosen
title that triggers the question whether the document is a Treaty or a Constitution. The
proponents of the orthodox constitutional theory that supported the view that the
existing system does not qualify as a constitution and the supporters of the opposite
view, would maintain their claims in relation to the DTC. The submission is that the
DTC is just another type of a constitution (typological discussion) because it contains
undeniable functional constitutional elements and the necessary legitimacy in the form
of the Rule of Law. It could be seen as exactly what its title states: both a Treaty and a
59
See Carpenter v Secretary of State for the Home Department (C60/00) [2002] E.C.R. I-6279 (ECJ);
Case C-110/00 Schmidberger [2003] ECR I-5659; and respect for ‘fundamental values’ Case C-36/02
OMEGA. For analysis see Kombos, C., “Fundamental Rights and Fundamental Freedoms: A Symbiosis
on the Basis of Subsidiarity”, (2006) 12 (3) EPL 433.
60
Birkinshaw, P., (2005) “Supranationalism, “The Rule of Law and Constitutionalism in the Draft
Union Constitution”, Yearbook of European Law, vol. 23 (2004) 199.
61
Available at < http://europa.eu.int/constitution/futurum/constitution/protocol/subsidprop_en.htm>.
11
Electronic Journal of Comparative Law, vol. 10.3 (December 2006), http://www.ejcl.org
Constitution because both terms and their features are present but without having a
mutually exclusive effect. Finally, if the title is the problem, one can refer to the
German constitution that is labelled the Basic Law (Grundgesetz) and not constitution
(Verfassung); is there anyone who can justifiably claim that it is not a constitution?
3.
The ECHR as a Constitution: Constitutional Exaggeration or Just Another
Type?
The Strasbourg court and the Convention would not in traditional terms be regarded as
a constitution or constitutional court. Contrariwise, the ECtHR has described the
Convention’s role as a ‘constitutional instrument of European public order’.62 The
Convention and the jurisprudence would be regarded as an internationally accepted
bench-mark of standards on human rights protection. They are stated to march ‘hand in
hand’ with the rights on civil and political matters within the common law and they
echo back to Magna Carta officials are quick to claim.63 The British are very quick to
assert a profound influence on the ECHR. But all of these benedictions could not
conceal the fact that there was often deep resentment to the decisions of the ECtHR by
government and by judges within the UK.64 More recently Lord Steyn described the
ECHR as creating a new legal order, language reminiscent of the ECJ and the EC in its
famous jurisprudence.65
Within the UK the dialogue with the Convention has been dominated by the
incorporation of the Convention within UK laws under the terms of the HRA 1998. The
ECHR itself is not a part of our domestic law but remains a part of our international
obligations.66 The HRA does not incorporate the whole of the Convention but it does
incorporate the major rights’ provisions. Breaches of Convention rights by public
authorities (or those exercising functions of a public nature) are unlawful leading to
remedies within domestic law.67 This has led to some interesting case law concerning
the effect of convention rights under the HRA and their relation to other norms of
international law.68 But the impact of the HRA and convention rights is determined by
the constitutional constraints and restraints of the UK.
Loizidou v. Turkey, 310 Eur. Ct. H.R. (ser. A) at 27, 31 (1995): “the Convention is a constitutional
instrument of European public order”.
63
McQuillan [1995] 4 All ER 400; Rights Brought Home: The Human Rights Bill Cm 3782 (1997
HMSO).
64
Hunt, H., Using Human Rights Law in English Courts (Oxford: Hart, 1997).
65
R (Jackson) v Att. Gen [2005] UKHL 56, (2005) The Times 14 October.
66
Blackburn v. Attorney-General [1971] 2 All ER 1380; McWhirter v. Attorney-General [1972] CMLR
882; R (On the Application of Al-Jeddah) v. Secretary of State for Defence [2005] EWHC 1809.
67
On the definition of public bodies see: Poplar Housing & Regeneration Community Association Ltd
v. Donoghue [2001] EWCA Civ 585, [2002] QB 548; Aston Cantlow and Wilmcote with Billesley
Parochial Church Council v. Wallbank [2003] UKHL 37, [2004] 1 AC 586; R (On the Application of
Heather) v. Leonard Cheshire Foundation [2002] EWCA Civ 366, [2002] 2 All ER 936; Marcic v.
Thames Water [2003] UKHL 66, [2004] 1 All ER 135.
68
See Al Skeini [2005] 2 WLR 1401and Al Jedda [2006] EWCA Civ. 327 raising questions about the
extra-territoriality of the HRA 1998 in Iraq and the precise meaning (and limits) of ‘Convention right’.
See further R (Quark Fishing Ltd) v Foreign Secretary [2005] UKHK 57: rights which are
unenforceable in Strasbourg are not enforceable in England under the Human Rights Act.
62
12
Electronic Journal of Comparative Law, vol. 10.3 (December 2006), http://www.ejcl.org
Convention rights are those set out in s.1 and Sched 1. The Act under section 2 makes it
unlawful for public authorities to act in a way which is incompatible with the
‘Convention rights’ as scheduled. Under section 3 (1) HRA 1998 when determining any
question in relation to a Convention right, the domestic court ‘must take into account’
any jurisprudence of the ECtHR (and decisions or opinions of the former Commission
and the Committee of Ministers). The instruction is to take it into account -- not to
regard it as binding.69 ‘Public authorities’ is defined widely in section 6 to include all
agents of central and local government and the police, while the definition includes
courts and tribunals themselves. This is very important where those bodies fail to
protect human rights and in the case of Articles 8 and 10 ECHR has been responsible
for the courts applying the articles horizontally between private parties, i.e. the press
and individuals.70 The question of human rights law may be raised in any court. The
Government preferred the rights to be invoked as they arose ‘rather than confining their
consideration to some kind of constitutional court’. This was because there was no
constitutional court as such. The Constitutional Reform Act 2005 has now established a
“Supreme Court” which will replace the Appellate Committee of the House of Lords.
There has been a trend towards a more law based constitution in the UK and the 2005
Act is the latest example.
If an individual wishes to bring a breach of a Convention right directly to the courts,
s/he will be able to do so; it creates a discrete right of action. Where Convention points
are raised on judicial review applications, locus standi will have to be established. The
test of standing in all cases is whether the person seeking relief is a ‘victim’ of a breach
of a convention right.71 Courts or tribunals will be able to award whatever remedies lie
within their normal powers: crucially here in the case of the courts damages and awards
of injunctions, but breaches of convention rights will not be criminal offences.72
Awards of damages on Convention grounds will take account of principles developed
by the ECtHR in awarding compensation so that domestic awards will be
‘equivalent’.73
The HRA does not allow courts to set aside acts of Parliament where there is a breach
of the Convention by a legislative provision, either in primary or secondary legislation.
The Consultation Paper on a new Supreme Court in 2003 clearly distinguished the
jurisdiction of the proposed new UK Supreme Court from the powers of the US
Supreme Court and the German Federal Constitutional Court.74 Higher courts will be
able to make a ‘formal declaration’ that a provision in a statute is incompatible with
Convention rights under section 4. In Ghaidan v Mendoza Lord Steyn noted that fifteen
declarations of incompatibility had been awarded although five had been overturned on
appeal.75 The number is now seventeen. Their subject matter has very often been of the
highest importance. One of the most dramatic concerned the declaration by the House
69
On the interpretative obligation see Bellinger v. Bellinger [2003] UKHL 21, [2003] 2 WLR 1174; R
v. A (No. 2) [2001] UKHL 25, [2002] 1 AC 509; Re S (Minors) [2002] UKHL 10, [2002] 2 AC 291
Sheffield City Council v. Smart [2002] EWCACiv 4, [2002] HLR 34.
70
Douglas v Hello! Ltd (No.1) [2001] 2 All E.R. 289 (CA); Campbell v Mirror Group Newspapers Ltd
[2004] 2 All E.R. 995(HL).
71
Under section 7 HRA 1998.
72
Under section 8 HRA 1998.
73
This has prompted a great deal of discussion. See e.g. R v Secretary of State for the Home
Department ex p Greenfield [2005] UKHL 14.
74
Constitutional Reform: “A Supreme Court for the United Kingdom”, CP11/03 (July 2003), para 20.
75
[2004] UKHL 30 paras 49-50.
13
Electronic Journal of Comparative Law, vol. 10.3 (December 2006), http://www.ejcl.org
of Lords in December 2004 that the derogation and provisions allowing detention
without trial of foreign nationals who were certified as being suspected by the Secretary
of State of being terrorists under the Anti-terrorism, Crime and Security Act 2001
section 23 were incompatible with Convention rights. The measures were
disproportionate and discriminatory. Specifically, they were in breach of Arts 5 and 14
ECHR.76 To the argument of the Attorney General on behalf of the government that the
judges were acting contrary to the exigencies of democratic government, Lord Bingham
said ‘The 1998 Act gives the courts a very specific, wholly democratic, mandate.’77
No direct effect will be given to Convention rights over domestic laws as in the case of
the EU and the ECHR as incorporated by the HRA will not be entrenched. Under
section 3 legislation will be interpreted so as to be compatible with the Convention ‘so
far as possible to do so’. If compatibility is clearly impossible, then consistent
interpretation cannot be achieved and a statute’s meaning must not be distorted.78 But
where more than one interpretation is possible, the interpretation which is consistent
with the Convention should be adopted. This rule of construction, which applies to past
and future legislation, has been used with extraordinary flexibility by the courts.79
The reason why the Government did not wish to give a power to the judiciary to strike
down primary legislation was because the government wished to maintain the
overarching practice and theory of Parliamentary Sovereignty:
To make provision in the Bill for the courts to set aside Acts of Parliament would confer on the
judiciary a general power over the decisions of Parliament which under our present constitutional
arrangements they do not possess, and would be likely on occasions to draw the judiciary into
serious conflict with Parliament. There is no evidence to suggest that they desire this power, nor
that the public wish them to have it. Certainly, this Government has no mandate for any such
change.80
The HRA allows for a ‘fast track’ procedure in section 10 and schedule 2 to amend
legislation by Order approved by both Houses to ensure it conforms with the Human
Rights Act as enacted. Where there is a case of emergency then both Houses will be
notified but they do not give its approval. By this means Parliamentary Sovereignty is
maintained.
Acts of the Scottish Assembly will have to conform with the Convention otherwise they
will be incompetent and invalid; disputes will be referred to the Judicial Committee of
the Privy Council where the matter is not resolved by Scottish courts and draft bills of
the Scottish Parliament may be referred to the Privy Council for preliminary rulings on
compliance with the Convention as well as EU law. In future they will go to the new
Supreme Court. One court and not two will deal with devolution matters.81
Ministers must provide a statement on Bills presented to the UK Parliament stating that
the Bill complies with obligations under the Convention. Where this might not be
possible, Ministers would explain the position in Parliamentary proceedings of the Bill.
76
A (FC) and Others (FC) v Secretary of State [2004] UKHL 56. There was also a violation of Art 15.
Ibid., at para. 42.
78
Wilson v First County Trust [2001] 3 All ER 229.
79
See eg R v A No 2 [2001] UKHL 25.
80
Bringing Rights Home White Paper Cm 3782 para. 2.13.
81
This has caused conflicting decisions based on judicial nationality: HM Advocate v R [2002] UKPC
D5 and cf. Att Gen’s Reference No 2 of 2001 [2003] UKHL 68.
77
14
Electronic Journal of Comparative Law, vol. 10.3 (December 2006), http://www.ejcl.org
Guidance on compliance with the Human Rights Act obligations will be revised to
assist departments and drafters of Bills and regulations on the Convention’s
requirements. There was a delay in the HRA coming into effect for two years while all
UK judges at every level underwent human rights training. The HRA is within the
responsibility of the Department for Constitutional Affairs which is headed by the Lord
Chancellor.82 The Act makes provision for derogations and reservations from the
Convention and its Protocols.
In the 1997 White Paper the Government explained why the model of incorporation
introduced by section 2(1) European Communities Act 1972 (ECA) was not going to be
employed. ECA was the product of a treaty requirement involving membership of the
then EEC under which Member States must ‘give priority to directly effective EC law
in their own legal systems.’83 The government emphasised the problems experienced
with the ECHR. There was considerable delay. The ‘foreign’ quality of the ECHR was
also emphasised in so far as its provisions were not enforced through British courts.
More constructively, the government indicated that incorporation would confer a
distinct benefit. The HRA would enable British judges to ‘make a distinctively British
contribution to the development of the human rights of Europe’.84 It may even come to
pass that their example of human rights jurisprudence may be drawn upon and followed
by other judges in other jurisdictions. The influence of the House of Lords judgment in
what became Pretty v UK85 has been openly acknowledged by the Irish judge on the
ECtHR. There is ample evidence to show that the Charter of Fundamental Rights has
been used by English and other MS courts to influence, not dictate, domestic
decisions.86 The Government accepted that the manner in which the Convention had
been treated by UK laws in the past had not afforded appropriate emphasis to the
contribution it should make in protecting human rights.
The HRA has invigorated the human rights debate in the UK. But incorporation has not
been without critics who have argued that the HRA will encourage the judges to move
into the overtly political arena and has encouraged them to pronounce political
decisions on controversial subjects as if they were elected. Lord Bingham’s comments
were referred to above. The Act was given by Parliament and provides a legitimate and
proper role for judicial protection of human rights in a democratic framework. It has
strengthened the judicial role in an enterprise in which Parliament and the government
also have vital roles to perform. Stories of the HRA’s excesses in protecting the
worthless, the self-centred, the querulous abound in the anti European press. In 2006
David Cameron, the Leader of the Opposition, spoke of a review of the HRA 1998 if he
came to power and the adoption of a new Bill of Rights that would be reflective of the
values of the British people similar to the manner the German Basic Law reflects
national values.87 Nonetheless, repeal of the measure would probably prove virtually
82
This department, to all intents and purposes, is a Ministry of Justice.
Para 2.12
84
WP para. 1.14.
85
(2002) EHRR 1.
86
See e.g. R v Secretary of State HD ex p Howard League [2002] EWHC (Admin) 2497.
87
Morris, N., “Cameron Pledges to Scrap the Human Rights Act in Constitutional Review”, The
Independent, 26th June 2006, p. 26, available at
<http://news.independent.co.uk/uk/politics/article1096457.ece>. Cameron’s analysis was criticised by
German lawyers for inaccuracy.
83
15
Electronic Journal of Comparative Law, vol. 10.3 (December 2006), http://www.ejcl.org
impossible. And British judges under European influence have developed a human
rights consciousness. The jurisprudence has become a part of the common law.88
The Convention, it is argued, is unlike any traditional multi-lateral international treaty
where governments’ agree to respect human rights. The most recent suggestion
concerning such treaties arose in relation to agreements between the UK and receiving
states who undertook not to torture or subject to inhumane treatment those deported by
the UK to those states. This was to circumvent the limitations imposed by Art 3 ECHR
-- limitations which the UK government in its war on terror virulently opposes. The
ECHR gives rights to individuals although states have to agree to individual rights of
petition. But as Lord Steyn implies, the Convention by itself, remained a part of our
international obligations. The UK traditionally has a fairly rigid approach to
international law based on dualism. But the rigidity of this approach is subject to
change. By itself, the Convention would set an impressive and international standard of
human rights protection which had an influence on British public life and governance,
an influence that was increasing and considerably so. The UK government would not
wish to be seen in open defiance of the ECtHR’s rulings. But these rulings were not
binding on UK judges. They were having an increasing influence on judicial decisionmaking; and legislation increasingly had to introduce necessary reforms in e.g. privacy
protection and judicial protection under the ECHR’s influence. Before 2000, there were
increasing signs that the common law was developing a human rights consciousness
where new common law philosophy was inspiring a greater sensitivity to human
rights.89 Signs of this come from the 1980s as we have indicated above.
But without any doubt it was the incorporation of the Convention by the Human Rights
Act 1998 that cemented the Convention as a part of the UK’s functioning constitution.
How the Act is interpreted, has been outlined above. The Act has helped to develop that
dialogue between domestic judges and judges of the CHR. In developing the
jurisprudence of the Convention in a British context the courts at first were anxious to
give a British patina to the rights.90 The case law of Strasbourg is not, as shown above,
strictly binding on British judges. Nonetheless, British courts should, ‘in the absence of
some special circumstances, follow any clear and constant judgments’ of the ECtHR.91
More recently the courts have stated that the ECHR is an international instrument the
correct interpretation of which can only be expounded by the Strasbourg court:92
It is of course open to MSs to provide for rights more generous than those guaranteed by the
Convention, but such provision should not be the product of interpretation of the Convention by
national courts, since the meaning of the Convention should be uniform throughout the states
party to it. The duty of national courts is to keep pace with the Strasbourg jurisprudence as it
evolves over time: no more, but certainly no less. 93
88
The ECHR has also been incorporated into Irish law by statute but Irish commentators are not as
impressed by the incorporation as are UK lawyers in the case of the UK. One of the reasons for this is
because the rights in the ECHR are in the Irish constitution and this gives individual rights in the event
of breaches: JM Kelly The Irish Constitution 4th ed 2003 eds G Hogan and G Whyte.
89
Derbyshire CC v Sunday Times [1993] AC 534; ex p Leech [1993] 4 549; Simms [1999] 3 All ER
400.
90
Saadi [2001] 4 All ER 961 para 36; R (ProLife Alliance) v BBC [2002] 756 paras 33-34.
91
Per Bingham in R (Ullah) v Special Adjudicator etc [2004] UKHL 26, at para. 20, (emphasis added)
citing R (Alconbury Developments) v Secretary of State for the Environment [2001] UKHL 23.
92
R (Ullah) v Special Adjudicator etc [2004] UKHL 26 para 20 per Lord Bingham
93
Ibid.
16
Electronic Journal of Comparative Law, vol. 10.3 (December 2006), http://www.ejcl.org
In formulating its decisions the ECtHR considers ‘the spectrum of attitudes across the
contracting states in order to determine the contemporary content of rights under the
Convention.’94 The House of Lords disagreed with the Court of Appeal and in the
absence of special circumstances cultural differences should not allow a variation in
protection under Art 8(1) as the latter had suggested. According to Lord Steyn, such
differences may be relevant for objective justification for interference by the state under
Art 8(2) with the right.95 However, although the House of Lords has followed the lead
of the ECtHR on questions such as the nature of a ‘public body’ which may be the
perpetrator of a breach under the Convention, more elastic interpretations may be given
in the future when government is effected more pervasively by private contractors.96
There may be differences in approach on items such as the fairness of procedures and
protection under Art 6 where the common law may take a broader view of the nature of
rights that need to be protected by fair procedure than would the ECtHR in interpreting
‘civil rights and obligations’.
This reasoning constitutes a clear statement of the central position that the ECtHR is
seen to possess under the terms of incorporation. It is achieved not through obedience
but rather by compliance. It is not hierarchical but cooperative. To that extent it has
constitutionalised the position of the ECtHR and its jurisprudence. One must repeat,
that while the ECtHR and its judges have influenced the manner in which UK judges
determine substantive rights under the HRA 1998 and the Convention, there has also
been an influence exercised by British judges over the Strasbourg judiciary.97
We believe there is an emergent European constitutionalism and the argument has been
supported elsewhere.98 The concept of human rights is taking an increasingly European
dimension and would be assisted enormously by the acceptance of the DTC and the
Charter of Fundamental Rights. The concept of the ‘Rule of Law’ must be treated with
caution. It means different things in different traditions. In the common law world, for
instance, the American tradition has no place for the supremacy of ordinary law. That
resides in the constitution. In the English tradition the constitution comes from the law
and from the rights of individuals guaranteed by independent courts. This used to be
seen as a way of privatising the constitution -- of arguing that the constitution was
based on private law concepts rooted in property and liberty. But the common law has
changed, not least through European influence, and this influence has enhanced legal
and constitutional sensitivities. Norms of constitutionality inform the common law
under the influence of more than thirty years of judicial decision making and statutes
such as the Human Rights Act, and the devolution legislation. There is a more robust
protection against government abuses and a greater substantive content to the rule of
law. But the English lawyer’s rule of law may not be the same as État de Droit or the
Rechtsstaatlichkeit to French or German lawyers. Nonetheless, the ECtHR can be seen
as forming a different type of constitution that is mono-dimensional, contained and
limited. The main problems are in effect functional since the ECHR is focusing solely
on the protection of human rights thus not covering the matters of division of powers,
while the enforcement element at the Convention level is weaker than at the EU level.
On the other hand, it can be argued that the focus on human rights alone has a spill-over
94
Per Lord Rodger in R v Chief Constable of South Yorkshire Police ex p LS [2004] UKHL 39 para 66.
Per Lord Steyn op. cit. note 36 para 27.
96
Aston Cantlow etc v Wallbank [2003] 3 All ER 1213 (HL).
97
Most famously in the area of public liability for fault and Arts 6, 3 and to a lesser extent 8.
98
See note 16 above.
95
17
Electronic Journal of Comparative Law, vol. 10.3 (December 2006), http://www.ejcl.org
effect in the sense that the standards established through the Convention and the
ECtHR’s jurisprudence have practical repercussions for the organisational operation of
a State. Therefore, there a an indirect fulfilment of that functionality element, while
there is no doubt that the process of standard setting by the ECtHR corresponds to the
legitimisation element and the Rule of Law component of a constitution. It is submitted
that the ECtHR is forming a different type of constitution, albeit thin and thematically
self-limited, that must not be compared with national or post-national constitutions; its
role is partly complementary and partly autonomous.
4.
The Relationship between Types of Constitutions in the UK
In a loose sense one could address the Treaty of the European Community as a
constitution. This has been alluded to already. But it would meet with the objections
already discussed. The term constitution would signify for some an unacceptable notion
of supremacy in a supranational entity. Nations never signed up to a superior
constitution. However, if the federalist tendencies in the term supranational constitution
were exposed as exaggerated, or false, then a constitution would be an appropriate
expression for parts of the existing Treaties. This would cover those parts contained in
Title I, Parts I and II of Title II and those parts dealing with institutions and some of the
provisions in Part VI, the Protocols on subsidiarity and proportionality and national
parliaments. Parts of Titles V and VI would fall within international affairs and security
and could fall within constitutional law, even though not legally binding within
domestic systems. But, it appears somewhat chaotic or messy from a constitutional
perspective: a constitution of bits and pieces.
But whether it would be correct to describe the law of the EC as constitutional law is
another matter. If confined to the areas that might be called a ‘constitution’ as above,
because it covers basic constitutional subjects, then logically such a description would
be proper. If used to include case law that develops EC principles then this would be in
the form of a self referential exercise described above. Much of the law in the treaties
has nothing to do with constitutional matters. By this it is meant institutional
relationships, or Union/member state relationship, or Union citizen relationship. Is
anything gained by referring to trade law, or competition law or Environmental law as
constitutional? If one is not careful one will be in the position as once described in the
UK: everything that happens is constitutional and even when nothing happens that also
is constitutional. The Charter on Fundamental Rights is not presently a legally binding
document and one has to look to case law to establish human rights and their protection.
Even then, the protection is qualified and has often been criticised by commentators as
tepid compared with the ECtHR in Strasbourg.99 Human rights have not been treated as
things of overriding significance and are respected to the extent that they do not remove
Coppel and O’Neill, “The ECJ: Taking Rights Seriously?”, (1992) 29 CMLRev. 669; Von Bogdany,
“The European Union as a Human Rights Organization? Human Rights and the Core of the European
Union”, (2000) 37 CMLRev. 1307; Toth, “The European Union and Human Rights: The Way
Forward”, (1997) 34 CMLRev. 491; Weiler, "Fundamental Rights and Fundamental Boundaries: on
Standards and Values in the Protection of Human Rights", in Neuwahl and Rosas (eds.), The European
Union and Human Rights, (Martinus Nijhoff, 1995), p.66; Weiler and Lockhard, “‘Taking Rights
Seriously’ Seriously: The European Court and its Fundamental Rights Jurisprudence”, (1995) 32
CMLRev. 51; Alston, The EU and Human Rights, (Oxford: OUP, 1999).
99
18
Electronic Journal of Comparative Law, vol. 10.3 (December 2006), http://www.ejcl.org
the fundamental basic freedoms on which the Union is based.100 The ECJ was reluctant
to refer to the ECtHR and its judgments even after it referred to the Convention. This
criticism is looking a little dated. Now the “ECJ refers extensively to Convention
provisions and to [the ECtHR’s] jurisprudence,”101while recently the ECJ made its first
reference to the EU Charter of Fundamental rights in Parliament v Council.102 There
have been crucial differences in detail in the treatment of rights by the ECJ and ECtHR
but the overall relationship is one of cooperation. It could be no other.
To sum up in the experience of our domestic legal development in the UK, there are
three levels of constitutional law: European, national and possibly regional. The latter
has emerged with devolution within the UK. There is a context of constitutional
pluralism to borrow a well worn phrase. Union law takes primacy even over
constitutional law where the measures of constitutional law fall within accepted Union
competence. But that leaves much of national constitutional law untouched. The
argument from Thoburn is that it also leaves untouched that part of national UK
constitutional law that gives the Union its primacy or supremacy, namely Parliamentary
Sovereignty.
What is novel in Thoburn, and controversial, is the differentiation in legal status of
statutes; that constitutional measures are of a higher order legally than other measures.
They are recognised by ‘our own courts, to which the scope and nature of
Parliamentary sovereignty are ultimately confided.’103 There is, Sir John claims, a
‘hierarchy of statutes’ and constitutional measures are those which ‘condition the legal
relationship between citizen and state in some general overarching manner’ or which
enlarge or diminish the scope of what we would now regard as fundamental
constitutional rights’.104 Sir John produced a fourfold argument: Community law is
incorporated by the ECA and is ‘supreme’; the ECA is a constitutional statute as
explained above; it is so by virtue of English law (sic) and the common law recognises
a category of constitutional statutes; the fundamental legal basis of the UK’s
relationship with the EU rests with the domestic not the European legal powers. The
matrix of that relationship, as it were, is common law, and the common law defines
ultimate sovereignty, and again according to Sir John, places limits on that sovereignty:
In the event, which no doubt would never happen in the real world, that a European measure
was seen to be repugnant to a fundamental or constitutional right guaranteed by the law of
England, a question would arise whether the general words of the ECA were sufficient to
incorporate the measure and give it overriding effect in domestic law … I consider that the
balance struck by [the fourfold argument above] gives full weight both to the proper supremacy
of Community law and to the proper supremacy of the United Kingdom Parliament. By the
former I mean the supremacy of substantive community law’ and by the latter ‘the supremacy of
the legal foundation within which those substantive provisions enjoy their primacy. If this
Costello and Browne, “Comity, Convergence and Contrasts: The European Convention on Human
Rights and European Union Law”, in Kilkelly (ed.), ECHR and Irish Law (Dublin: Jordans, 2004),
p.35; Scheeck, “Solving Europe's Binary Human Rights Puzzle. The Interaction between Supranational
Courts as a Parameter of European Governance”, Research in Question Working Paper, Centre d’études
et de recherches internationals, (Paris: Sciences Po, 2005).
101
Bosphorus Hava Yollari Turizm v Ireland (2006) 42 EHRR 1, at para. 159.
102
Case C-540/03, Parliament v Council, at para. 38.
103
Thoburn at para 60.
104
Thoburn at para 62.
100
19
Electronic Journal of Comparative Law, vol. 10.3 (December 2006), http://www.ejcl.org
balance is properly understood, it will be seen that these two supremacies are in harmony and
not in conflict.105
We have then multi-layered constitutions the relationship between which is
constantly evolving and adapting to mutual accommodation. The Bosphorus
decision on the ‘equivalent’ and ‘comparable’ protection of human rights under
EU law and under the Convention is a striking example of that cooperation
between courts.106 Comparable not identical was the key. ‘Any such finding of
equivalence could not be final and would be susceptible to review in the light of
any relevant change in human rights protection.’ The presumption could be
rebutted if protection of human rights within the EU proved ‘manifestly
deficient’. In such cases, the interest of international cooperation would be
outweighed by the Convention’s role as a “constitutional instruments of European
public order” in the field of human rights. 107 The statement is analogous to that
made in the case of Loizidou v Turkey108 and it creates the same situation as the
ECJ’s judgment in Les Verts: the court declaring the system that it serves has
constitutional status, thus focusing attention on the accuracy of that point.
We end with a reference to the future. The accommodation and dialogue achieved
by the preliminary reference procedure and the ECJ and CFI’s relationship with
the ECtHR and national courts is likely to be continued in the operation of DTC
Arts I-7, I-28(1) second line, II-51(1),(3),(4) and (6), II-53, III-337(ii) and (iii).
Furthermore, the fear of a strict hierarchical division brought about by the
judgment in Costa v ENEL in which transfers of sovereignty involved ‘a
permanent limitation of sovereign rights’ in areas subject to the transfer must be
seen in the light of the right to withdraw from the Union in Art I-59.
105
Thoburn at para 70.
Bosphorus Hava Yollari Turizm v Ireland (2006) 42 EHRR 1. For analysis see Costello, C., “The
Bosphorus Ruling of the European Court of Human Rights: Fundamental Rights and Blurred
Boundaries in Europe”, (2006) 6 (1) Human Rights Law Review87. Cf. with C-84/95, Bosphorus
Airways [1996] ECR I-3953. The latter was criticised in Canor, ‘ "Can Two Walk Together, Except
They Be Agreed?" The Relationship Between International Law and European Law: The Incorporation
of United Nations Sanctions Against Yugoslavia into European Community Law Through the
Perspective of the European Court of Justice’, (1998) 35 Common Market Law Review 137; Burrows,
“Caught in the Cross-Fire’, (1997) 22 European Law Review 170; and Drewniak, “The Bosphorus
Case: The Balancing of Property Rights in the European Community and the Public Interest in Ending
the War in Bosnia”, (1997) 20 Fordham International Law Journal 1007.
107
Bosphorus Hava Yollari Turizm v Ireland (2006) 42 EHRR 1, at para. 156.
108
Loizidou v. Turkey, 310 Eur. Ct. H.R. (ser. A) at 27, 31 (1995): “the Convention is a constitutional
instrument of European public order”.
106
20
Electronic Journal of Comparative Law, vol. 10.3 (December 2006), http://www.ejcl.org
5.
The ‘New’ Phenomenon of European Constitutionalism: Concluding
Comments
The realisation of the realities of constitutional pluralism109 and constitutional
coexistence in Europe110 leads to the question whether it is time to consider that the
discussion about European constitutionalism needs modification. The methodological
approach of this paper has been structured on the idea that the attention should turn
beyond ontology and towards typology, i.e. the systematic study of types of
constitutions that share functional characteristics.111 From the perspective of
typological analysis, the report concentrates on different types of constitutions in
Europe that share the following characteristics: living/evolving constitutions, with the
judiciary performing an integral role in ensuring the responsiveness of constitutions,
with certain basic functional characteristics and the necessary legitimising element of
operating under the Rule of Law.
Certain preliminary observations can be made about the different types of
constitutions. Firstly, all the different types of constitutions are not autonomous, since
a process of constitutional blending is in operation and it is in this way that
constitutionalism is defined and refined.112 Within the process of blending of
constitutions, which we describe as the process of European Public Law (EPL),113 a
constant exchange of influences between the different types of constitutions takes
place and is evident at a macro level that observes systems as a whole and at the micro
level of examining the development of specific legal principles.114 Secondly, there is a
constitutional spectrum comprised by different constitutional shades and formed
through the process of constitutionalism. Therefore, the European constitutional
spectrum is created by a state of synergy where the final item is greater than the sum
of the individual constituent parts.
The European constitutional spectrum has certain essential characteristics. The main
feature is the exchange of influences that in the United Kingdom has been identifiable
in recent years in a number of fields.115 For instance, the decisions in Jackson116 and
Walker, N., “The Idea of Constitutional Pluralism”, (2002) 65 MLR 317; La Torre, M., “Legal
Pluralism as an Evolutionary Achievement of Community Law”, in Snyder, F. (eds), The
Europeanisation of Law: The Legal Effects of European Integration, (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2000),
p. 125.
110
Weiler, J., “Why Should Europe Be a Democracy: The Corruption of Political
Culture and the Principle of Toleration”, in Snyder, F. (eds), The Europeanisation of Law: The Legal
Effects of European Integration, (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2000), p.213.
111
On functionality see Tsatsos, D., Die Europäische Unionsgrundordnung, 2002, at p. 29.
112
See Freedman, B. and Saunders, C., “Symposium: Constitutional Borrowing: Editors Introduction”,
(2003) International Journal of Constitutional Law 177; Goldsworthy, J., “Homogenizing
Constitutions”, (2003) 23 OJLS 483; Harlow, C., “Voices of Difference in a Plural Community”, in
Beaumont, P., Lyons, C. and Walker, N. (eds.), Convergence and Divergence in European Public Law,
(Oxford; Hart, 2002), p. 199.
113
Birkinshaw, op. cit., note 10, at pp. 3-4.
114
Birkinshaw, op. cit., note 10, at pp. 327-71.
115
Birkinshaw, op. cit., note 10, at pp. 3-4; Walker, op. cit., note 14. See e.g. Pepper (Inspector of
Taxes) v. Hart [1993] AC 593 (on use of Hansard as interpretative tool). See also the principle of
proportionality: from rejection- R v. Secretary of State for the Home Department, ex parte Brind [1991]
1 AC 696, to exiguous application- R v. Secretary of State for the Home Department, ex parte Venables
[1998] AC 407; R v. Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority, ex parte Blood [1997] 2 All ER
687;Congreve v. Home Office [1976] QB 629- to application in human rights cases International
Transport Roth Gmbh v. Secretary of State for the Home Department [2002] EWCA Civ 158, [2002] 3
109
21
Electronic Journal of Comparative Law, vol. 10.3 (December 2006), http://www.ejcl.org
Thoburn117 illustrate a turn in the judicial approach that is now willing to consider
subjecting statutes to the demanding scrutiny of constitutional review and to elaborate
on the theoretical foundations that could underpin it, while at the same time the
emphasis is placed on the rule of law as the underlying value of the constitutional
theory.118 In the past, the development of a constitutional theory by judges was simply
a matter of understanding a mechanical constitution,119 but with the introduction of
the Human Rights Act 1998 and the cases that followed,120 there is a shift in the
judicial reasoning towards the creation of an articulated justification for scrutinising
governmental action.121 However, it must be noted that despite the apparent change in
the judicial mentality and approach, there are still constraints imposed by the basic
rules of the common law system. In the recent case of Leeds City Council v Price122
the issue was whether the Court of Appeal had to follow in accordance with precedent
the decision of the House of Lords in Harrow London Borough Council v Qazi 123 that
was in direct conflict with the jurisprudence of the ECtHR concerning
property/possession claims as explained in Connors v UK.124 A seven-member
appellate committee of the House of Lords agreeing with Lord Bingham on this point
further endorsed Leeds’ submission that lower courts remain bound by domestic
authority notwithstanding later ECtHR decisions which appear to conflict with that
authority.125 It was stated that the ECtHR accords a margin of appreciation to national
courts to decide the manner in which the principles of the Convention are to be
applied domestically and “It is by the decisions of national courts that the domestic
standard must be initially set, and to those decisions the ordinary rules of precedent
should apply”.126 Therefore, the changes in judicial approach that can be partly
attributed to the European influence have taken place within the existing
constitutional framework and subject to its basic constraints.
WLR 344; John Richard Lindsay v. Commissioners of Customs and Excise [2002] EWCA Civ 267
[2002] 3 All E.R. 118; Customs and Excise Commissioners v. Newbury [2003] EWHC (Admin) 702,
[2003] 2 All ER 964; A v. Secretary of State for the Home Department [2005] 2 WLR 87.
116
R (Jackson) v Attorney General [2005] UKHL 56.
117
Thoburn v Sunderland City Council [2002] 4 All ER 156.
118
R v. Secretary of State for the Home Department, ex parte Pierson [1998] AC 538;
119
On traditional views of the constitution see ex p. Selwyn (1872) 36 J.P. 54; Madzimbamuto v.
Lardner-Burke [1969] 1 A.C. 645; Pickin v. British Railways Board [1974] A.C. 765; R (On the
Application of Al-Jeddah) v Secretary of State for Defence [2005] EWHC 1809; R v. Secretary of State
for the Home Department, ex parte Brind [1991] 1 AC 696: no constitutional review, independence of
each Parliament, no possibility of entrenchment, dualist system of law, rejection of proportionality.
120
See for example R. v DPP Ex p. Kebilene [2000] 2 A.C. 326 (on reversal of burden of proof); R v
Lambert [2001] 3 All ER 577 (consistent interpretation); R (H) v Mental Health Review Tribunal
[2002] QB 1 (burden of proof on patient in breach of Art. 5 ECHR);Wilson v First County Trust [2001]
3 All ER 229 (limits of interpretative obligation); Daly [2001] 3 All ER 433 (correspondence control
and cell searches are anxiously scrutinised by courts); R. (on the application of Mahmood (Amjad)) v
Secretary of State for the HD [2001] 1 W.L.R. 840 (interference with fundamental rights requires a
higher degree of scrutiny and justification); Farrakhan [2002] Q.B. 1391(on freedom of expression and
protection of public order); Ex p. Rehman [1999] WL 477367 (on access to legal aid); Venables v News
Group Newspapers Ltd [2001] H.R.L.R. 19 (freedom of expression against right to life).
121
R v. Secretary of State for the Home Department, ex parte Daly [2001] UKHL 26; A v Secretary of
State for the Home Department [2004] UKHL 56; A v SSHD (No 2) (HL) [2005] 3 WLR 1249.
122
Leeds City Council v Price [2006] UKHL 10.
123
Harrow London Borough Council v Qazi [2003] UKHL 43, [2004] 1 AC 983.
124
Connors v United Kingdom [2004] 40 EHRR 189.
125
Leeds City Council v Price [2006] UKHL 10, at paras. 40-5.
126
Leeds City Council v Price [2006] UKHL 10, at para. 44, per Lord Bingham.
22
Electronic Journal of Comparative Law, vol. 10.3 (December 2006), http://www.ejcl.org
On this basis, there is a surfacing of common principles at the micro level of
constitutionalism that is founded on the rule of law and human dignity. The human
rights cases in the English context are evidence of that and are developed in parallel
with similar approaches at the Union level as the decision in Omega illustrates.127 In
addition, the process of influencing is evidently multidirectional since there is the
example of the Pretty128 decision operating as the guide for the ECtHR in relation to
the right to die. Finally, there are also important diverging elements within European
constitutionalism that provide elasticity and control tension, thus operating as
safeguards of the system that is in effect endothermic in the sense that conflicts are
constructive and useful as long as they remain controlled. Examples of such
controlled tension can be found in the areas of supremacy of EC law,129 KompetenzKompetenz130 and the diverging meanings of human dignity in different legal systems
that warrant the application of a margin of appreciation.131
Therefore, the process of constitutionalism that creates the constitutional spectrum
that incorporates different types of constitutions has both diverging and converging
effects, with the significance of both being of equal weight for the system. Moreover,
it must be stated that the stepping stone for the preceding analysis is the realisation of
the limits of the ontological discussion and of the advantages of the typological
analysis. In other words, in the quest for understanding the nature of European
constitutionalism it is essential to consider that system a paradigm of constitutional
polymorphism. On this basis, it is submitted that the theme of the session titled ‘the
emergence of a European constitutional law’ could be more inclusive and challenging
if it is approached in terms of ‘the emergence of European constitutional laws’.
Cite as: Patrick Birkinshaw and Costas Kombos, The UK Approach to the Emergence of European
Constitutionalism, vol. 10.3 ELECTRONIC JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE LAW, (December
2006), <http://www.ejcl.org/103/article103-2.pdf>.
Kombos, C., “Fundamental Rights and Fundamental Freedoms: A Symbiosis on the Basis of
Subsidiarity”, (2006) 12 (3) EPL 433.
128
R (Pretty) v DPP [2002] 1 AC 800 HL and Cf. with Pretty v UK (2002) 35 EHRR1 (decision by
ECtHR).
129
See Kumm, M., “Who is the Arbiter of Constitutionality in Europe?”, (1999) 36 CMLRev. 351; De
Witte. B., “Direct Effect, Supremacy and the Nature of the Legal Order”, in Craig, P. and De Burca, G.,
(ed.), The Evolution of EU Law (Oxford: OUP, 1999), p. 177.
130
Herdegen, M., “Maastricht and the German Constitutional Court: Constitutional Restraints for an
Ever Closer Union”, (1994) 31 CMLRev. 235; Weiler, J., “The Reformulation of German
Constitutionalism”, (1997) 35 JCMS 597; Reich, N., “Judge- Made ‘Europe á la Carte’: Some Remarks
on Recent Conflicts between European and German Constitutional Law”, (1996) 7 EJIL 103;
Elbers,U. and Urban, N., “The Order of the German Federal Constitutional Court of 7 June 2000 and
the Kompetenz-Kompetenz in the European Judicial System”, (2001) 7 EPL 21.
131
Harlow, C., “Voices of Difference in a Plural Community”, in Beaumont, P., Lyons, C. and Walker,
N. (eds.), Convergence and Divergence in European Public Law, (Oxford; Hart, 2002), p. 199;
Birkinshaw, op. cit., note 10, at pp. 7-26.
127
23
Download