A revisionary Kantian view of moral dilemmas Michael Cholbi [mjcholbi@csupomona.edu] (November 4: appx 10,588 words) A working single mother whose birth control fails must decide whether to abort her recently conceived fetus for fear that she will have to leave the workforce otherwise; an emergency room physician must determine in what order to perform triage on victims of a natural disaster; a national leader must decide whether to attack a rogue nation’s recently discovered nuclear weapons factories, even if this entails harming civilians; a teacher is torn between upholding high academic standards and discouraging students who are at risk of dropping out of school because of low grades; world leaders attempting to fashion a response to global climate change consider how to balance the interests of present and future generations; a sadistic concentration camp physician forces a mother to choose which of her two children will be gassed to death. Most every moral theorist concedes that these situations represent at least apparent moral dilemmas. The more provocative question is whether there are genuine moral dilemmas: An individual is in a genuine, rather than merely apparent, moral dilemma when she is morally obligated to perform act A, and morally obligated to perform act B, but the contingent circumstances of the world make it impossible to perform both A and B. Such a dilemma is genuine because it is not the individual’s ignorance of any moral (or factual) consideration that leaves her uncertain about what to do.1 It is rather that the moral universe itself is 1 Standard characterizations of genuine moral dilemmas found, e.g., in Christopher Gowans, Moral Dilemmas (New York: Oxford UP, 1987), p. 3, or Terrance McConnell, “Moral dilemmas,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moral-dilemmas/, accessed 8/11/2009), tend not to index dilemmas to the agent’s metaphysically constituted such that, despite an individual’s knowing what she is morally obligated to do, it is impossible for her to do it. She is seemingly fated to moral failure. In debates about the existence of genuine moral dilemmas, Kant is typically represented not simply as denying the possibility of such dilemmas,2 but as the principal historical spokesperson for a “rationalist” tradition in moral philosophy for whom genuine moral dilemmas are anathema. As Christopher Gowans has characterized it, this rationalist tradition regards moral practice as a species of human rationality, where reason is seen “as requiring system and order, as necessitating commensurability and hierarchy, [and] as insisting on the importance of generality and abstraction.”3 Because rationalists tend “regard whatever moral conflict might appear in moral practice as mere appearance, as a betrayal rather than a manifestation of reason, and as something that reason properly understood would reveal as such,”4 the rationalist tradition is skeptical of genuine moral dilemmas. In contrast, what Gowans calls the “experimentalist” tradition aims to “understand moral practice primarily from the standpoint of the moral experience of persons,” giving priority to “observation and reflection on what it is like for a person embedded in a particular social context to live a life constituted by values and commitments, to encounter circumstances of perplexity and choice, to deliberate and determine a epistemic or moral competence, knowledge, etc. Hence, it is possible for an agent both to be in a genuine dilemma without knowing she is and possible for an agent to wrongly believe she is in a genuine moral dilemma. As McConnell expresses it elsewhere, (“Moral residue and dilemmas,” in H.E. Mason (ed.), Moral Dilemmas and Moral Theory (Oxford: Oxford U. Press, 1996)) “genuine moral dilemmas are ontological, not merely epistemic; the truth of the conflicting ought-statements is independent of the agent’s beliefs.” (p. 36) 2 Gowans, Moral Dilemmas, pp. 6-7; Ruth Barcan Marcus, “More about moral dilemmas,” in Mason (ed.), p. 24; Mary Mothersill, “The moral dilemmas debate,” in Mason (ed.), p. 69; Norman O. Dahl, “Morality, moral dilemmas, and moral requirements,” in Mason (ed.), p. 90n8; and Thomas E. Hill, “Moral dilemmas, gaps, and residues: A Kantian perspective,” in Mason (ed.), pp. 173-175. 3 Gowans, “Moral theory, moral dilemmas, and moral responsibilities,” in Mason (ed.), p. 200. 4 Gowans, “Moral theory, moral dilemmas, and moral responsibilities,” p. 202. 2 course of response, and to carry out this decision and live with its consequences.” Since moral dilemmas do appear to arise within ordinary moral practice, the experimentalist tradition tends to support the existence of genuine dilemmas. My aim here is to defend a Kantian view concerning moral dilemmas that, while broadly rationalistic, incorporates the experimentalists’ aim of accounting for ordinary moral experience. At the level of theory, the revisionary Kantian view I shall defend is agnostic about whether genuine moral dilemmas exist. However, at the level of practice, this view takes the denial of genuine moral dilemmas as a regulative ideal that both guides and provides a goal for the operation of practical reason in the moral realm. Moral inquiry and deliberation thus operate on the implicit assumption that there are no genuine moral dilemmas, much in the fashion that scientific inquiry and deliberation operate on the implicit assumption that our scientific knowledge can be unified. Being agnostic about whether there are genuine moral dilemmas, this revisionary Kantian view thus takes the denial of genuine moral dilemmas (or, correlatively, their resolvability) as a methodological, rather than a metaphysical, hypothesis. Aside from its interest as an interpretation of Kant, this view is superior to its metaphysical rivals — those that either affirm or deny genuine moral dilemmas — in one crucial respect. Much of the recent debate between these rival metaphysical views of moral dilemmas has focused on whether certain features of our experience, most notably the “moral residue” identified by Bernard Williams, show that there are genuine moral dilemmas. Proponents of genuine dilemmas claim these features point to the existence of genuine dilemmas, whereas opponents of dilemmas reject this inference. I shall argue that, by underscoring how apparently irresolvable moral dilemmas represent failures to realize the aforementioned regulative ideal of practical reason, my revisionary Kantian view more fully and more parsimoniously accounts not only for moral 3 residue but for other crucial phenomenological dimensions of our experience of moral dilemmas. The revisionary Kantian view I defend is thus both historically significant and philosophically attractive. Indeed, the plausibility of the view illustrates that the experimentalists’ commitment to honoring ordinary moral practice, especially in “circumstances of complexity and choice,” is not antithetical to the rationalists’ commitment to the elimination of moral conflict in the pursuit of rational system and order. In fact, the latter is presupposed by the best account of the former. My discussion unfolds as follows. Parts 1 and 2 argue that the passages on which the standard interpretation of Kant on moral dilemmas rests have been read too hastily and that Kant’s casuistical remarks about apparent moral dilemmas, as well as his views regarding the general aspirations of reason, permit a methodological reading wherein the denial of moral dilemmas is a regulative ideal instead of a metaphysical claim. On my reading, Kant sides neither with those who accept, nor with those who deny, the existence of genuine moral dilemmas. Instead, Kant’s apparent denial of moral dilemmas is an a priori principle of practical reason we both use to guide our moral deliberation and as an ideal toward which such deliberation strives. However, just as there may be as yet unnoticed evidence against even our best scientific theories, evidence that confounds our effort to unify our scientific knowledge, so too can never be certain that we have fully realized the regulative ideal according to which there are no genuine moral dilemmas. For not only are there possible dilemmas we have not yet encountered in our moral experience, we may also encounter apparent dilemmas that do not appear resolvable despite our rational commitment to their resolution and despite our exercising our deliberative capacities with full competence. This apparent irresolvability does not demonstrate that there are genuine dilemmas, however, nor does it undermine the resolution of dilemmas as a regulative ideal of practical reason. 4 After answering (in part 3) worries about the relation of theoretical and practical reason and about the apparent incompatibility of this methodological view of moral dilemmas with core elements of Kant’s moral philosophy, parts 4-6 show how this revisionary Kantian view fruitfully explains three main features of the phenomenology of moral dilemmas. First, it can explain the rationality of the self-reproach that agents often experience subsequent to acting within apparent moral dilemmas. Second, it explains our attitudinal ambivalence concerning which negative self-appraisals are appropriate in the wake of a moral dilemma. Lastly, it explains an important asymmetry between our first personal and third personal standpoints on moral dilemmas. This revisionary Kantian view, wherein the denial of moral dilemmas functions as a regulative ideal of practical reason, is thus inviting both as an interpretation of Kant and as a philosophical stance. If correct, this view permits us to retain many of our beliefs and attitudes concerning moral dilemmas without hitching them to any metaphysical stance about whether genuine moral dilemmas are real or not. Before proceeding, a final note concerning the Kantian pedigree of my view: The revisionary Kantian view of moral dilemmas I defend here rests on Kantian claims concerning the goals and commitments of practical reason as it is deployed in moral deliberation and inquiry. Hence, I take pains to show that this view coheres with other substantive commitments of Kantian morality (the standing of the Categorical Imperative as the supreme principle of morality, etc.). However, I deploy a Kantian vernacular in part for rhetorical convenience. Indeed, I believe that this view of moral dilemmas should be congenial to moral theorists with other substantive philosophical leanings (consequentialists, virtue theorists, etc.). For, as best as I can surmise, the view does not hinge on whether the substance of Kant’s moral philosophy — 5 the Categorical Imperative, humanity as end in itself, etc. — is correct. Different moral theories will yield different conclusions concerning which situations represent apparent or genuine moral dilemmas, and why. The Kantian pedigree of my view should not, I believe, raises suspicions among moral theorists whose allegiances lie elsewhere. 1. Dilemmas in Kant’s Doctrine of Virtue Readers of Kant’s Doctrine of Virtue might be surprised to learn that Kant is so commonly interpreted as denying moral dilemmas. For there Kant offers5 series of casuistical questions in conjunction with each main type of moral duty (whether it is morally permissible to end one’s life to save one’s country, whether merely polite lies are wrong, etc). But strikingly, Kant does not answer these questions. Now, if Kant truly thought there are no genuine dilemmas, then the presence of these unanswered casuistical questions is a puzzle. Kant was presumably highly competent at applying his own moral theory, so if these casuistical dilemmas are resolvable, we would expect Kant to be able to resolve them in order to illustrate the power of his moral theory. That these casuistical questions are merely mentioned without even an attempt at their resolution is surprising if we assume that Kant believed there are no genuine moral dilemmas. Still, that Kant leaves these casuisical questions unresolved is at most indirect evidence for Kant’s views about moral dilemmas. In addition, advocates of the standard interpretation of Kant’s view on the matter may well reply that Kant says nothing in connection with these casuistical questions to suggest that these questions are not rationally resolvable even in principle, i.e., nothing here indicates that Kant supposed these are genuine moral dilemmas rather than simply hard cases for his moral theory to tackle. 5 Starting at 6:423. 6 The standard interpretation would be more problematic, however, if the passages central to this interpretation can be plausibly read so as not to support that interpretation. Such is the case, I contend, with the most widely cited passage given in favor of the standard interpretation, here quoted in its entirety:6 A conflict of duties would be a relation between them in which one of them would cancel the other (wholly or in part). — But since duty and obligation are concepts that express the objective practical necessity of certain actions and two rules opposed to each other cannot be necessary at the same time, if it is a duty to act in accordance with one rule, to act in accordance with the opposite rule is not a duty but even contrary to duty; so a collision of duties and obligations is inconceivable. However, a subject may have, in a rule he prescribes to himself, two grounds of obligation, one or the other of which is not sufficient to put him under obligation, so that one of them is not a duty. — When two such grounds conflict with each other, practical philosophy says, not that the stronger obligation takes precedence but that the stronger ground of obligation prevails. Kant’s words certainly seem to deny the existence of moral dilemmas.7 Agents can certainly be subject to competing “grounds of obligation,” Kant acknowledges. That is, an agent may, even when subject to a “rule he prescribes to himself” such as the self-legislated Categorical Imperative, recognize two moral “obligations” or considerations each of which, in isolation, would be sufficient to impose upon him a duty. Yet in circumstances where both grounds of obligation are present (and in accordance with the notion of a moral dilemma, the agent cannot act on both such grounds), it is “inconceivable” in light of the “objective practical necessity” expressed by the concept of duty that the agent could have a duty stemming from each 6 Metaphysics of Morals 6:224. I have excised Kant’s Latin renderings of certain phrases. 7 Kant is best interpreted here as concerned only with what are perfect duties in his taxonomy. Imperfect duties prescribe only general ends and cannot, in a strict sense, come into conflict with one another or with perfect duties. Perfect duties prescribe specific actions and therefore can generate dilemmas. Alan Donagan, “Consistency in rationalist moral systems,” Journal of Philosophy 81 (1984), p. 294, notes these relationships as well. 7 such ground of obligation.8 It must be the case, Kant concludes, that the agent’s duty stems from the “stronger ground of obligation.” Apparently then, there cannot be a circumstance in which an agent both has a duty to perform, and to abstain from performing, one and the same action. In cases of competing grounds of obligation, one such ground must not be sufficient to constitute the agent’s duty. It would appear, then, that Kant is deploying modus tollens against the claim that there are genuine moral dilemmas: If the imperatives of duty were to yield conflicting obligations, then morality’s imperatives would lack “objective practical necessity.” But since those imperatives are imperatives of duty, they must incorporate “objective practical necessity” and so cannot yield conflicting obligations. All the same, to attribute to Kant the denial of genuine moral dilemmas on the basis of this passage is too quick. In general, philosophers ought to interpret passages from the work of their historical predecessors so as to ensure consistency with the relevant texts, coherence with those predecessors’ overall philosophical stances, and, when necessary, to opt for the weaker or less ambitious interpretation of a passage if this interpretation has clear philosophical advantages over stronger or more ambitious rivals. By these criteria, Kant is not best read as denying the possibility of genuine moral dilemmas. 2. The denial of dilemmas as a regulative ideal Kant is clearly concerned in this passage that the existence of genuine moral dilemmas would somehow threaten the intelligibility of morality’s demands. In order to pinpoint the 8 Kant offers the same argument in the other main passage seeming to address dilemmas. In the Lectures on Ethics (27:261), Kant states that “no two obligations can clash, because what is rendered morally necessary by one cannot be made otherwise by another. …If the one duty is an obligation, the other cannot properly be termed so.” 8 threat, we can consider how the existence of genuine dilemmas might undermine the Categorical Imperative, the principle which, in Kant’s ethics, gives expression to morality’s demands. The Categorical Imperative plays two roles in Kantian morality. It is on the one hand a theoretical principle, identifying those attributes of actions which render their performance morally permissible or morally impermissible. Admittedly, how these attributes are identified is a complex matter in Kantian ethics. Maxims — those principles that agents use to justify their actions — are justified in a procedural manner under the Formula of Universal Law, but in a more substantive manner under the Formula of the End in Itself. The Categorical Imperative is morality’s supreme principle, in a theoretical sense, because no more fundamental principle logically determines our moral obligations. On the other hand, the Categorical Imperative is also morality’s supreme practical principle, directing human agents to what they must do, regardless of their contingent inclinations. Even though we rarely deploy such general principles explicitly in our moral deliberations, we nevertheless can, according to Kant, deploy the Categorical Imperative to test our maxims and thereby judge what we morally ought to do.9 To interpret Kant as rejecting the possibility of genuine moral dilemmas in this passage is to suppose that Kant’s concern here is with the theoretical standing of the Categorical Imperative. In other words, if the Categorical Imperative were to yield genuine moral dilemmas, its theoretical supremacy would be threatened because the Categorical Imperative itself would yield contradictory moral demands. But I doubt the theoretical standing of the Categorical Imperative is what worries Kant here. Granted, Kant may have naively believed that only a monistic moral theory, i.e., one that offers a single supreme principle, can thereby avoid 9 My way of describing the Categorical Imperative’s two roles is indebted to Robert Stern, “Does ‘ought’ imply ‘can’? And did Kant think it does?” Utilitas 16 (2004), pp. 56-59. 9 generating genuine dilemmas.10 Yet philosophers now recognize that although a logically inconsistent moral theory can yield genuine dilemmas, logical consistency is not sufficient to forestall their existence either. The moral rules ‘defend your country against aggressors’ and ‘care for one’s parents in their old age’ are perfectly consistent but quite capable of generating a moral dilemma, as Sartre’s famous example illustrated.11 Inconsistency can be generated by a theory itself, but it can also be traced to the facts the theory takes as morally salient. 12 Since there is simply no a priori guarantee that the world will cooperate with our best lain moral schemes, the more cunning source of inconsistency, i.e., of genuine moral dilemmas, is the world itself, which so often seems factually arranged to thwart even the most fastidiously consistent moral theory. That the Categorical Imperative is logically consistent is of course a controversial assumption. Doubts may be raised about, for instance, whether its various formulations yield the same verdicts or whether contradictory imperatives result when we attempt to use it to determine what we morally ought to do. But the important point for our purposes is that Kant certainly supposed that his supreme principle of morality was logically consistent in these ways, and if so, then the worries he expressed about the threat genuine moral dilemmas would pose to the intelligibility of morality’s demands are not worries that the Categorical Imperative fails in its theoretical role at identifying the moral attributes of actions. If the theoretical standing of the Categorical Imperative is not what is threatened by genuine moral dilemmas, then Kant’s anxiety must stem from the fear that the Categorical Imperative’s practical supremacy is threatened by genuine moral dilemmas. And there are subtle hints in this 10 See Marcus, “More about moral dilemmas,” p. 25. Moral dilemmas need not result from the presence of distinct rules at all. An agent who promises two distinct parties that she will be at different locations at the same hour appears to face a dilemma rooted in the very same rule to honor one’s promises. 11 See Ruth Barcan Marcus, “Moral dilemmas and consistency,” Journal of Philosophy 77 (1980): 121-136. 12 Mark Timmons, Moral Theory: An Introduction (Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Littlefield, 2002), p.13. 10 passage that this is Kant’s intent. Note first that Kant does not literally deny the existence of genuine dilemmas in this passage. Rather, the existence of moral dilemmas is, Kant says, “inconceivable” in light of the objective practical necessity expressed in the Categorical Imperative, morality’s supreme principle. The existence of moral dilemmas would in effect deny the a priori practical authority of the Categorical Imperative, an authority which, Kant argues in the Groundwork, is evident to common moral understanding. For such a principle to yield two incompatible ‘musts’ need not cast into doubt its theoretical supremacy, but it would stymie our ability to deploy it in identifying what we must do. The “inconceivability” of a “collision of duties” is presumably not the inconceivability of a principle that literally directs us to perform two metaphysically incompatible actions. For the principle in question, the Categorical Imperative, is definitely conceivable. What is inconceivable is that this principle could, in conjunction with the factual circumstances in which we attempt to deploy the principle, could yield metaphysically conflicting imperatives. Throughout the passage, Kant’s language is epistemological or methodological, not metaphysical. For it is the possibility of “certain actions” colliding, actions each of which bear the imprint of objective practical necessity, that piques Kant’s worries. The resolution of moral dilemmas is an requirement emanating from our practical reason. This is why Kant says that “practical philosophy” insists that a stronger ground of obligation must prevail in any apparent moral dilemma. I propose, then, that the thesis of this passage is not that acknowledging the existence of genuine moral dilemmas would be a metaphysical error, a false belief about the nature of moral reality. Rather, accepting the existence of genuine moral dilemmas would be a practical error, in effect denying morality its distinctive normative capacity to guide action. But what is the source or rationale for this practical Kant is clearly indicating that we should accept that there are no 11 dilemmas — that their denial should be treated as true for practical purposes. But why should this be so? We see in the aforementioned passage glimmers of Kant’s characteristic transcendental argumentation: We possess uncontroversial knowledge of a certain kind (of the Categorical Imperative as morality’s supreme principle, in this case), knowledge of which is explicable only if some other claim (that there are no genuine dilemmas) is acknowledged as a necessary condition of the first. But this cannot be quite right, for again, Kant does not seem to be arguing that the Categorical Imperative would not be morality’s supreme principle if there were genuine dilemmas. The problem is instead that we could not coherently treat the Categorical Imperative as the principle that ought to guide our moral deliberations if we assume there are genuine dilemmas. Regardless of whether the Categorical Imperative is morality’s supreme principle, acting as if there are genuine moral dilemmas would make deliberating as if the Categorical Imperative is morality’s supreme principle unintelligible. Perhaps Kant’s denial of moral dilemmas is a practical conclusion akin to his infamous “postulates of practical reason,” conclusions supported not by theoretical reason but by demands of “moral faith.” But this too cannot be quite right. For we are to accept the postulates of God’s existence and the immortality of the soul because these ensure the congruity of happiness and moral virtue that Kant believed constituted the highest good. The acceptance of such a congruity provides us hope in the face of the challenges presented by the evident divergence between happiness and moral virtue in the actual, empirical world. But Kant’s denial of moral dilemmas does not sustain our commitment to morality in the same way. The denial of moral dilemmas assures that morality’s own principle can intelligibly guide choice and action. The practical necessity of this denial is internal to the moral point of view, whereas the practical postulates are 12 necessary to assure us of the harmony of the moral point of view with something only contingently related to it, happiness. Kant’s denial of moral dilemmas is better understood as what Kant termed a “transcendental idea,” a concept originating in reason, the faculty that seeks to unify our understanding under principles.13 As such, transcendental ideas cannot be objectively deduced as the basis of the principles of possible experience, as the transcendental categories can. Nor are there objects in our experience corresponding to such ideas. Transcendental ideas can only be subjectively deduced from the nature of reason itself, and in this case, the denial of moral dilemmas is deduced from the nature of practical reason, and more specifically, from the nature of the demands imposed by the Categorical Imperative as the supreme principle of practical reason. However, the denial of moral dilemmas cannot be known as a matter of synthetic a priori knowledge, nor can it be empirically verified. It is rather an assumption or aspiration that practically rational creatures must bring to their moral deliberation and inquiry in order for their understanding of morality as prescribing categorically to be intelligible. Kant’s denial of moral dilemmas thus reflects reason’s interest in the systematic unity of its knowledge. Reason guides our empirical inquiry, postulating as an ideal the increasing subsumption of our scientific knowledge into fewer and fewer principles so that the necessary connections among the items of our knowledge are apparent.14 In so doing, reason must both assume and aspire to such a unity. Hence, the unity of science sets the philosophical agenda for the conduct of science. The denial of moral dilemmas plays a similar role in the conduct of moral deliberation. It is both an assumption and an aspiration of practical reason that sets the agenda for moral deliberation. Reason, Kant reminds us, always seeks the unconditioned to 13 Critique of Pure Reason, A399/B355-56, A303/B358, A311/B368 14 Critique of Pure Reason (A646-651/B674-80) 13 unify what is conditioned and thus assumes that the unconditioned can be found. The Categorical Imperative is, Kant argues, an unconditional practical demand, but it can only unify or “complete” the various particular moral demands (morality’s innumerable categorical imperatives) if its prescriptions are free of contradiction, i.e., if the non-existence of moral dilemmas is assumed. Kant’s denial of moral dilemmas thus reminds us that Kant believed that the proper use of reason is always “regulative,” not “constitutive.” The principle that there are no genuine moral dilemmas would be constitutive if it provided a real object with which it is assumed to correspond. Yet the point of Kant’s Transcendental Dialectic is that attempts to provide such objects for certain ideas of reason (God, freedom, etc.) inevitably result in contradiction and illusion, thus dooming traditional metaphysics. So, too, presumably for the denial of moral dilemmas in a metaphysical sense: Not only does such a thesis transcend reason’s proper application, it cannot be empirically verified or disconfirmed either. Yet reason must retain a regulative use such that the transcendental ideas orient inquiry and deliberation. Our empirical inquiries would, Kant concludes, be little better than fumbling and groping absent the aspiration for theoretical unity in the sciences. But we cannot in advance, or at any given point, determine whether our scientific understanding has achieved this unity, for there is no standpoint outside our best scientific practices from which we inspect them for this unity. Similarly, the most we can hope for is that the denial of moral dilemmas may be true. But it cannot be legitimately treated as a knowledge claim in a metaphysical sense. Furthermore, there may be no standpoint outside the proper deployment of our moral powers from which we could determine whether an apparent moral dilemma has been fully resolved. The denial of moral dilemmas thus serves as a regulative, rather than constitutive, principle of reason: not a claim 14 known to be true but a condition for the rational application of our knowledge of morality as issuing in categorical rational demands. 3. Two worries One worry here stems from the seemingly ambiguous rational status of the denial of moral dilemmas on my revised Kantian view. I have argued that the denial of moral dilemmas is a regulative principle of practical reason whose authority rests on its being a consequence of our recognition of the Categorical Imperative as practical reason’s supreme principle. But whether there are genuine dilemmas appears to be a theoretical question, a question about whether moral considerations supervene on non-moral ones to generate incompatible imperatives. Thus, it may seem that the position I have attributed to Kant is orthogonal to recent philosophical debates about moral dilemmas. To a large extent, this worry is on target, for the position I have outlined is not a position about how the world is, morally speaking, but a position about the stance we ought to take toward the world in our moral deliberation and inquiry. Yet for Kant, not all metaphysical beliefs or attitudes are settled by theoretical considerations. Practical reason has primacy, according to Kant, such that practical considerations should sometimes guide our beliefs and actions even in the face of evidence against those beliefs or actions. Moreover, since the Categorical Imperative is the supreme principle of practical reason, the interests of theoretical reason may be subordinated to it. In the case of moral dilemmas, then, this primacy mandates that the non-existence of genuine moral dilemmas be assumed, even absent a theoretical demonstration of that thesis. A second worry is that this view of moral dilemmas is far more damaging to Kant’s overall project in ethics than I have acknowledged. In particular, this methodological view weakens 15 Kant’s claim that the Categorical Imperative is the supreme principle of morality. Allowing that we ought to utilize the Categorical Imperative as a principle of deliberation through which we aspire to resolve moral dilemmas, critics may contend that this principle’s supremacy is in doubt if the existence of moral dilemmas is even possible. Yet it is not the case that the Categorical Imperative’s supremacy is threatened by this view of dilemmas. The Categorical Imperative is typically understood as articulating necessary and sufficient logical conditions for the moral permissibility of acting on a maxim, and my position does not cast that into doubt. Nor does it weaken this principle’s claim to having any of the features that Kant seemed to have in mind when he sought morality’s supreme principle: It does not undermine its a priori necessity; its application to all rational agents; its being such that we can abide it motivated by respect for the moral law; its ability to derive a plausible set of moral duties; or its standing as fundamental (i.e., there is not a more basic principle than the Categorical Imperative).15 Admittedly this view of moral dilemmas inserts what Thomas Hill has called “gaps” into Kantian theory, since it concedes that there is a respect in which the Categorical Imperative is not always sufficient, “even given all pertinent facts about a case,” to determine “for all acts whether they are obligatory, forbidden, or neither.”16 For this regulative ideal may be unrealized when we confront an apparent dilemma where the options end up in a tie after full moral deliberation. But Kantianism’s inability to eliminate all such gaps does not show that the theory or its supreme principle fail to be action-guiding. Not to be uniquely action-guiding is not to be non-actionguiding simpliciter, and nothing in this revisionary Kantian view necessitates our relinquishing the Kantian thesis that the “primary function of moral judgments … is to express rational 15 These are among the conditions that Samuel Kerstein, Kant’s Search for the Supreme Principle of Morality (Cambridge: Cambridge U. Press, 2002) argues Kant intended to capture in a supreme principle of morality. 16 Hill, “Moral dilemmas, gaps, and residues,” p. 179. 16 demands on our wills as deliberating agents, telling us which among our (perceived) options to choose to take.”17 In sum then: In terms of Kant’s famous three central questions for reason — what can I know, what ought I do, and what may I hope— the answers with respect to moral dilemmas are: 1. We can know a priori that reason assumes and aspires to the denial of genuine moral dilemmas, but we cannot know whether that denial is in fact true. Nor can we come to know with certainty that an apparent moral dilemma has been correctly resolved, for we have no standpoint outside our practical reason from which to appraise such resolutions. 2. We ought to deliberate and inquire in moral matters on the assumption that there are no genuine moral dilemmas – that every apparent dilemma is resolvable. 3. We may reasonably hope that the world is not fundamentally dilemmatic in character. The revisionary Kantian position I have outlined has a number of modest, and thereby attractive, features. It neither asserts nor denies the existence of genuine moral dilemmas, but instead takes the resolution of moral dilemmas as a methodological ideal. However, advocates of non-agnostic views of genuine moral dilemmas — those philosophers who defend or deny their existence— may be happy to accommodate my methodological view. For its very modesty does not impugn, and is in fact consistent with, either non-agnostic view. Hence, my revisionary Kantian view may appear to complement non-agnostic views rather than being a philosophical rival to them. However, this would not be the case if there were independent reasons to favor the revisionary Kantian position over its non-agnostic rivals. And if we can explain a body of phenomena solely in terms of our epistemic or rational commitments rather than reverting to a 17 Hill, “Moral dilemmas, gaps, and residues,” p. 175. 17 controversial metaphysical hypothesis, we should do so. In the next three sections, I argue that the revisionary Kantian position has the advantage that it can better explain several central dimensions of our experience of moral dilemmas than can its non-agnostic rivals. 4. Explaining the phenomenology, part I: Moral residue and rational self-reproach As one might expect, my revisionary Kantian position is skeptical of arguments, whether empirical or a priori, intended to establish whether or not genuine moral dilemmas exist. Such arguments can nevertheless appeal to premises that reflect central dimensions of our experience of moral dilemmas. The best-known example of such an argument is Bernard Williams’ argument from ‘moral residue.’18 This argument attempts to demonstrate that in order for the reactive attitudes we often have after we act in dilemmas to be rational, there must in fact be genuine moral dilemmas. More specifically, when an agent acts in response to an apparent moral dilemma, she is rightly subject to self-reproach in the form of various negative self-appraisals (regret, guilt, remorse, etc.), regardless of which of the two acts she performed. But these selfappraisals are rational or justified only if the agent would have been equally rational or justified had she acted to fulfill the other apparent obligation that bound her in the dilemma. Since these self-appraisals are appropriate only when an agent acts wrongly, it follows that the agent could not have failed to act wrongly and was therefore in a genuine moral dilemma. Put more formally: 1. Suppose S is in an apparent moral dilemma, compelling her either to do A or to do B. 2. Regardless of whether S does A or B, S will undergo rational self-reproach. 3. Self-reproach is rational only if S acts wrongly (i.e., S violated a moral obligation). 4. Thus, regardless of whether S does A or B, S will have acted wrongly. 18 “Ethical consistency,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society supp. 39 (1965): 103-24. 18 S’s situation is a genuine moral dilemma (since she cannot avoid acting wrongly). Skeptics about moral dilemmas typically object to the moral residue argument by rejecting premise 3 on the grounds that the rationality of these negative self-appraisals does not entail that an agent acted wrongly. For one thing, much will depend on the exact negative selfappraisals in question. Some such self-appraisals (e.g., guilt) imply wrongdoing, but others (regret) do not. Furthermore, it can be rational for agents to experience negative self-appraisals that imply wrongdoing even when agents accept they did not act wrongly.19 Such self-reproach could motivate agents to compensate (or seek the forgiveness of) those they injure as a result of acting in a dilemma or motivate agents to fashion social institutions and circumstances that do not tend to put individuals in dilemmas in the first place. Hence, considerations of social welfare make self-reproach rational even when agents do not in fact violate any obligations in the course of acting to resolve a dilemma. I follow opponents of genuine dilemmas in concluding that these objections to the moral residue argument show the moral residue argument to be unsound: premise 3 is not the only credible explanation for the truth of premise 2, and in general, using our experience of moral dilemmas to diagnose the existence of genuine dilemmas looks like a hasty leap from phenomenology (or epistemology) to metaphysics. (And if my revisionary Kantian view is correct, all such leaps will be illicit.) However, rather than resting satisfied with an apparent refutation of the moral residue argument, I wish to shift focus to the common ground that unites advocates of the moral residue argument and its critics, namely, its second premise. Both accept 19 See among other responses, Terrance McConnell, “Moral dilemmas and consistency in ethics,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 8 (1978): 269-87; Barcan Marcus, “Moral dilemmas and consistency”; Earl Conee, “Against moral dilemmas,” Philosophical Review 91 (1982): 87-97; Philippa Foot, “Moral realism and moral dilemma,” Journal of Philosophy 80 (1983): 379-98; and McConnell, “Moral residue and dilemmas,” p. 38. 19 that after acting in an apparent moral dilemma, an agent may be subject to rational self-reproach, regardless of which act she performs. Even after doing what we believe we ought to have done in resolving a moral dilemma, we rarely feel pleasure or a sense of emphatic selfcongratulation.20 Granting that the existence of genuine moral dilemmas is a problematic explanation of this rational self-reproach, what view of moral dilemmas would explain this fact? There are two specific features of premise 2 that require explanation. The first is that the rationality of this self-reproach is intrinsic to it inasmuch as it is, or results from, retrospective judgments of moral dilemmas themselves and how agents acted in those dilemmas. Skeptics about moral dilemmas, as I mentioned above, attempt to explain how such rational self-reproach is justified, regardless of which course of action a person takes in an apparent dilemma, by claiming that making amends to those injured, trying to reform social institutions so as to reduce the frequency of dilemmas, etc., are rational responses to the experience of dilemmas. A physician who experiences negative self-appraisals after finding herself in too many moral dilemmas concerning end of life care may then advocate for better palliative care so as to minimize future dilemmas of this kind. Doubtless, responses such as making amends and the like can be supported by moral reasons, and in this sense, the dilemmas have a causal role in the history of these responses. But this is quite different from a rational response to dilemmas themselves, and it is the rationality of self-reproach itself, not the rationality of how we act in the wake of such self-reproach, that advocates of the moral residue argument seek to explain in terms of the existence of genuine dilemmas. Advocates of the moral residue argument thus see the 20 Daniel Markovits, “The architecture of integrity” in D. Callcut (ed.) Reading Bernard Williams (London: Routledge 2009), p. 114, makes this same observation in connection with how consequentialists analyze Bernard Williams’ infamous ‘Jim and Pedro’ example — that “having killed one, Jim might congratulate himself on saving nineteen lives.” 20 rationality of self-reproach as justified retrospectively, as involving the proper cognition or appreciation of dilemmas and how best to resolve them. What makes guilt, remorse, etc., rational, they argue, is that they incorporate accurate cognitions both of the moral considerations that constitute moral dilemmas and of how to act when facing moral dilemmas. In contrast, skeptics about genuine dilemmas explain the rationality of self-reproach prospectively, in terms of how agents respond, rationally-cum-morally, to having been in apparent moral dilemmas. But this is the wrong kind of explanation (moral, rather than epistemic) of the rationality of this selfreproach and it targets the wrong explanandum (our moral responses to our judgments concerning moral dilemmas, rather than the judgments themselves). Skeptics about genuine dilemmas may reply that they can explain this rational self-reproach in other ways, however. Regardless of how agents react to having been in dilemmas (whether they try to avoid such dilemmas in the future, etc.), agents undergo rational self-reproach when they believe they judged a dilemma wrongly. If, as skeptics believe, there are no genuine dilemmas, then an agent who concludes that she opted for the wrong course of action ought to feel selfreproach. Suppose that agent S does B in an apparent dilemma, when in reality, she was obligated to A, and S later comes to realize this fact. In such a case, rational self-reproach would clearly be warranted. But this reply is inadequate, for in endorsing premise 2, skeptics about dilemmas are conceding that this rational self-reproach does not depend on whether an agent believes she erred in evaluating a dilemma. The self-reproach is supposed to be rational irrespective of whether an agent believes she acted properly in resolving the dilemma. Thus, even if believing one erred might be part of the explanation for rational self-reproach in some cases where agents were compelled to act in a dilemma, it cannot be the full explanation. Furthermore, this only deepens the puzzle about providing a comprehensive explanation of 21 rational self-reproach: If the self-reproach is rational in the sense that if involves a cognition or judgment of the dilemma and how to resolve it, then it would appear that agents’ self-reproach must rest on their judgments that they erred in evaluating or responding to the dilemma (or both). But self-reproach does not appear to hinge on agents’ judgments about whether they erred in evaluating or responding to a dilemma. Although the self-appraisals we experience after acting in a dilemma are to some extent sensitive to our judgments about whether we engaged in wrongdoing, there often are, as Patricia Greenspan has suggested, agents who feel guilt without having a corresponding judgment of fault or wrongdoing.21 But the rationality of such selfreproach is precisely the fact in need of explanation, and for agents to suffer an “uneasy conscience” even when they correctly judge both that their situation was not a genuine dilemma and that they acted correctly in that situation is actually irrational. We will return to this first feature in a moment, but the perplexity about rational selfreproach only deepens when we consider a second important feature of it: The reproach is reproach of the self.22 But neither non-agnostic view of moral dilemmas illuminates how the agent herself is an object of reproach after she acts to resolve a moral dilemma. There is something insufficiently reflexive about explaining these self-appraisals by proposing that there are moral dilemmas. For these are negative self-appraisals, and there need be no failure (epistemic, moral, or otherwise) on the part of an agent if these negative attitudes reflect a disjointed moral world populated by genuine moral dilemmas. That an agent is, in a sense, trapped by a genuine moral dilemma is not a rational basis for negatively appraising the agent (aside from dilemmas that are the agent’s own making). Indeed, an agent who concludes that she 21 Practical Guilt: Moral Dilemmas, Emotions, and Social Norms (Oxford: Oxford U. Press, 1995), p. 151. 22 Greenspan is one of the few philosophers to take much stock of the specifically self-directed character of dilemmatic moral residue. See Practical Guilt: Moral Dilemmas, Emotions, and Social Norms, p. 135. 22 was in a genuine dilemma may in fact experience the opposite of such negative self-appraisals. She may instead feel a sense of relief that there was, in an important sense, no way not to have done wrong. On the other hand, we have already observed that skeptics about moral dilemmas can argue that reproach directed at the self is appropriate if an agent concludes she erred in evaluating or responding to a dilemma. But even here it is not entirely clear that an agent who believes she erred in evaluating or responding to a dilemma ought to feel self-reproach. For a failed effort to resolve what is assumed to be in principle resolvable need not reflect negatively on an individual. Suppose that arithmetic is such that all its theorems are provable. Nevertheless, there are theorems whose proofs cannot be readily identified. The proof of Fermat’s last theorem eluded generations of brilliant mathematicians, for example. Now imagine such a mathematician felt self-reproach because she inferred that because of (a) the in principle provability of all theorems, and (b) her own inability to prove Fermat’s theorem despite her using sound disciplinary methodology, etc., that she must therefore have erred in some way she is unable to detect. Such self-reproach would not be a rational response to her failed efforts. It would instead amount to self-flagellation. Some problems in mathematics are sufficiently daunting that erring in evaluating or responding to them does not impugn mathematicians who so err. After all, even Andrew Wiles, the mathematician who ultimately proved Fermat’s last theorem, said it was to some degree due to luck. So too for morality: There are some moral dilemmas, apparent or otherwise, that are sufficiently daunting that erring in evaluating or responding to them does not impugn agents who so err. If Sophie in Styron’s novel Sophie’s Choice chose the wrong child to send to the gas chambers, would anyone hold this against her? If this is correct, however, 23 regardless of whether there are no genuine moral dilemmas, rational self-reproach does not hinge on whether agents believe they succeeded in resolving a dilemma. Thus, the rationality of self-reproach is therefore not contingent on whether genuine moral dilemmas exist23 or even whether agents believe they deliberated correctly in their efforts to resolve dilemmas. Thus, the rationality of this self-reproach cannot be located either in the metaphysical facts about the existence of genuine moral dilemmas or in the properties of agents’ specific deliberative or epistemic performances. It seems as if this rational self-reproach is not the product of substantive irrationality, since it does not depend on agents’ getting moral reality right. But nor is it the product of procedural irrationality, since it does not necessarily depend on how well agents deliberate or act in their efforts to get moral reality right. Is the rationality of self-reproach just inexplicable then? No. The Kantian position I have outlined, despite taking no stand on the metaphysics of moral dilemmas, nevertheless provides an explanation of why such negative self-appraisals may be rationally warranted regardless of whether genuine moral dilemmas exist and regardless of whether agents believe they have successfully resolved a dilemma. As a regulative ideal, the denial of dilemmas is implicitly accepted by all moral agents as a norm of reason. It is thus the agents’ own deliberative moral ideal. Thus, when an agent finds herself in what appears to be an especially confounding dilemma, it would not, I contend, be irrational for such an agent to later experience the negative self-appraisals allegedly associated with the existence of moral dilemmas. Moral agents aspire to have their conduct guided by the categoricity of moral demands, but hard cases can make it unclear in which acts that categoricity resides. We are, Kant claimed, capable of the distinctly moral emotion of reverence for the moral law. To worry that we have not identified what the 23 Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, Moral Dilemmas (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1988), pp. 46-47. 24 moral law asks of us thus sparks a rational anxiety that manifests itself as self-reproach. Moral residue thus induces the sense that we have let morality let down. Yet Kant’s conception of morality is that it emanates from our own autonomous, practically rational nature. Thus, to worry that one may have acted immorally by choosing the wrong horn of an apparent moral dilemma is to let oneself down. It is the moral law within and not the starry heavens above that generates this self-reproach. A negative moral appraisal is thus implicitly a negative selfappraisal. Hence, the regulative ideal implicit in agents’ deliberation explains how agents are subject to negative appraisals directed specifically at the self as a moral agent. Furthermore, the regulative ideal pinpoints what makes this self-reproach rational. It is neither that, because there are no genuine dilemmas, agents must have fallen short in the resolution of apparent dilemmas despite their best deliberative and epistemic efforts. Nor is that agents must have deliberated or reasoned badly. Instead, as dilemmas increase in their apparent intractability, concern that the regulative ideal will not be realized increases in proportion. This concern is not rooted in the firm belief either that genuine dilemmas do not exist or that agents have not on a particular occasion actually resolved a dilemma. Agents’ self-reproach is rational because especially daunting dilemmas put the realizability of this regulative ideal in doubt. 5. Explaining the phenomenology, part II: Attitudinal ambivalence As noted above, the negative self-appraisals individuals may experience once they act within an apparent moral dilemma are numerous. They include guilt, shame, regret, and remorse, as well as attitudes or intentions that flow from these self-appraisals, such as desires to make amends to injured parties and to seek their forgiveness and understanding. Furthermore, only some of these carry the suggestion that an individual violated a moral obligation. A person 25 ought to feel guilt, for example, only on the condition that she violated an obligation, but if she did not, an appraisal such as regret is more appropriate. Some of these (a desire to make amends to injured parties, for instance) may be appropriate regardless of whether an obligation was violated. But taxonomizing these self-appraisals and attitudes in terms of their relationship to moral wrongdoing is one matter. Deciphering which ones are appropriate to attribute to oneself in a given context is another. For one thing, they do not necessarily have sufficiently distinct phenomenological profiles to enable us to identify which of them we are in fact undergoing in a given instance. Guilt and shame, on the one hand, and regret on the other, are all species of ‘feeling bad’ for what one has done. But the anguish associated with these is often so inchoate that introspection cannot tell us which of these self-appraisals is most fitting in the wake of our having acted in an apparent moral dilemma. Our emotional discernment is simply not that finetuned.24 This phenomenological coarseness may be inevitable. Perhaps it serves an important developmental or evolutionary function. (The analogous phenomenon of survivor guilt, despite not being a form of guilt, could be an evolutionary byproduct, an emotion that enhances solidarity and social responsibility even when blame is not justified.) Yet when we act in a situation that seems to us like a moral dilemma, we often do not have confidence after the fact how we feel, or ought to feel, about our actions. Normative and descriptive self-interrogation become intertwined here, as we simultaneously attempt to discern what we feel and evaluate the fittingness of what we feel. We can of course have recourse to the dilemma itself, again sifting through the facts that gave rise to it, the moral considerations speaking in favor of each course of action, etc. But as I 24 McConnell, “Moral residue and dilemmas,” p. 39. 26 have argued, an agent thrown back on the dilemma may still find it troubling even in retrospect, a fact which generates the moral anxiety that grounds these negative self-appraisals. In that case, intractable ambivalence about the dilemma not only occurs, but is a warranted response. My revisionary Kantian view has a ready explanation for the rationality of this ambivalence. It stems from ambiguity about the dilemmas themselves. The regulative ideal that denies the existence of genuine dilemmas, and to which we are committed just insofar as we are practically rational agents, collides with situations in which dilemmas are difficult to resolve. Our agential aspirations clash with moral reality, but with no obvious path indicating whether it is the aspirations or moral reality that must give way. In contrast, non-agnostic views of moral dilemmas — those claiming that there are or there are not genuine dilemmas — must ultimately dismiss this ambivalence. For on either nonagnostic view, additional information or moral insight can, in every instance and in principle at least, be mustered to answer the metaphysical question of whether an individual was in a genuine dilemma. And once mustered, this information or insight directs the agent to the appropriate appraisals or attitudes (guilt, say, if the dilemma stands, mere regret if it does not). The resolution of the metaphysical uncertainty in turn resolves the phenomenological ambivalence. But my revisionary Kantian view honors the rationality of this ambivalence and does not seek to argue it away prematurely. 6. Explaining the phenomenology, part III: Self-other asymmetry This revisionary Kantian view also helps explain a third feature of our experience of dilemmas. 27 Our reactions to apparent dilemmas exhibit an asymmetry. As described earlier, from the first-personal standpoint of the person whose dilemma it is, the aftermath of a dilemma often brings self-reproach, a fact that my revisionary Kantian view is able to explain. However, for third parties to hold similarly reproachful attitudes about how other agents acted in response to moral dilemmas seems less appropriate. The proper responses to other people having confronted apparent moral dilemmas include sympathy and solidarity, rather than condemnation or emphatic judgment. Sympathetic third parties may well have opinions concerning how the dilemma was best resolved, and it would not be inappropriate to provide those opinions if, for example, the agent who was in the dilemma sought advice or insight after the fact. But the impulse to evaluate the conduct of the agent in the dilemma is properly subordinated to less epistemically grounded responses such as sympathy and solidarity. There is, then, an asymmetry between first-personal responses to moral dilemmas and third personal responses to dilemmas. Let us call the appropriate first-personal response the verdictive standpoint and the appropriate third-personal response the sympathetic standpoint. This attitudinal asymmetry is difficult to explain. One possible explanation for this asymmetry is epistemic: ‘Outsiders’ to a dilemma may believe that they have insufficient understanding of the situation to form a reasoned moral judgment about the dilemma (or at least not the level of understanding that the individual in the dilemma has simply by virtue by being in it). Hence, the inappropriateness of outsiders’ adopting the verdictive standpoint, and the corresponding appropriateness of the sympathetic standpoint, reflect outsiders’ reasoned suspension of judgment, i.e., they simply do not know enough to form a reasoned moral judgment (or their judgments cannot be as well-grounded as the judgments of the individual in the dilemma). But this too cannot be the explanation of this asymmetry. For these third-party 28 attitudes do not spring from a outright suspension of judgment. Third party sympathy and solidarity are not contingent on third parties’ own judgment concerning how the dilemma is best resolved. An outsider may have just as much information or moral probity as the agent actually in the dilemma and come to conscientiously agree or disagree with the actions taken by that agent. But sympathy or solidarity are called for in either case. That this asymmetry does not stem from third-parties’ epistemic perspective on the dilemma does not mean that others’ judgments concerning the dilemma place no limits on how they respond. Third parties must at least think that the individual is in at least an apparent dilemma — that she is confronting a ‘hard case,’ so to speak — in order to feel sympathy or solidarity with her. A dogmatic moral opponent of abortion, for instance, may not feel sympathy for an agent who, caught in an apparent dilemma, opts for an abortion. After all, for the opponent of abortion, the situation does not even present an apparent dilemma.25 Another tempting explanation is that this asymmetry is only superficial. While it may not be appropriate for individuals to assert or express critical or judgmental attitudes about how others respond to dilemmas, one might argue, it is not inappropriate for third parties to have such attitudes. Rather, the appropriate attitudes to express are those of sympathy or solidarity, regardless of whether these are one’s true attitudes. But this cannot be the correct explanation either. For one thing, a person who has unsympathetic attitudes may experience self-reproach of her own simply for having those attitudes. In other words, a person may subject herself to selfcriticism because she wishes she felt sympathy or solidarity in response to another person’s 25 In any event, our sympathy or solidarity for those who must act in difficult moral dilemmas does not immediately follow upon an epistemic suspension of judgment concerning such dilemmas. For one can lack both the verdictive response and the sympathetic response.. Hence, whatever considerations militate against the verdictive response, those considerations do not suffice for the sympathetic response. 29 dilemma, while in actuality she is indifferent or even harshly judgmental. This indicates that whatever may be wrong with expressing verdictive responses, its wrongness supervenes on having those responses in the first place. Lastly, one might think that the third-personal sympathy, etc., occur because third parties recognize that agents in apparent dilemmas often have their own interests or concerns at stake in those dilemmas. For example, one reason to sympathize with Sophie is that one of her children had to die, regardless of how she responded to her dilemma. Certainly sympathy for other agents’ anguish or suffering is usually justified. But this cannot be the whole picture, for not all moral dilemmas are self-affecting in this way. Physicians, military leaders, or educators may confront moral dilemmas in which their own concerns or interests are not implicated, and yet sympathy and solidarity still seem to be appropriate response by third parties. Furthermore, our sympathies for those in self-affecting dilemmas extend beyond what happens to them. They extend to what they must do. For imagine if Sophie were not made to choose between her children, but instead, a Nazi officer simply killed one of her children. Sympathy and solidarity for her loss would of course be justified in that case. But if Sophie herself is made to choose which of her children should die, there is an additional set of reactive attitudes we ought to feel as a response to her having been placed in a dilemma. Our sympathy, solidarity, etc., reflect not simply what happened to her, but also how her agency became entangled in a dilemma such that what happened became the product of her agency. Of course, a number of factors may rightfully mitigate our sympathy with those in moral dilemmas. For instance, our sympathies lessen if the dilemma is of the agent’s own making (if, by having chosen differently in the past, she might have avoided the dilemma altogether). But explaining this asymmetry is challenging, and the non-agnostic rivals to my revisionary Kantian 30 view succeed in explaining only half of the asymmetry. The thesis that there are no genuine moral dilemmas helps to explain the first-personal verdictive standpoint. Since there are no genuine dilemmas, agents in apparent moral dilemmas strive to resolve them, and this necessarily involves arriving at justifiable verdicts concerning how one acts (or acted) in a dilemma. However, the thesis that there are no genuine moral dilemmas can only explain thirdpersonal sympathy in the very epistemic terms I have already suggested are inadequate. For if there are no moral dilemmas, why should we have sympathy for another person’s being in a dilemma aside from our being impressed with the difficulty of adjudicating the dilemma? Conversely, that there are genuine dilemmas can explain third-personal sympathy but not the first-personal verdictive standpoint. Those who are not party to a dilemma justifiably experience a sense of its injustice to the individual whose dilemma it is. But if a situation is a genuine dilemma, the agent whose dilemma it is has comparatively little basis for self-criticism. Being concerned to get a dilemma right is intelligible only if there is a unique something to be gotten right, which is not the case in a genuine moral dilemma. Thus, the non-agnostic views about moral dilemmas can only account for different halves of this attitudinal asymmetry. However, if the denial of dilemmas is merely a regulative ideal, then an explanation for this asymmetry itself comes into view. I have argued that practically rational agents, as Kant understood them, accept the resolution of moral dilemmas as a constitutive aim of their practical deliberation. However, this claim is ambiguous. The notion of a moral dilemma can be analyzed in terms of situations where individuals function as variables, i.e., a situation is a moral dilemma iff any agent S in that situation would be subject to incompatible claims of obligation. But this characterization is clearly inadequate. For one thing, not just any agent S will be in a dilemma if placed in such a situation. In some cases, features 31 specific to S (her profession, her loyalties, etc.) determine whether or not the situation is a dilemma in the first place. More fundamentally, every dilemma is someone’s dilemma. If there are simply no possible agents for whom a situation would appear to generate incompatible obligations, that situation is not a moral dilemma. At root, moral dilemmas are relations between individuals and their circumstances so that talk of a situation’s being a dilemma must ultimately be analyzable in terms of someone’s being in a dilemma. Moral dilemmas are thus fundamentally local. And just as we can speak of headaches in the generic, so too can we speak of situations as dilemmas, but we should not be deceived into believing that dilemmas exist independently of the agents whose dilemmas they are anymore than we should be deceived into believing that headaches exist independently of those individuals whose headaches they are. In claiming that moral dilemmas are fundamentally someone’s dilemmas, I do not intend to deny that some moral dilemmas present themselves to agents in concert. Many quite ordinary moral decisions (for instance, how much to provide others by way of charity) invite dilemmas for many agents. In fact, some of the most unsettling dilemmas involve multiple agents because they are symmetrical. Individuals in the stereotypical ‘desert island’ scenario may each be torn between their morally justifiable interest in survival and their moral reservations about the use of violence to secure the means to that survival. Nor am I suggesting that moral dilemmas should be approached solipsitically, as if each apparent dilemma is so novel that agents should not draw upon moral insights learned from prior dilemmas. Nevertheless, this picture of the ontology of dilemmas — that dilemmas qua relations are prior to dilemmas qua generic situations — bears on how we should understand the rationality of the prerogative associated with the regulative Kantian ideal I have defended. 32 I have argued that the denial of moral dilemmas is a regulative ideal that both structures and motivates moral deliberation and that this is an ideal for practically rational agents who seek to govern their conduct in accordance with morality’s categorical demands. If moral dilemmas were fundamentally generic situations, then the reasons that underlie this regulative ideal might appear to be agent-neutral. As Phillip Pettit describes it, an agent-neutral reason is a reason that can be fully specified without irreducible indexical reference to an individual.26 If the rationality of the regulative ideal consisted in providing agents with agent-neutral reasons to resolve moral dilemmas, then an agent’s relation to the reasons she has for seeking to resolve dilemmas is strictly incidental. She happens to find herself in moral dilemmas due to contingent facts, and her reason for seeking to resolve these dilemmas is that moral dilemmas ought to be resolved. In contrast, since moral dilemmas are fundamentally relational, an agent has agent-relative reasons to seek to resolve those dilemmas she finds herself in, where an agent-relative reason is “one that cannot be fully specified without pronominal back-reference to the person for whom it is a reason.” In other words, that a moral dilemma is her dilemma is part of the rational force behind her aspiration to resolve the dilemma. The reasons generated by the regulative ideal that denies genuine moral dilemmas are agent-relative. That is, aside from the substantive moral considerations associated with the dilemma itself (that, depending on which course of action the agent takes, a person may be injured, a promise may be broken, etc.), which may provide either agent-relative or agent-neutral reasons for action, an agent aspires to resolve a moral dilemma for reasons that are irreducibly hers, and more exactly, because the dilemma is normatively realized by her involvement in it. 26 “Universality without universalism,” Mind 72 (1987), p. 75. 33 At the same time, however, each moral agent has the resolution of the dilemmas in which she finds herself as an aim of her practical deliberation. Hence, each agent has agent-relative reasons to seek the resolution of her dilemmas. Thus, the regulative ideal that denies, for practical purposes, the existence of genuine moral dilemmas is a universal but agent-relative norm. It is a norm grounded in the common, constitutive agential features of rational humans who acknowledge the categoricity of morality’s demands.27 This way of understanding the normativity of the denial of moral dilemmas allows us to explain the aforementioned asymmetry between the verdictive first-personal standpoint and the sympathetic third-personal standpoint on moral dilemmas. The verdictive quality of our firstpersonal responses to the moral dilemmas we find ourselves in is a reflection of the rational aspiration to resolve all such dilemmas in accordance with the Kantian regulative ideal. Yet when we encounter others in moral dilemmas, our acceptance of this regulative ideal elicits our sympathy because we see other agents in morally fraught situations structurally analogous to those we know or can imagine. To focus attention principally on the epistemic or moral aptness of the verdicts others reach in their dilemmas is to adopt, however implicitly, the stance that their agent-relative reasons that animate their desire to resolve their dilemmas are our reasons too — that their reasons are not simply analogous to ours, but are ours, with the result that we should adopt the deliberative first-personal standpoint that strives to resolve the dilemmas. Thus, we engage in a kind of bracketing of our epistemic and moral judgment of others, without fully renouncing our own judgment. 27 The sort of reason is similar to what Christine Korsgaard has called a “mixed reason.” See her “Reasons we can share: An attack on the distinction between agent-neutral and agent-relative values,” in her Creating the Kingdom of Ends (Cambridge: Cambridge U. Press, 1996), p. 288. 34 In this respect, though the regulative ideal I have defended is methodological rather than being a substantive moral principle of its own, it nevertheless has moral implications. When agents in moral dilemmas adopt the verdictive standpoint toward their own decisions and conduct, and when third parties adopt the sympathetic standpoint toward those decisions and that conduct, they respectively exhibit the Kantian virtue that Jeanine Grenberg has called “proper humility.” Agents with proper humility are aware of their limitations as moral agents, and thus manifest humility. Yet at the same time, they enjoy self-respect that grounds their recognition of their worth as moral agents and their entitlement to claim morally decent treatment from others. Proper humility combines these attributes resulting in a “meta-attitude” wherein the rational agent perceives herself as “dependent and corrupt” but “capable and dignified”28 in striving to honor the moral principles she takes as her own. The regulative ideal that denies moral dilemmas is characteristic of Kantian agents with proper humility. Such agents are committed to resolve moral dilemmas because they are committed to the often daunting task of according their conduct with the supreme principle of morality. Agents with proper humility therefore see other agents entangled in moral dilemmas not as their inferiors but as engaged in a common, and humbling, human endeavor. Indeed, it would be wrong for them to judge others’ reactions too harshly, for that would run afoul of their duty “to sympathize actively in [others’] fate.”29 In so doing, they judge themselves not in relation to one another but in relation to the supreme principle of morality they and other rational agents accept. Having developed the instinct of conscience, the instinct to “to direct oneself according to moral laws,”30 such agents 28 Kant and the Ethics of Humility (Cambridge: Cambridge U. Press, 2005), p. 133. 29 Kant, Metaphysics of Morals 6:457 30 Lectures on Ethics 27:351 35 thereby spurn “moral egoism”31 and enjoy “moral self-esteem”32. As Grenberg explains it, this proper appreciation of moral principles transcends the self in that it transcends particular agents’ perspectives. But we do not transcend our selves entirely since moral principles, including the denial of moral dilemmas as a practical implication of the categoricity of the moral law, are autonomously given. The denial of moral dilemmas thus provides a standard that instead of being “foreign, other, inaccessible, and truly not one’s own,” is a standard to which we aspire because it is a consequent of the moral law. The Kantian regulative ideal is thus a transcendent and “simultaneously local” standard whose authority is rooted in the “self-evaluation of a person claiming status as a rational being.”33 The regulative ideal I have defended does not logically preclude non-agnostic views of moral dilemmas. Nevertheless, the phenomenology of moral dilemmas suggest that the revisionary Kantian view more fruitfully and parsimoniously accounts for central features of our experience of moral dilemmas than do non-agnostic views. 7. Conclusion Since my thesis is unorthodox both as an interpretation of Kant and as a position concerning moral dilemmas, its practical implications could easily be misunderstood. I do not claim that every apparent dilemma is a genuine one. Many apparent dilemmas will turn out to be resolvable once we come into possession of additional facts, refine the maxims we are considering acting upon, etc. Some apparent dilemmas could in fact be genuine dilemmas. Some will prove irresolvable in practice even under optimum epistemic and deliberative conditions. 31 Lectures on Ethics 27:359 32 Lectures on Ethics 27:349 33 Grenberg, Kant and the Ethics of Humility, p. 142. 36 We simply cannot know in advance and without careful attention to contextual detail whether or not an apparent dilemma will prove resolvable. For that fact will, in these instances, not be one to which we finite rational agents have access. Remaining agnostic about the metaphysics of genuine moral dilemmas while treating the denial of dilemmas as a methodological precept permits us to steer clear of two conclusions that Kantians ought to hold in suspicion. If genuine moral dilemmas exist, then the enterprise of conforming our conduct to the Categorical Imperative’s categorical demands is undermined. The very goal of a “metaphysics of morals” becomes untenable. On the other hand, a sweeping denial that genuine moral dilemmas exist requires an unwarranted confidence in our rational and moral powers, a kind of arrogance that flies in the face of our own moral experience. Thus, if my revisionary Kantian view is at all plausible, it represents an intriguing hybrid of the experimentalist and rationalist orientations. In treating the denial of dilemmas as a regulative ideal rooted in practical reason, my view reveals a commitment to the rationalist aspiration for systematize our moral judgments. Yet the revisionary Kantian view also honors the “the standpoint of the moral experience of persons” and the “circumstances of perplexity and choice.” Indeed, it provides a more accurate account of this standpoint and of the circumstances of perplexity and choice than does its more metaphysically ambitious rivals. Conversely, despite its Kantian heritage, my position is not one which moral theorists in other traditions ought to reject ab initio. Moral inquiry and moral deliberation presuppose, and aspire to, the resolution of any apparent dilemmas that arise in the course of these endeavors. This claim is relatively uncontroversial and should not invite hostility from non-Kantians. Of course, some moral theories may be inhospitable to the possibility of moral dilemmas. Actconsequentialism, for instance, permits numerical ties between alternative courses of action, but 37 does not treat these actions as representing a dilemma but as representing equally defensible options. And while I believe that such non-agnostic theories become less plausible in light of the phenomenological advantages that my revisionary Kantian view offers, even these non-agnostic theories need not reject the regulative ideal. Moreover, although the claims that moral inquiry and moral deliberation presuppose and aspire to the resolution of moral dilemmas, and that this regulative ideal stems from a rationalist aspiration to systematize our moral understanding, are claims that are most at home in a Kantian framework, they are intelligible within other theories too. The rational aspiration to resolve moral dilemmas is rooted in a yearning to govern our conduct by morality’s demands and is hence an expression of the autonomy of practical reason. However, this does not necessitate that the content of morality’s demands be grounded in that autonomy, as Kantians do. Nor am I making the implausible claim that moral agency as such requires acknowledgment of the moral ideal. Dogmatists and ideologues will deny the possibility of such dilemmas, and I do not deny that dogmatists and ideologues are moral agents. However, if moral agents acknowledge even the appearance of moral dilemmas, they shall find themselves compelled by the regulative ideal I have identified to deploy their moral powers in the service of these dilemmas being resolved. Most importantly, my revisionary Kantian view explains why the appearance, if not the actuality, of moral dilemmas causes us to undergo a feeling of rationally justified dismay directed not at the world but at ourselves insofar as morality is an enterprise rooted in our own rational self-governance. As a prominent Kantian has written: Life does prey on life; nature is a scene of suffering; if those things are repugnant to human moral standards, then the world is set up in a way that we must deplore, but in which we must nevertheless participate. But on a Kantian conception of morality, this objection is not to the purpose. For Kant 38 believed that moral standards, like all rational standards, are essentially human standards, and there is no guarantee that the world will meet them, or make it possible for us to do so. 34 At the same time, my account permits a guarded optimism about our ability to make moral reality tractable by resolving each and every moral dilemma. In this regard, the revisionary Kantian view I have defended reflects the sentiments that our knowledge of morality as issuing in categorical demands should guide our action, so that reason compels us to exercise our moral capacities to the utmost and thereby seek to resolve the apparent moral dilemmas we confront, regardless of whether the world is ultimately constituted so as to thwart our rational aspirations. 34 Christine Korsgaard, “Fellow creatures: Kantian ethics and our duties to animals,” Tanner Lectures on Human Values (delivered at the University of Michigan, 2004), p. 35. 39