1 Exclusion for Democracy? Adam James Tebble, Department of Political Science, Brown University Young women march against verbal and physical abuse for wearing revealing clothing on the streets of major urban centres. Gay and lesbian activists blow whistles and wave placards denouncing the withdrawal of gay awareness programmes in schools and universities, whilst outraged university students unfurl banners depicting the last gruesome moments of animals undergoing ritual slaughter. Citizens of all ages, income groups and both sexes march against the erosion of their culture, racism in employment practice and education and the failure of the state to ensure homeland security. All chant the slogan: “Identity, Democracy and Justice”. The images are familiar, as are the issues. Yet, this is no depiction of a rainbow coalition of concerns that seeks to influence a political process that the participants feel marginalised and alienated from. It is, rather, the depiction of an entirely new political preoccupation with identity and culture from the right-wing - often extreme right-wing - of politics. For, perhaps in response to mass migration and policies of multiculturalism, there have arisen and continue to arise in many Western liberal democracies political movements and parties that address issues of identity, democracy, the impact of global capitalism and the destruction of cultural values that have in recent times been considered to be the preserve of the multicultural left. From the Christian Coalition and Buchananite and Dukeite ‘cultural warriors’ in the United States, to the emergence of right and far right movements and political parties in Western Europe, North America and Australasia the rightward orientation of the cultural turn is a phenomenon that it is becoming increasingly difficult to ignore. Indeed, what can be called the New Social Movements of the Right may in fact prove to have a far more significant impact upon public policy formation than those of the left to which the overwhelming majority of attention has been given in academia.1 Whilst in countries such as the UK, France, Australia, Belgium, Denmark and Norway, such parties have had an impact unheard of in the last half century, in others such as Austria, the Netherlands, New Zealand, Switzerland and Italy they have actually achieved national government.2 Moreover, the th atrocities of the 11 of September 2001 and the general elections that took place in their aftermath in many western democracies suggest that it would only take one significant event to 1 On this see Dryzek, J., Deliberative Democracy and Beyond, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2000 p. 23; Barry, B., Culture and Equality, London, Polity Press, 2001, p. 277. 2 A point which would make Miller’s reason for ignoring the claims of the far right on the grounds that they have no ‘prospect of taking hold as the public philosophy of one of the technologically advanced liberal democracies’ seem to be more a case of wishful thinking than hard-headed analysis. On this see Miller, D., ‘Communitarianism: Left, Right and Centre’ in Miller, D., Citizenship and National Identity, Oxford, Polity Press, 2000, p. 102. 2 tip the balance of popular rather than fringe opinion still further in the nationalistic cultural right’s favour. 1.i Three Kinds of Nationalism Of course, this is not to say that there is a single nationalist viewpoint. Indeed, there are at least two types of nationalist argument which are commonly discussed in the academic literature. The first of these is a nationalism that seeks to defend either social democratic or some other set of values. The second, by contrast, is more conservative in its outlook and sees national identity as a good in itself and, indeed, one that is in need of preserving regardless of the kind of political culture that the national identity underpins. In more philosophical terms, we may say that these two varieties of nationalism differ to the extent to which they regard national identity in instrumental or constitutive terms. In the academic literature the first of these viewpoints is represented in a particularly systematic way by David Miller who defends a principle of nationality as instrumental to the pursuit of social justice.3 The second constitutive or conservative nationalist perspective takes nationality and national culture as worthy of protection by the state as they are as goods in themselves. This viewpoint has gained contemporary expression in the work of Roger Scruton.4 This notwithstanding, the central claim of this paper will be that both of these positions do not adequately capture what makes nationalism a newly resurgent force in politics. For what is unique about much nationalist discourse today is its power to both baffle and surprise. Most interestingly, perhaps, the nationalist contribution to public discourse concerning culture and identity is opening up wholly new and hitherto unexpected fissures in politics that seem to transcend the hitherto dominant liberal and conservative conceptions. From the multiracial supporters of California’s Proposition 187 and the openly gay but immigration and multiculturally-sceptical Pim Fortuyn in the Netherlands, to Jewish supporters, candidates and high-ranking members of supposedly far-right political parties in Europe and the British National Party’s ‘outreach’ programmes to Hindus and Sikhs in the UK, contemporary nationalism destabilises in a most fundamental way our received notions of identity, democracy, toleration and, indeed, what it even means to be on the right-wing of politics.5 3 See David Miller, On Nationality, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1995; Citizenship and National Identity. 4 Scruton, R., The Meaning of Conservatism, London, MacMillan, 1980, Chapters 2 and 3;‘In Defence of the Nation’, in Scruton, R., The Philosopher on Dover Beach, London, St. Martin’s Press, 1990, pp. 299328. 5 Proposition 187 denied all but essential public services to illegal immigrants and had a high degree of support from American Blacks as well as Whites. During the last presidential election in France, many Jews voted for Jean-Marie Le Pen because of their perception that the far-right Front National would deal more vigorously with Muslim immigrants whom they blamed for a rise in anti-Semitic attacks. In 2004 Londoner Patricia Richardson was the first Jewish candidate to stand for the British National Party which is committed to the voluntary repatriation of all non-white immigrants. Cohen, David, ‘Why I’m in the BNP’, Evening Standard, London, 26.03.04. Prominent Austrian journalist Peter Sichrovsky was the Party General Secretary of the right-wing Freiheitspartei Österreichs (FPÖ) until September 2002. 3 In order to capture this it will be claimed that there is in fact a third nationalist perspective that is distinct from the traditional liberal and conservative understandings. Furthermore and to introduce the second claim of this paper, it will be argued that this ‘new wave’ nationalism is more in tune with contemporary nationalist sentiment that the two other versions despite having no representation in the academic literature. The reason for this has much to do with the fact that it appears to be particularly adroit at appropriating much of the public language and ethical reference points governing political discourse about identity that emanate in the main from the left - more specifically the multicultural left to which, ironically, it is so profoundly opposed - and reapplies them to the national community, thus giving it a relevance and timeliness far beyond those liberal and conservative varieties of nationalism that are the mainstays of academic consideration of these themes.6 The issue of the non-existence of a third ‘new wave’ nationalist position is, of course, of academic interest in its own right. A subsidiary claim of this paper, then, will be that this position is an emergent one in the world of politics and civil society and one that merits serious discussion in academia. The fact, therefore, that all the citations used in this paper in support of the existence of such a position are from the news print and other, non-academic, media should not been regarded as deficiencies of the position; as if this were somehow reflective of intellectual unworthiness. What we are witnessing, rather, is the emergence of a position that is yet to find a voice, let alone a research project, in contemporary political theory. It is one, however, that may well deserve both. In this paper I will outline the liberal and conservative versions of nationalism and claim that they both fail to account for the political relevance of contemporary nationalism. Building upon this, I will outline what will be called the new wave nationalist position that both borrows and yet is distinct from the other two versions of nationalism discussed. Like the principle of liberal nationality, new wave nationalism appeals to progressive values yet also contains conservative aspects that claim that those values are constitutive of our identities and, as such, are non-negotiable. Moreover, it will be claimed that the politics of culture is by no means the preserve of the political left. Indeed, what makes new wave nationalism so powerful as well as distinct from liberal and conservative nationalism is that it borrows the language of multiculturalism to justify political positions that are quite opposed to it. 1. Liberal Nationalism Similarly to authors such as Nancy Fraser, Brian Barry and John Dryzek, David Miller locates political theory’s concern with culture in the historical demise of communism. In the wake of A similarity which I hope has been made clear by this paper’s opening paragraph’s self-consciously ‘right-wing’ parody of the opening passages of Iris Young’s Justice and the Politics of Difference. On this, see Young, I. M., Justice and the Politics of Difference, Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1990, p. 15. 6 4 the break-up of the Soviet Union ‘[i]t matters less,’ he writes, ‘whether the state embraces the free market, or a planned economy, or something in between.’ Rather, ‘[i]t matters more where the boundaries of the state are drawn, who gets included and who gets excluded, what language is used, what religion endorsed, what culture promoted.’7 However, for Miller the post- communist concern with culture and identity is not only manifested in the West in the politicisation of minority group claims within society. Indeed, to end the analysis here would be to tell only part of the story of the cultural turn for it leaves unanswered the question of the determination of the political conditions in virtue of which these and other claims are made. The link between these two types of concern with culture, of course, is the notion of national identity for it is one of Miller's primary contentions that without a conception of national identity we cannot make adequate sense of any of the claims we make in politics, multicultural or otherwise, nor of the persistent nature of national sentiments Yet, what for Miller is a national identity and what purpose does it serve? The notion of national identity contains three interconnected propositions. First, national identity is part of our personal identity; that is, national identities exist for us and are rationally defensible. Of course, to say this does not commit Miller to a realist social ontology for his account of national identity is an anti-essentialist one. That is, national identities are following Benedict Anderson, ‘imagined communities’ that are ‘constituted by belief’.8 Another way of saying this, of course, is to say that Miller defends an interpretative account of national identity in which ‘it is a mistake to begin from the position of an outside observer trying to identify nations by looking to see which people have common attributes such as race or language.’9 Rather, national identities must be conceived of as existing ‘when their members recognize one another as compatriots, and believe that they share characteristics of the relevant kind’.10 In Ernest Renan’s memorable phrase, Miller tells us, the nation is ‘a daily plebiscite’ whose existence ‘depends on a shared belief that its members belong together, and a shared wish to continue their life in common’. 11 The second proposition in the account of national identity is that nations are ethical Miller, D., On Nationality, p. 1. See also see Fraser, N., ‘From Redistribution to Recognition?’, Dilemmas of Justice in a “Postsocialist” Age’, in Fraser, N., Justice Interruptus: Critical reflections on the “Postsocialist” Condition, New York, Routledge, 1996, pp. 11-39. Barry, B., Culture and Equality, London, Polity Press, pp. 3-5; Dryzek, J., Deliberative Democracy and Beyond: Liberals, Critics, Contestations, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2000, p. 57. 8 On Nationality, pp. 22, 32; ‘In Defence of Nationality’, in Citizenship and National Identity, p. 28. See also Tamir, Y., Liberal Nationalism, Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1993, p. 8. On imagined communities see Anderson, B., Imagined Communities, London, Verso, 1991, rev. edn. In all Miller lists five elements that define what a national community is. The community should be ‘(1) constituted by shared belief and mutual commitment, (2) extended in history, (3) active in character, (4) connected to a particular territory, and (5) marked off from other communities by its distinct public culture.’ On Nationality, p. 27. 9 On Nationality, p. 22. 10 op. cit, emphasis added. 11 On Nationality, p. 23; ‘In Defence of Nationality’ in Citizenship and National Identity, p. 28. See also Renan, Ernest, ‘What is a Nation?’ in Zimmerman, A. (ed.), Modern Political Doctrines, London, Oxford University Press, 1939. 7 5 communities of obligation that generate duties among fellow nationals. Thirdly and related to this, states that are formed from national communities have a good claim to be self-determining in order that these duties and obligations of fellow nationals may be fulfilled.12 From the above it is clear that Miller's motive for defending national identity is not only an explanatory one. It is also normative in that he claims that national identity should be defended. 1.i Trust, Social Justice and Deliberative Democracy Miller’s reasons for defending the idea of national self-determination - that is, that it is ‘valuable for the boundaries of political units (paradigmatically, states) to coincide with national boundaries - fall into two sets, dependent on whether they are reliant upon the defensibility of the idea of nationality itself; that is, upon the defensibility of proposition 1.13 The first set of reasons move us from the idea of a nation to the idea of the state and, tracking his account of national identity above, claim that ‘national identities are defensible, and [that] we are justified in acknowledging special obligations to compatriots,’ propositions that Miller defends in the first two chapter of On Nationality.14 Thus, when a nation is politically autonomous - that is, when it has its own state - it is able to implement schemes of social justice, protect the national culture and is able to view itself as autonomous and to some extent at least as the master of its own social and economic destiny. By contrast, the arguments from state to nation rely only upon the idea of people valuing ‘the effective functioning of political communities.’15 That is, when states are populated by citizens who share a common national identity, they are more likely to trust one another in order to solve collective action problems (such as providing a clean environment) support schemes of social justice and engage in deliberative democracy.16 Clearly, the most prominent reason here - it is the only one that features in both sets of reasons - is that a common national identity or nationality is crucial for the pursuit of social justice.17 That is, for Miller, the sense of obligation, solidarity and mutual trust that is emergent from a solid national identity is instrumental to the pursuit of social justice: ‘[I]f we believe in social justice and are concerned about winning democratic support for socially just policies, then we must pay attention to the conditions under which different groups will trust one another, so that I can support your just demand on this occasion knowing that you will support my just demand at some future moment. Trust requires solidarity not merely within 12 On Nationality, pp. 10-12. On Nationality, p. 82. 14 On Nationality, p. 82. 15 On Nationality, p. 82, emphasis added. 16 On Nationality, pp. 82 - 98. 17 See also Miller, ‘Group Identities, National Identities and Democratic Politics’ in Citizenship and National Identity, p. 78. See also Tamir who claims that the ideas of social justice and national identity go hand-in-hand. Liberal Nationalism, pp. 10, 117-121. 13 6 groups but across them, and this in turn depends upon a common identification of the kind that nationality alone can provide.’18 Of course, the importance of nationality to the pursuit of social justice does not immediately tell us how the state should be self-determining. After all, an aristocracy or some other elite may run the state and could conceivably pursue social justice. Yet, Miller contends that the citizenry as a whole should be actively engaged in running the state so that national self-determination is just that, genuinely national in the sense that it is reflective of national, rather than sectional, interests.19 Thus, it follows from this and from the fact that national identities are constantly evolving that citizenship is best conceived of in republican terms ‘according to which the citizen should be actively engaged at some level in political debate and decision-making.’20 Ideally, moreover, this republican form of citizen participation is taken to endorse a deliberative form of democracy in which ‘decisions are reached through an open and unforced discussion of the issue at stake where the aim of all participants is to arrive at an agreed judgement.’ 21 It is here, then, where the specifically liberal nature of Miller’s account becomes explicit. Rather than viewing nationality as being exclusive and authoritarian, it is constantly evolving and can lend itself to the pursuit of liberal goals within liberal institutions without marginalizing the interests and voices of minorities. 3.i Belonging to Imagined Communities: What is so Private about Wearing a Burkha to the Supermarket? Now, Miller is certainly correct to claim that the imagined and active character of national identity means that it is liable to change; that is, that such identities are in a constant state of flux.22 However, precisely this subjective, imagined character also has profound implications for his account of nations as possessing distinct public cultures or, in older terminology, national identities that need politically to be upheld.23 On Nationality, p. 140; see also pp. 83-5, 90-96; ‘Is Deliberative Democracy Unfair to Disadvantaged Groups?’, in Citizenship and National Identity, p. 158; ‘In what sense must Socialism be Communitarian?’, Social Philosophy and Policy, 6, pp. 51 - 73. Another quasi-Hayekian argument that Miller makes is that a strong sense of national identity is needed not only to ensure the trust necessary for mutual obligations to be met, but that it also functions in this way when societies are, like the majority of national societies are, large scale entities marked by mutual ignorance. National identity, then, acts as a kind of impersonal glue of obligation that allows us to make demands upon and in turn accept demands made upon us by countless unseen others. On this see On Nationality, pp. 83, 92, 98; ‘Bounded Citizenship’, in Citizenship and National Identity, pp. 87 - 88. 19 On Nationality, p. 89. 20 On Nationality, pp. 150, 194 - 5. 21 On Nationality, p. 96. 22 On Nationality, pp. 126-8 23 On Nationality, pp. 25-7. Tamar Meisels has argued that despite his understanding of national identity as that of an imagined community, Miller in fact assumes an objectivist position, most obviously in his discussion of secessionist claims in Citizenship and National Identity. There is, however, little textual evidence to support this view throughout the bulk of his writing on the subject. On this, see Tamar 18 7 We will recall that out of the need to distance his position from the more extreme versions of nationalism, Miller discounts certain factors that members of the national community must share from the account of the distinctive public culture, despite acknowledging that there must be at least some such features in order for that culture to be distinctive. In the first instance Miller wishes to exclude the characteristic ‘that our fellow-nationals must be our ‘kith and kin’, or that they all be born in the territory of the nation in question´. 24 ´Secondly, he claims that it is erroneous ‘to suppose that the common public culture required for a national identity must be monolithic and all-embracing’.25 From this, he concludes that neither the food one eats, the clothes one wears, nor even the music one listens to are ‘normally part of the public culture that defines nationality’ and which in turn is the source of particular ethical obligations to fellow nationals.26 Yet, this seems problematic in a number of important respects. Firstly it seems to exclude a number of very fundamental characteristics that many would suppose do play a part in defining what it means to be a member of a national community. Physical appearance and style of dress in particular - but in this day and age with ever more powerful and portable sound systems - even the music one listens to do play a part in defining the public culture, and hence identity, of a nation. This is because whilst being private in the sense of being private preferences, choices concerning dress, language use, food and music do have a public impact on other people’s lives. In this way, they may be conceived of as part of the public architecture of a society - the kinds of things, like buildings, that manifest cultural and even, to extend the sense of Barry’s usage, ‘propositional content’ which through action not only concretise a nation’s public culture but also reveal what the substance of that culture is.27 Even physical appearance, whilst not usually being the results of personal choice, contributes in its own way to how a locality ‘feels’ to its inhabitants. The various Chinatowns in many of the worlds great cities, for example, are not considered to be such because they are populated by middle-class Europeans who have embarked en masse upon some ethnic fad, but because they are populated by people who look, eat and sometimes even dress like Chinese people. In this sense we may borrow from argument found in much feminist literature that emphasises that the ostensibly private can often be political. Wearing a burkha to the supermarket in Eastbourne, for example, may be a private, individual decision - although on many occasions one must remain sceptical Meisels, ‘Territorial Resolutions in Divided Societies’, in Daniel A. Bell and Avner de-Shalit (eds.) Forms of Justice: Critical Perspectives on David Miller’s Political Philosophy, Lanham, Rowman and Littlefield, 2003, pp. 183-203. 24 On Nationality, pp. 25-6 25 On Nationality, p. 26 26 op. cit. On the idea of the public culture as a source of particular ethical obligations, see On Nationality, pp. 68-70. 27 Barry, Culture and Equality, p. 270 8 of even this much - but it is also undoubtedly an act of public significance and impact. The same, of course, would go for not wearing one to the market in Taliban-ruled Afghanistan. Of course, what is curious about this is that Miller readily accepts the link between the physical features of a society, the content of its public culture or national identity and the interest of the national community in preserving those features via the institutions of state.28 So, contrary to Miller, it would seem that such factors cannot be excluded in advance – as if part of some private realm - from the list of things that on at least some occasions may contribute to a national community’s self-understanding. Indeed, the ideas of a national dress, a national food or a national music express in a particularly vivid way that such things do express the identity and cultural characteristics of the national community. It would be wrong, of course, for conservative nationalists to take heart from this and conclude that such factors must always be contributive to national identity and appeal to them in order to exclude members of certain groups. That is precisely the point of the subjectivist, imagined nature of identity that Miller’s account presupposes: what is to count as public and private will vary both between and within societies. Yet, importantly this is equally problematic for Miller. With the assumption of an interpretative position with respect to the imagined nature of national identity one cannot help but conclude that such factors can and often do enter the community’s daily plebiscite of shared belief and mutual commitment and consequently membership may be accorded, or withheld, in virtue of them. To attempt to rule such factors out of the equation of nationhood and belonging in advance, then, would not only seem to run the risk in many instances of emptying the notion of national identity of much of its meaningful content, but runs contrary to Miller’s own philosophical understanding of what it means to be a member of the national community and how this may vary from place to place. Of course, the reason that Miller does rule them out, is to gain some critical distance from the more intemperate varieties of nationalism. Yet he is unsuccessful to this end because the imagined nature of identity necessarily commits him to the proposition that in at least some places not only dress and language but even one’s race may well enter into the self-definition of the nation. Yet, equally problematically, Miller does in any case seek to rule what he views as core components of national identity in. Underlying his view here, of course, is an understanding one of the alternatives to a politics of nationality as a ‘cultural free-for-all’ or ‘cultural supermarket’. Yet, Miller´s argument here is implausible because there is no guarantee that resultant from a deliberative democratic process even what he takes to be core aspects of national identity will be transformed or stripped away entirely. Importantly, then, without imposing principled side-constraints upon the kind of issue that citizens can debate, Miller’s account of republican participation could yield similar results to the cultural free-for-all. Of 28 On Nationality, pp. 87-88 9 course, if he were to impose such constraints this would raise serious doubts about his commitment to participatory and deliberative politics. In any case and similarly to the issue of ruling aspects out, to stop at any point with regard to any given aspect of the identity and attempt to institutionalise its permanence is just, as Miller would say, to set the identity in stone or cast it in aspic. Indeed, Miller explicitly claims that ‘[t]he role of the sate should not be to impose some preformed definition of national culture on people who may resist it, but to provide an environment in which the culture can develop spontaneously rather than being eroded by economically self-interested action on the part of particular individuals.’29 Yet, why the protection of landscapes, musical traditions or even languages is not to impose a preformed definition of national culture is a question that Miller appears reluctant to answer. Again, this core essentialism of the liberal nationalist account of national identity would seem to make it unusually close to the conservative ideal it seeks to distance itself from. Given identity’s imagined nature, then, rather than attempt to define in advance who and what does an does not belong in which public culture and, importantly, on what grounds, we would be better off developing principles of justice that leave individuals free to discover answers to such questions rather than having them imposed by the state. That is, to develop principles that in themselves are agnostic about such issues but which are nonetheless capable of providing answers. 3. ii Identity, Democracy and Social Justice As we have seen Miller endorses the idea of participatory republican politics and deliberative democracy as the means by which national identities may be transformed on an open, unforced and equitable basis.30 Yet, it is questionable whether this kind of political process sits comfortably with contemporary trends in nationalist discourse. This is made clearer when we examine Miller’s claim that multicultural theorists assume away the problem of majority hospitality for it would appear that this is also a problem for his own theory. Majority and host communities could, and indeed, increasingly do argue that it is the minorities that must adapt to the social reality they have chosen to reside in if they are to be accepted or, in Miller’s own terms, if they are to be received into the imagined public culture Thus, despite arguing convincingly that multiculturalism assumes away the problem of majority hospitality whilst at the same time seeking to displace any overarching conception of nationality in virtue of which minority claims can be fairly made, Miller too assumes away the problem of majority 29 On Nationality, p. 88, emphasis added Of course he is quick to point out that we should look at deliberative democracy as but a regulative ideal in this respect – as a useful approximation of how just decision would look – and one that is usually unattained in actually existing polities. Nevertheless, he believes that some form of deliberative democracy where ‘decisions are reached through an open and uncoerced discussion of the issue at stake where the aim of all participants is to arrive at an agreed judgement’ is necessary to ensure the legitimacy of its decisions. On Nationality, p. 96. 30 10 hospitality. For the majority group it seems unrealistic - if not something of a confidence trick that republican participation and deliberative democracy are intended only to facilitate the transformation or stripping away of aspects of national identity that the nation’s component groups may find repugnant or that the public sphere should be free of ‘symbols, practices and unstated assumptions that prevent members of some groups from participating as equal citizens’.31 Interestingly, he cites Australia as a country where the national identity has been progressively and democratically transformed in the manner he favours.32 Yet, it is debatable whether this was a transformation the majority community of British origin ever desired, nor whether it was rather a product of top-down, often ghastly, bipartisan collusion rather than bottom-up grass-roots pressure for diversification, a fact that perhaps has been periodically exposed when the population has been given the direct opportunity to express its view on issues such as the monarchy.33 Yet, perhaps the most serious problem with the account of republican participation and deliberative democracy is that, as a procedural account of the public decision-making process there is no guarantee that the decisions it arrives at will be in accord with Miller's ultimate goal of the achievement of social justice. After all, and particularly given the diversity of voices Miller wishes to see in some sense included in public, transformative discourse, there is no guarantee that they will speak univocally with respect to society’s political goals. Deliberative democratic participants, that is, may equally endorse a programme of sweeping privatisation of public services as they would vote to protect or reform the institutions that mete social justice. It may be true as Miller contends that our national identities ‘are not set in aspic’ - at least if they are set within pervasive liberal institutions - but neither are our political goals, especially if they are the objects of such an avowedly transformative public discourse procedure as deliberative democracy. As we have seen, Miller’s principal concern in defending a principle of nationality is that it is instrumental to the trust, solidarity and sense of mutual obligation that is a prerequisite for the pursuit of social justice.34 However and similarly to the above problem with the account of deliberative democracy, the defence of social justice itself is problematic in at least two 31 'Group Identities, National Identities and Democratic Politics' in Citizenship and National Identity, pp, 79 - 80; On Nationality, p. 142 32 On Nationality, p. 135 33 Witness the 1999 referendum on the republic which failed in every state and territory except the Australian Capital Territory - where the federal government is based - and where one of the more prominent arguments in its favour was that it was more representative of contemporary multicultural Australia and would therefore enable New Australians to identify with their adopted country. Furthermore, the 1998 general election that saw the overtly anti-multicultural One Nation Party obtain over 1,000,000 votes, not to mention the disturbing lengths to which opponents of this party in the highest echelons of government sought to undermine it, culminating in the imprisonment and subsequent acquittal of its leader on charges of electoral fraud in 2003. 34 ibid., pp. 83 – 5, 91 – 92 footnote 14, 93 – 6, 98, 139 – 40, 185. See also Miller, D., ‘In what sense must Socialism be Communitarian?’ Social Philosophy and Policy, 6 (1988 – 9), pp. 51 – 73; Market, State and Community, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1989. 11 respects. Firstly, it is by no means certain that the public culture will be sufficiently solidaristic to carry the burden of social justice. It is here, of course, where Miller draws a distinction between the ‘strength’ and ‘character’ of national identity.35 Doing so enables him to claim that the counter-example of a country like the United States that has a strong national identity but an ‘unusually individualistic’ public culture does not damage his argument for nationality as necessary for the pursuit of social justice.36 Yet, even if this is so, it does commit him to a particular kind of national identity - one that is both strong and of a solidaristic character - if social justice is to be realised. This, of course, subverts idea of an evolving national identity. National identity, that is, may move away from a solidaristic to an individualistic conception and thus cannot be appealed to as the basis for an account of social justice. Another way of saying this, of course, is to say that social justice may need an account of national identity but it does not follow that national identity needs an account of social justice. Indeed, in an earlier discussion Miller is quite explicit about this. ‘Nationality,’ he writes, ‘is associated with no particular social programme: the flexible content of national identity allows parties of different colours to present their programmes as the true continuation of the national tradition and the true reflection of national character’.37 Yet, if this is so, what role does nationality play in the account of social justice? The answer is that it may not play any role in the cultivation of the bonds of trust necessary for social justice and, as such, is a redundant aspect of the theory.38 What these criticisms highlight is the fundamentally instrumental nature of Miller’s theory for if the principal reason for defending a principle of nationality is to secure the conditions of social justice this merely raises the question of why social justice should be pursued. This is, of course, an answer that Miller does not give and indeed, if he did, it would seem to sit uneasily with his commitment to the democratic transformation of national identity and the cultural diversity towards which he professes to be sensitive. The idea that the public culture may be transformed, but only insofar as it does not challenge the pervasiveness of the ideal of social justice would seem to make that culture a rather stale and ossified one; one that is indeed cast in aspic. Moreover, and only if we assume that the account of social justice is unproblematic, Miller claims we need a principle of nationality to cultivate those bonds of trust and mutual obligation that guarantee the smooth running of its institutions. Yet, regardless of whether the principle of nationality is capable of doing so, there is in any case good reason to contend that 35 On Nationality, p. 94 On Nationality, p. 94 37 ‘In Defence of Nationality’, in Citizenship and National Identity, p. 33 38 See also Kukathas, Chandran, The Liberal Archipelago, pp. 208-9 where he claims that ultimately Miller’s conception is wanting because despite requiring that ´people live by standards they do not recognize or cannot abide, 'it is in any case unnecessary because society can be organized politically so that it functions properly and so that different ways of life can coexist. The liberal nationalist state, then, is as unnecessary as it is undesirable. 36 12 the very institutions that dispense social justice - that is, those of the welfare state - are themselves complicit in the undermining the bonds of trust required to sustain them. For the monopolisation by the state of the process of welfare provision means that individuals are excluded from the very process by which they gain trust in one another, particularly in times of need. That is, by institutionalizing a relationship of entitlement between the individual-in-need and the state, the institutions of social justice make trust, and indeed, any other ethical value, an unnecessary commodity because recipients never have to interact with donors on an ethical, potentially trust-cultivating basis. Being a matter of entitlement rather than, say, agreement between individual recipients and donors and donor agencies, the welfare state only succeeds in acting as a kind of moral steriliser that stifles the very cultural process in virtue of which values such as trust could actually emerge. Of course, the issue of the corrosive effect of the welfare state upon the emergence and sustenance of relationships of trust raises another important issue: that of the incentive structure that immigrants encounter when they enter a new country. It seems that one important reason why Miller finds himself having to defend a principle of nationality in the first place is the concern that the universal entitlements of the welfare state act may serve to warp the incentive structure that attracts migrants, particularly those from countries for whom the concept of money and other benefits falling as if manna from heaven is entirely alien. The problem here is that it is all too easy for immigrants to be accused of being work-shy and of failing to contribute to society through the tax system. Immigrants, that is, fail ´to do their bit for society and only take from it. The consequence of this is to put an often intolerable political strain upon host community acceptance of immigration itself, or, if not this, then of migrants receiving welfare benefits. Of course for Miller, the trust-enhancing role of a common nationality acts to counterbalance this. Yet, it seems reasonable to assume that without the welfare state, both the numbers and types of immigrant attracted by a new life in a new country would be substantially different and those who really were work-shy would either leave or self-select not to come, thus rendering the principle of nationality unnecessary. With this in mind, it remains unclear whether an assimilationist principle of nationality would be needed so as to cultivate trust. That is, a welfare state-free society would be more likely to attract migrants who already have the requisite social skills and attitudes to successfully interact with the host community, thus lowering the costs of assimilation, of immigrant social exclusion and, importantly in Miller’s own terms, of host community hospitality. All the universal guarantees of the welfare state achieve, then, are to act as disincentives toward integration and mutual understanding as they make it relatively costless to fail to integrate and seek acceptance. The existence of a 13 multicultural welfare state would, upon this account only make matters worse for it would not only remove the economic incentive to integrate but also the cultural one.39 This is an issue of which Miller is certainly aware. In a footnote to his discussion of the role of trust in the sustenance of social justice he concedes that perhaps ‘a lesser degree of trust is required to support a night watchman state’.40 Yet, rather than giving a principled answer as to why it is not possible, then, to do away with the role of nationality as the cultivator of trust, he only records his empirical scepticism with regard to such an option being a viable possibility in the late twentieth century.41 Thus, it is questionable in any case whether the pursuit of social justice is what makes nationalism so attractive. For conservative nationalists at least, the transformative aspects of Miller’s account makes any professed nationalism to be merely subservient to the liberal values and, as such, is something of a flirtatious tease to true believers in the value of the nation. What Miller has to say about national identity may as he happily accepts be heretical to liberal minded cosmopolitans but for conservative nationalists the real heresy is in the failure to be sufficiently nationalistic.42 Rather, it would seem that it is the conservative claim that national identities are goods in themselves that is the best explanation of nationalism’s enduring attractiveness. With this in mind, let us examine this doctrine. 2. Conservative Nationalism We saw earlier that nationalist thought broadly divides into two camps, one largely liberal and individualistic, the other, conservative and collectivist. Another way of capturing this is to claim that conservative nationalism distinguishes itself from its liberal counterpart in that it sees the value of national identity not in instrumental terms as subservient to some other goal such as the pursuit of social justice, but rather in constitutive terns as a good in itself and without which the community ceases to be the community that it is. For conservative nationalists, that is, the cultural integrity of national identity is itself the ultimate value as it provides the preconditions that make justice possible. Of course, we may ask here what makes this position any different from Miller's account. We will recall that he too makes much of the idea of national identity providing a pre-political sense of mutual obligation. Yet he goes on to claim that it is needed ultimately so that the political conditions for the achievement of social justice may be secured, something which conservatives would not necessarily sympathise with. Rather, at the heart of the conservative nationalist viewpoint are the ideas of authority and tradition where the institutions of nationality are to be respected. That is, as Miller elucidates in his discussion of 39 Another issue here is that no matter how benign our attempts to make the mechanisms of assimilation and identity formation are, one ultimately must resort to the power of the state to enforce the mechanisms that are agreed upon, to the exclusion of other possible accounts of intercommunal cohesiveness. 40 On Nationality, pp. 91-2, footnote 14. 41 On Nationality, p. 91, emphasis added 42 On Miller’s supposed heresies see, ‘Introduction’, Citizenship and National Identity, p, 7 14 this position - a discussion which will be a principal reference point here - ‘the nation is conceived not merely in terms of horizontal ties to fellow-members, past and present, who share whatever features are taken to constitute the common identity, but in terms of vertical ties to established institutions, which are regarded as authoritative.’43 The implications of this view of established institutions according to Miller are threefold. The first of these relates to the stance of the state towards minority faiths and practices. Rather than being one of neutrality - that is of equal recognition or of equal lack of recognition - the state gives formal recognition only to the institutions through which the national identity is expressed. This, Miller tells us following Scruton, is the ‘establishment’ and may include institutions such as the monarchy and the church.44 Above all, the conservative nationalist believes that the state should not ‘confer the same status on the institutions of minority faiths as it does on the national church, because to do so would be to weaken the authority of the national institutions.’45 Secondly, there arises an injunction to protect these institutions, as well as the beliefs and practices that constitute them, from criticism in order that their authority be maintained. Finally, the conservative nationalist conception ‘is bound to entail a discouraging if not prohibitive attitude towards would-be immigrants who do not already share the national culture.’46 The contrast with the principle of liberal nationality could not be clearer. Where the liberal nationalist position defends republicanism and deliberative democracy as the means by which the public culture and the institutions that embody it can be interpreted, criticised and, if need be, revised, for the conservative nationalist this would be to violate what is essential to our having politics in the first place. Similarly, where the principle of liberal nationality would, with qualification, be permissive with respect to immigration, for the conservative nationalist to admit immigrants who do not already share the national identity would be to undermine its authority and to weaken the pre-political conditions of justice. 4.i The Critique of Conservative Nationalism Miller’s general critique of conservative nationalism is that it ‘moves from a valid premiss that a well functioning state rests upon a pre-political sense of common nationality - to a false conclusion - that this sense of common nationality can be preserved only by protecting the present sense of national identity and the authority of the traditions that now express it.’47 This broad view, moreover, is reflected in his more particular criticisms of the three aspects of the conservative nationalist position. 43 On Nationality, p. 124 On Nationality, p. 125 45 On Nationality, p. 125 46 On Nationality, p. 127 47 On Nationality, p. 129, emphasis added. See also 'Communitarianism: Left, Right and Centre', in Citizenship and National Identity, pp. 103- 104 44 15 Miller’s principal criticism of the conservative nationalist deference to the authority of tradition and national institutions is that it fails to acknowledge the changing nature of identity and the fact that we need liberal freedoms in order to secure the legitimacy of the ensuing discourse that manages that change.48 Importantly, Miller is not claiming that at any given moment our national identity will not be experienced by at least some of us as substantial. Rather, it is to claim that the articulation of this experience is itself only one of many possible interpretations of the authority of the traditions that underpin the national identity. Given this, for Miller it is important that there is a ‘collective conversation’ about the status of our national institutions - one that is secured in large measure by liberal freedoms of conscience and expression and the institutions of deliberative democracy - rather than enforced respect. Miller is less explicit in his criticism of conservative nationalism’s position with regard to state neutrality and its attitude toward minority faiths and practices. Nevertheless, his position can be divined from the above criticism of conservatism’s hostility towards criticism of establishment. Presumably, the liberal nationalist position would be contrasted with that of the conservative nationalists not in the sense that at some point there may be a particular faith that receives state recognition and protection as part of establishment. Rather, he is concerned to claim that which faith may be recognised will always be open to deliberative democratic agreement.49 The difference, then, is that for Miller the state may be non-neutral both in the substance of its attitude toward, for example, religion whereas at all times is ought to be neutral insofar as the public procedure for the determination of that substance is concerned. By contrast, for the conservative nationalist, the state must always be non-neutral in substance and procedure with respect to such issues. Importantly, however, Miller does concede that ‘where some cultural feature - a landscape, a musical tradition, a language - has become a component part of national identity, it is justifiable for the state to discriminate in its favour if the need arises.’50 Miller’s critique of conservative nationalism with regard to immigration is that it is unduly harsh in its desire to use immigration policy as a tool for the maintenance of national unity.51 Rather than pursue an overly restrictive immigration policy, Miller contends that his own liberal principle of nationality only asks that immigrants be willing 'to accept current political structures and to engage in dialogue with the host community so that a new common identity can be forged.’52 Let us now look more closely at each of these criticisms. One aspect of the conservative nationalist position to which we may with Miller object is the claim that our national identity should be immune from criticism and treated with 48 On Nationality, p. 127 On Nationality, pp. 180-1, 195 50 On Nationality, p. 195 51 On Nationality, p. 120 52 On Nationality, p. 130 49 16 deference and respect. The problem here is that over the course of history this tends not to happen regardless of whether conservatives think it should. The case of the evolution of the religious identity of England from the reign of Henry VIII to Elizabeth I is particularly instructive here. By the conservatives’ own argument England should have remained subsequent to Mary I, the Catholic nation that it had been for the previous millennium and the temporary supremacy of the Church of England under Henry VIII - today’s established church since Elizabeth I - dismissed, although perhaps tolerated, as an historical aberration. The cut-off point of the national identity and component institutions to which we should defer, then, is always an artifice of politics and, perhaps more importantly if it is not, the result of a hitherto inflexible political system having to come to terms with social forces beyond its control. As such, the content of national identity is somewhat arbitrary.53 Given our broad agreement with Miller here the next issue is that of state neutrality. We will recall that the conservative position can be characterised as one of partial-in-substance and partial-in-procedure. Yet, as we have seen, if the body of institutions that the state if supposed to be partial towards are merely the result of the art of politics, then it seems arbitrary for the state to be particularly partial towards them. Given, then, our rejection of the conservative nationalist partial-in-substance and partial-in-procedure position, the question becomes whether Miller’s partial-in-substance but neutral-in-procedure position is an adequate response to the issue of state neutrality. The further question that needs to be asked here, of course, is whether there should be a substantive conception of national identity, regardless of whether it is worked up from a neutral public procedure. This, of course, ties in with the instrumental role national identity plays in Miller's account as the guarantor of the bonds of trust necessary for the political sustainability of redistributive policies of social justice. The problem here is that this specifically social democratic account of justice is not defended but rather asserted. Yet, without an account of why the public culture should be coloured by the precepts of social democracy, Miller’s claim that we need a substantive account of national identity to underpin it remains unsubstantiated. The fact that the account of the formation of the substance of national identity is more inclusive than that of the conservative nationalists is, therefore, beside the point. Moreover, and consistent with Miller’s ethically particularist presuppositions, it seems in any case that the list of things which may be viewed as component parts of the national identity would vary greatly from nation to nation with the result that the state may in fact be wholly partial in its stance 53 The position of the pro-James, Duke of York Tories during the Exclusion Crisis of 1678-81 was both philosophically consistent and politically commendable in this respect. For them, the fact of the Duke’s Catholicism should not have been allowed to trump the fact that he was, according to tradition, the rightful heir to the throne rather than Charles II´s protestant bastard son James, Duke of Monmouth. The Exclusion Crisis, of course also lead to the formation of the first modern Tory and Whig political parties. 17 toward minority faiths, cultures and languages.54 At this point, then, there seems little to differentiate Miller’s position from the position he seeks to reject. Similarly, his critique of conservative scepticism of immigration seems fanciful. Firstly, as we have seen, Miller does not give an account of why the host community would find a transformative dialogue with immigrant communities desirable, given that they presumably already have a settled sense of national identity. More problematically still, he fails to acknowledge in his critique of the conservative attitude toward immigration that some immigrant groups do not appear as willing to accept current political structures or the values that underpin them as he expects. Moslems in the United Kingdom, for instance, set up their own ‘Muslim parliament’ in 1992 as they regarded Westminster as inimical to their interests and also demonstrated contempt for the values of democracy itself when rioting outside the Houses of Parliament in 1988 over the publication of Salman Rushdie’s novel The Satanic Verses. Given this, it seems entirely plausible that such groups should not be welcomed by the host community and accorded recognition as co-imaginers of national identity, just as conservative nationalists would have us believe. Yet, despite this fact doing some damage to Miller's position, whether it can be used by conservative nationalists to appeal to the state with regard to immigration is doubtful. In order to do so they would not only have to assume weakly that the institutions of state can manage the character and numbers of immigrants but, more strongly, that only the institutions of state can do so. This, however, is an argument that is yet to be made. Indeed, it would seem that, equipped with the appropriate set of freedoms to pick and choose among other things neighbours and colleagues - that is, to discriminate individuals acting within the liberal institutions of civil society could do this in a manner that is more sensitive to the values and traditions already latent in society, something which one would expect to be in tune with the deepest philosophical commitments of conservatism. A deeper problem here, moreover, is that the conservative nationalist can always respond that our sense of national identity only changes over time because it is set within permissive and corrosive liberal institutions. This response, of course, makes Miller’s critique appear circular. He moves from the claim that national identity is subject to change to the conclusion that we need the institutions of the liberal state to manage that change. Yet, the conservative nationalist may reply that it is only because those institutions are specifically liberal ones that the national identity changes in the first place. However, as we have seen, this response ultimately has little impact for it presupposes that there actually is a given, identifiable national identity that remains unchanging. Yet, the record of history is full of examples of regimes being forced to change or being removed from within because of their failure to understand the social forces around them. Conservatives may be wary of revolution as Burke famously was but that does not stop revolutions from taking place. Miller’s point, then, is that 54 See On Nationality p. 181 for this particularist view with respect to civic education. 18 liberal institutions enable us to avoid the more unsavoury consequences of revolutions by allowing the dissatisfaction and resentment that fuel them to be expressed and brought into the political sphere. Of course, one issue where we may concur with Miller is in his charge that conservative nationalists presuppose an ossified or essentialist account of (national) identity. Indeed, in this regard it seems that the only philosophical difference between the multicultural and conservative nationalist position here is one of the number of identities that should be recognized and protected by the state. That is, whereas multiculturalists, or at least the most sincere amongst them, seek a politics that enables a myriad of groups to assert their identities, conservative nationalists just think that only one such group should be allowed to do this, the national group. Yet, as Miller claims in On Nationality, the multicultural argument that unlike national identities, group identities are natural and authentic is simply untrue; all identities are to a certain extent impure, inauthentic and the results of imposition from above. 55 If, moreover, identity is forever in flux, conservative nationalists have no greater claim to the preservation of just one identity than the multiculturalists have to preserve a diversity of them. Ultimately, then, we may claim that conservative nationalism errs when it seeks, like multiculturalism, to institutionalise an end to the cultural process, as if somehow society’s cultural problem has been resolved. Instead of presupposing what the optimal relationship between the diverse members of society, or between host and immigrant communities is or, for that matter, to which institutions we should defer, we should forge institutions that leave us free to discover what these might be in line with the embedded, tradition-bound nature of our identities. Moreover, and similarly to the liberal nationalist position, it is reasonable to claim that conservative nationalism does not capture what it is about nationalism today that makes it so attractive to so many. This, however, is not so much in connection with the fact that conservatives seek to defend the integrity of the national identity with more gusto than, say, liberal nationalists. Rather, it is in the overly traditionalistic account of the content of national identity that conservatives presuppose. This is made clear, moreover, once the content of the national identity that conservatives seek to defend cashed out in terms of particular issues. Most notably, the conservative attitude towards race, gender and sexuality whilst always being attractive to some, is viewed by many if not most citizens of contemporary liberal democracies as being on the margins of contemporary opinion. 3. New Wave Nationalism: Nationalism’s Third Way? Thus far we have claimed that the politics of culture and identity is by no means the preserve of the left. Those on the right of politics can and do couch their policy preferences in terms of 55 ibid., pp. 132-5. 19 culture. To this end, we have looked at the two standard accounts of nationalist political thought to see how this is so yet we have claimed that neither of these accounts adequately explains why contemporary nationalism is so appealing. In the case of Miller’s liberal nationalist theory it is doubtful that the principal reason for the current attractiveness of nationalism is because society is concerned with social justice or the transformation of national identity. Indeed, we have suggested that ultimately the instrumental account of liberal nationality betrays the ultimately distributive rather than cultural concerns of the politic sit supports. Rather, it seems that nationalism’s vitality is more likely rooted at least in part, precisely in a regret about the changes and transformations that have taken place in the West during the post-war era as a result of mass migration and with post-September 11 feelings of insecurity. In this respect, it is the conservative nationalist elemental concern with the integrity of national identity that would appear to be a more adequate explanation. Yet, we have also claimed that one must be careful not to overplay the appeal of conservatism here. Whilst the cultural explanation of the new found popularity of nationalism rings true to a greater extent than the social democratic one, there is much elsewhere in the conservative agenda with which few have ideological empathy.56 The new nationalism, then, appears to be a mixture of the two positions: conservative, if not at times decidedly militant in its desire to protect national identity as a good in itself, yet liberal-minded in the bulk of its views on the substance of that identity and the national life it supports. Moreover, what is particularly noteworthy about new wave nationalism is that not only can culture be invoked by the right, but that right-wing cultural policies can be justified in terms of arguments normally considered the preserve of the left. That is, in many respects new wave nationalism appropriates the discourse and terminology of the multicultural left and appeal to notions of democracy, equity, cultural survival and the iniquities of exclusion and privilege in its critiques of both multiculturalism and immigration. This new, almost post-modern, form of nationalist argument represents, then, a most fundamental reworking of political discourse and destabilises in a profound way our received notions of what it means to be on the cultural right. 3.i Inclusion as Assimilation, Exclusion for Democracy Let us now look at a number of issues to get a better idea of what new wave nationalism is and how it engages in cultural politics form the right by appropriating much of the political vocabulary of the left. The issues that we will examine are democracy, multiculturalism, discrimination and cultural survival. The argument presented by new wave nationalism with regard to democracy is twofold. The first aspect relates to the satisfaction of democratic values 56 Indicative here is the view of Gerolf Annemans, the head of the right-wing Flemish nationalist Vlaams Blok party in the Belgian National Assembly who stated that the Blok ‘was not opposed to legal cohabitation of homosexuals’. Bryant, Elizabeth, ‘The Battle over Same-Sex Marriage’, San Francisco Chronicle, San Francisco, March 15, 2004. 20 within the institutions of state whilst the second is concerned with the democratic character of the national culture itself. Defenders of difference-based politics often couch their arguments in terms of democratic values.57 We need a politics of difference in order to be fully democratic and in order to ensure that minority groups have a say in decisions that affect them. However, it is significant to note that this argument for a politics of difference can be put forward by those who favour a politics of assimilation. Thus, whilst the multicultural left defends a differencebased account of politics so as to make good on the promise of democracy, new wave nationalists defend an assimilationist politics on the same grounds. Without a politics of assimilation, that is, immigrants will be ill-equipped to operate effectively within the host society.58 At the level of policy this translates into the claim that immigrants should be compelled to learn the host community’s language as a condition of their gaining citizenship and to adopt over time its customs. The benefit of this, moreover, is not only for the immigrants themselves whom without assimilation would be confused and marginalised, but also for the cohesiveness of inter-communal relations as a whole, an argument that was central in the French Government’s defence of laicité with respect to religious symbolism in public schools. Of course, for some the actions such as those taken by the French government with regard to religious symbolism does not address the core problem. ‘The debate about religious symbolism’, commented Jean-Marie Le Pen, leader of France’s Front National, ‘reminds me of that about the sex of angels. The Orthodox hierarchy was quibbling about obscure points of doctrine whilst Mohammed's troops were preparing to storm the Byzantine Empire.’59 What this comment makes clear is that the protection of democratic values is for new wave nationalists not only a matter of internal policy. That is, for the sake of the values that democracy represents, the state must not only pursue a politics of assimilation rather than multiculturalism internally, but must on occasion follow policies of exclusion with respect to immigrants whose cultural backgrounds are deemed incompatible with, or even hostile towards, those of the host community. Thus, the politics of exclusion for the sake of democracy addresses the issue of the health of the values that are so central to the functioning of democracy itself. For new wave nationalists, liberal democratic culture only functions effectively, indeed only survives if the populace holds it in high esteem and if it can exclude those whose values are inimical to it. Such a view, of course, was central to Dutch politician Pim Fortuyn’s concerns when he claimed that further Muslim immigration into the Netherlands should be halted because ‘Christianity and Judaism have gone through the laundromat of humanism and enlightenment, 57 On this see Young, I. M., Justice and the Politics of Difference; Inclusion for Democracy; Philips, A., The Politics of Presence, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1995. 58 A point expressed by British Labour MP Ann Cryer who claimed that without such assimilationist measures immigration policy amounted to little more than the importation of poverty. The Guardian, Manchester, 17 July, 2001. 59 Le Point, Paris, 16 January,. 21 but this is not the case with Islam’.60 Politicians such as Fortuyn claimed that the state needs to adopt a restrictive stance toward immigration not because it is intolerant, racist or insensitive to difference per se but in order to protect the secular, democratic values that are central to Western societies and to which many of the non-Western immigrants who make up by far the largest proportion of the contemporary inflow appear to be indifferent, if not overtly hostile. An example of such hostility occurred in London when a mayoral election meeting organised by Operation Black Vote - a community organization working to encourage ethnic minority participation in the democratic process - had to be abandoned after Muslim protestors objecting to the presence of leading UK gay rights advocate Peter Tatchell invaded the hall.61 In stark contrast to much multicultural theory, then, we may term this Fortuynesque argument as one of exclusion for the sake of democracy. We may note, furthermore, that unlike Miller who remains conspicuously silent with regard to what should happen if immigrants do not accept current political structures, new wave nationalists are prepared to make hard policy choices to ensure that they do or to prevent them form penetrating the boundaries of the state if they do not. It seems, then, that despite the incompatibility of their policy prescriptions, both multiculturalism and new wave nationalism may appeal to the value of democracy in support of them.62 3.ii Domination: Multiculturalism as the new racism Of course, one way of separating multiculturalism and new wave nationalism would be to claim that multiculturalism is rooted in a deeper concern with inequality and processes of power and domination within society that lead minority and vulnerable communities to be marginalised by the wider community. That is, defenders of a difference-based account of politics argue that it is needed to combat processes of domination and oppression that leave members of minority communities unable to lead fulfilling lives.63 For new wave nationalists, however, it is the very edifice of multiculturalism itself that is all too often the engine of such processes so far as member of majority communities are concerned. Thus, it is claimed that majority communities carry the burden of multiculturalism's injunction that the diverse cultures of society - except the majority one - be protected and even celebrated and that consequently multiculturalism should be done away with. In many towns in the North West of England, for example, it is precisely the perception that the national community is being ignored by governments who appear to be 60 The Guardian, London, 05 July, 2002. ‘Tatchell flees Muslim abuse’, The Pink Paper, London, 05 May, 2000 62 A similar argument has been made by Bruce Ackerman who, despite viewing national boundaries and the luck that comes to those born within those of prosperous countries as morally arbitrary and hence in need of equalisation through free movement, claims that we need immigration controls to protect liberal values, that is, to maintain ‘a cadre of natives familiar with the operation of liberal institutions’. Ackerman, B., Social Justice in the Liberal State, New Haven, Yale University Press, 1980, p. 94. 63 On this see Young, I. M., Justice and the Politics of Difference; Inclusion and Democracy, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2000. 61 22 more concerned with the well being of immigrant and minority communities insofar as the targeting of community project funding and welfare is concerned that has lead in recent years to record levels of support for the British National Party.64 Fundamental to maintaining popular support for any public policy agenda in a democracy, of course, is public opinion and it is here where new wave nationalists makes another complaint. Two cases are of particular relevance here. In the first, approximately 2000 supporters of the anti-multicultural and anti-immigration Pauline Hanson’s One Nation Party in Australia had their names and home addresses published by the Australia-Israel and Jewish Affairs Council four month prior to the 1998 general election.65 Moreover, in the UK MPs who refused to sign a pledge promising to avoid the use of language likely to whip up racial hatred during the 2001 general election campaign were publicly named on the UK Commission for Racial Equality’s (CRE) website. The problem here was twofold. In the first instance, it would always be a matter of controversy as to what would constitute language likely to whip up racial hatred. Indeed, for many the determination of such matters is precisely what democratic politics is for rather than within the remit of an unaccountable public body. Thus, when any organisation attempts to steer the course of public debate on an important issue, it unavoidably appears to be attempting to control the debate and in the process usurping the role of politics itself. The second issue, of course, is the fact of the publication of the names of those MPs who refused to sign the pledge. The problem here is that there are probably as many possible reasons for refusal as there are people who refuse. Yet, by publishing names in this manner the CRE appeared to be condemning people in advance as guilty of racism. Taken together, these events communicated in no uncertain terms that not only would the formation of political parties sceptical of immigration and multiculturalism be hindered, but that even if those sympathetic to the politics of assimilation managed to get elected, their voices would be constrained in any case. New wave nationalists complain that supporters of multiculturalism resort to undemocratic and even antidemocratic strategies to make sure that public discourse is conducted in terms favourable to their particular political agenda. Yet the new wave nationalist complaint about the dominating effects of multiculturalism is not only about the distortion of the democratic process. The very architecture of society itself is part of the process. For example, the erection in north London in 2003 of an eruv - a notional boundary within which Orthodox Jews can perform tasks otherwise banned on the Sabbath and comprised in this particular case of 84 telegraph poles standing 30ft high, positioned beside roads and houses and connected with 1,000 metres of fishing line to help define the boundary caused controversy as it was perceived as turning a public space into a quasi-private one. Other arguments against it were numerous and of a distinctly progressive nature, ranging from a 64 65 The BNP gained over 800,000 votes at this year’s European Elections. Australia/Israel Review, Australia-Israel and Jewish Affairs Council, July 1998. 23 concern that local flora and fauna, particularly birds, may be injured by the wires, to the unsightliness of the poles, to violation of freedom of conscience to the fact that the construction of the eruv was a ‘a claim for territory’ that was ‘extremely offensive to the majority of people who live in the borough, who are of all religions and none.’66 Similarly, the decision by a local government committee to rename a ward in the ancient London district of Spitalfields as Spitalfields and Banglatown in order to acknowledge the presence of significant numbers of Bangladeshi immigrants as well as to encourage tourism was seen as dominating. This was particularly so because the district in question is famous for its history of immigration, ranging from French Huguenots in the seventeenth century to Ashkenazi Jews in the nineteenth. Yet, it was pointed out, Spitalfields was not renamed to accommodate either of these communities. Indeed, in this regard the very name Spitalfields is itself synonymous with the idea of hospitality to immigrants and it was in this sense that many argued that the traditional name should have been respected. For new wave nationalists what such examples often communicate is a colonising mentality in which place names are often the first victims, a practice which was widespread during the era of global expansion by western European powers. Indeed, the idea that immigrants often only seem to be interested in setting up colonies and of living unintegrated or ‘parallel lives’ within the host society was acknowledged in the official independent report into race riots that took place between ethnically English and Muslim Asian youth across northwest England in June 2001.67 Another example of domination comes not from the physical manifestations of multiculturalism but from the consequences of diversity itself, particularly with regard to women. In this case however, the consequences at issue are not those for minority women - of which Doriane Lambelet Coleman and Seyla Benhabib’s discussions are particularly instructive - but for women from national communities.68 In many high immigration areas today it is not uncommon for majority community women to be subjected to verbal and other forms of abuse for wearing clothing that leaves parts of their bodies uncovered. In Australia, moreover, there have been a number of high-profile gang-rape trials in which the majority ethnic background of the victim was a significant factor in the motivation for the attack.69 Even more disturbingly, in Lydall, Ross, ‘Jewish Move Sparks Criticism,’ Evening Standard, London, 02 August 2002. On this see Community Cohesion: A Report of the Independent Review Team, Community Cohesion Unit, UK Home Office, 2003. 68 On this see Coleman, L. L., ‘Individualizing Justice through Multiculturalism: The Liberals’ Dilemma’, Columbia Law Review, vol. 96 no. 5, June 1996, pp. 1093 – 1167; Benhabib, S., The Claims of Culture, pp. 86 - 91. 69 Toy, Naomi & Knowles, Lorna, ‘Pack rapists’ racial taunts’, Sydney, The Sydney Morning Herald, 24 August, 2001; Devine, Miranda, ‘Racist rapes: finally the truth comes out’, Sydney, The Sun-Herald, 14 July, 2002; Sheehan, Paul, Racist to deny the truth of rape’, Sydney, Sydney Morning Herald’, Sydney, Sydney Morning Herald, 19 April, 2003; Devine, Miranda, ‘Betraying the rape victims’, Sydney, The Sun-Herald, 30 November, 2003 66 67 24 at least one of these trials, the culture of the accused was used in their defence.70 This argument, both Coleman and Benhabib explain, is often called the ‘cultural defence’ strategy and involves the defence presenting cultural evidence as an excuse for an otherwise criminal act. Moreover, far from being dismissed by the courts, the production of this evidence has on some occasions been accompanied by reduced sentences and acquittals, particularly if the victim is a member of the same minority community as the defendant.71 Now, whilst there is no recorded case of a minority defendant successfully appealing to the cultural defence strategy with respect to a majority victim, the potential for this to occur s real. Moreover, this raises the important issue of discrimination insofar as majority defendants cannot by definition appeal to the cultural defence strategy for the norms of their culture are already implicit in the legal systems to which they are subject. Not only, then, as Benhabib and Coleman correctly point out, does the strategy of cultural defence undermine aspects of the multicultural agenda itself ‘because minority victims or minority perpetrators do not have access to the same justice as all victims of majority perpetrators’, but, as they inexplicably fail to point out it would also mean that majority perpetrators do not have access to the same justice as minority perpetrators.72 3.iii Discrimination Next is the new wave nationalist complaint about the discriminatory nature of antidiscrimination measures. Of course, one of the important factors in determining whether a practice is discriminatory or not is whether it affects known others. In this way, anti- discrimination advocates seek to outlaw many forms of discrimination on the basis of race, gender, religion and sexuality. Yet, it could be equally consistent to outlaw arranged marriages as these invariably select life partners on the grounds of religion with the consequence that known others are systematically rejected on a discriminatory basis. This, of course, is yet to happen and the fact that it has not leads to the claim that anti-discrimination practice is necessarily selective and hence discriminatory with respect to the social outcomes it seeks to eradicate. An interesting example of the discriminatory effects of multiculturalism itself comes from the workplace and, more specifically, workplace dress codes. In contrast to the example above where in the interests of anti-discrimination communities have to shoulder the burden of a practice that is only prevalent within a handful of them, this example moves in the opposite direction. That is, only some types of community are able, to enjoy the protection of antidiscrimination measures rather than others. Importantly, the complaint here is not the more common one of anti-discrimination measures being examples of ‘reverse discrimination’ which Wallace, Natasha, ‘Gang rapists told age, culture no defence’, Sydney, The Sydney Morning Herald, 02 March, 2004; 71 Although it is not clear from Benhabib’s discussion whether the cultural defence strategy was solely responsible for them. 72 Benhabib, S., The Claims of Culture, p.??? 70 25 is often directed at affirmative action measures. Rather, the complaint proceeds from the premiss that an anti-discrimination measure is uncontroversial, but that it is applied unfairly to the disadvantage of particular groups. In one workplace it was decided that a new female Muslim employee should be allowed to wear a headscarf in the office. The reasons given were respect for her understanding of the requirements her religion placed upon her in terms of appearance. Some weeks after this, a position for a new receptionist arose at the company and after a round of interviews it was decided that the best candidate was an ethnically English male. He was offered the position but only conditionally. The condition was that he remove the piercing above his eyebrow as it was not appropriate to the position he had been chosen for. In the first instance, new wave nationalists complain that it is arbitrary to conclude that one form of cultural expression is appropriate whilst another is not. One could respond here, however, that to put the issue in these terms is misleading. We are not dealing with only cultural forms of expression but, rather, with religion. Yet this seems only to shift the question to the issue of why religion should be accorded some privileged status relative to other forms of cultural expression - in this case, we may say relative to youth cultural expression. This is all the more strange, new wave nationalists contend, when religion itself plays such a limited or non-existent role in the majority of people’s lives in contemporary liberal democracies. One answer is that youth culture is, unlike religion, but a bundle of freely chosen fads, a passing phase which will eventually be grown out of. The practices central to religion, by contrast, are often obligatory and of long standing. Yet, even here there is good reason to be sceptical of the special claims of religion. In the first instance piercing is not the preserve of the young. Yet, in any case, it is questionable that the transient nature of the practice is a relevant factor. At the time the piercing may have been a part of the young person’s journey of selfdiscovery and, no less of his identity. In any case, both the religion itself and the particular practices associated with it are no less the subjects of personal choice. Of course it is at this point where defenders of religious exemption claim that they have no choice because the doctrines to which they subscribe demand it, or because the practice is a central and unalterable aspect of their identity. Yet, if this is so, how do we account for the facts of conversion, renunciation and schism? It may be the case that certain aspects of the religion are obligatory but subscribing to a particular religion is not. The free-choice obligation argument is one to which defenders of multiculturalism cannot appeal in order to rebut the new wave nationalist charge of discriminatory anti-discrimination. Another avenue which defenders of the religious exemption may pursue is that of the profundity and meaningfulness of the practices concerned. This, of course, is the converse of the ‘fad’ argument and claims that, even if the motivation for piercing one’s eyebrow is sincerely held, unlike the donning of the headscarf, it is a superficial practice. Yet, this too 26 seems only to reflect a rather shallow understanding of culture and cultural practice itself. For the piercing itself can, on at least one reading, reflect some of the most profound elements of liberal secular culture, although these may be elements which the piercer is not consciously aware of. That is, the piercing represents not only the attaining of adulthood and the freedom to choose that this implies, but goes to the heart of what it means to be, we may say, an individual chooser. What often disguises this fact is that there is no official doctrine, book or godly Author to sanction the practice. That is, the ethical reference point for both adopting a practice and for deciding what the practice should be resides in the person of the chooser himself. But this does not make the practice any less meaningful. Indeed, in contrast to much religious practice which seems very often to be but the result of either habit, superstition or communal imposition, the liberal chooser confers a unique moral authority upon the practice he adopts through the simple exercise of choice itself. There is little that is more reflective of liberalism for new wave nationalists, then, than the youth with the pierced eyebrow for new wave nationalists. To discriminate against him from within a liberal culture and on the grounds of liberal values of toleration and respect for difference is little short of perverse, let alone unjust and, ultimately, self-contradictory. 3.iv Cultural Survival Another familiar claim from multicultural and difference theory is that without a politics of difference or recognition, vulnerable minorities will be submerged in the majority culture, leaving their members confused and deracinated and unable to voice their distinctive perspective in public deliberation.73 Similarly, however, the same argument is made on behalf of members of majority and host communities is areas with high migrant intake. The underlying issue here and it is one that both camps share, is the issue of the importance of cultural identity to individual well-being.74 On the one hand multiculturalists claim that because culture is so central to individual identity, we need to institute a multicultural politics to protect vulnerable minorities. Similarly, new wave nationalists claim that precisely because cultural identity is so important, it is necessary that the state takes measure to ensure the well-being and survival of the national culture that is so central to the well-being of the majority, indigenous population. The claim gains credibility with the fact that in many western cities today immigrants do not appear to wish to adapt to the host society in any way at all, a fact perhaps most evidenced in their retention of traditional forms of dress and a failure to learn the language of the majority community. On this see Taylor, C., ‘Multiculturalism: the politics of recognition’, In Taylor, C., and Gutmann, A., ???,??? ??? 74 A systematic investigation of which is to be found in Kymlicka, W., Liberalism, Community and Culture, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1989 73 27 In itself, of course, this does not necessarily imply any major problem. Western liberal democracies have always known and tolerated dissent. However, this issue returns again to the question of numbers and the idea of national identities, like all identities, being imagined identities. The problem here, of course, is not just the fact that an unwillingness to adapt to local customs and norms may be experienced as offensive to members of host and majority communities, nor even that such outward signs of indifference to local customs only fuel the host communities reluctance to extend inclusion into its imagined identity to such newcomers. Rather, the problem is made particularly acute when incomers arrive in such numbers as to begin to outnumber the locals. At this point, the nature of the community thoroughly changes to the point where those doing the imagining, imagine in a completely and often incompatible way to the indigenous population and, quite possibly, to the exclusion of the idea of toleration of dissent and difference.75 The problem here, of course is that in a very significant sense the very fact of diversity itself represents the negation of the indigenous culture, when that culture is a largely homogenous one. The argument behind the denial of this claim is that multiculturalism allows indigenous and migrant cultures to co-exist and does so, moreover, on an equitable basis. Yet to the extent that the definition of culture extends not only to belief but, as we have emphasised, to dress, food, music, language and architecture, this is simply untrue. Culture, that is, is not something we only carry in our heads. It infuses the physical realm itself and therefore has tangible consequences for the integrity of the host community culture. 4. Conclusion The aim of this paper has been twofold. In the first instance it has been to make the claim that a concern with the politics of identity is not the preserve of the multicultural left. A concern with identity, that is, is also important to much nationalist thought, whether it is of the liberal instrumentalist or conservative constitutive variety. Yet, we have also claimed that the traditional understanding of nationalist thought in liberal or conservative terms is an inadequate one. In contemporary politics at least, much nationalist thought does not seem to be about securing the political conditions for the achievement of social justice, less still the institutional prerequisites for the transformation of national identity. Neither, moreover, does this mean that nationalists are overly attached to a traditionalistic, hierarchical account of identity. Indeed, in many important respects, much of contemporary nationalist sentiment appears to embody a desire to protect liberal values and freedoms from forces deemed hostile to them. Perhaps even more paradoxically and despite its hostility to multiculturalism at the level of policy, we have 75 Importantly, in smaller nations such as Flanders and Denmark, the feeling that the indigenous culture is becoming increasingly marginalized is all the more keenly felt. For such nations, cultural diversity represents not the flowering of many cultures within society but the submergence of an alreadyvulnerable national community. 28 also seen that the new wave politics of national identity often justifies its normative conclusions in terms that are very similar to its leftist rival. The politics of identity, then, is a far more complex politics than is often acknowledged in contemporary political theory. The second, more practical, aim has been to set out the new wave nationalist position in order to fill a gap in the political theory of nationalism as well as in philosophical discourse concerning the political implications of culture and identity more generally. This, we may add, is all the more important because despite gaining significant ground politically in many Western democracies in the wake of the atrocities of September 11th 2001, the concerns of what we have called new wave nationalism are yet to be formulated in any systematic way within political theory. By attempting to do so here, I hope to have not only to have achieved this but also to have opened up, if not a new research project, then at least a new avenue of enquiry within the political theory of nationalism. Whether, of course, new wave nationalism is a philosophically coherent position, or whether it is morally defensible, are two further questions which, I hope, this paper has succeeded in planting in the mind of the reader. Bibliography Ackerman, B., Social Justice in the Liberal State, New Haven, Yale University Press, 1980 Anderson, B., Imagined Communities (rev. edn), London, Verso, 1991 Barry, B., Culture and Equality, London, Polity Press, 2001 Benhabib, S., The Claims of Culture: equality and diversity in the global era, Princeton, Princeton University Press, 2003 Coleman, L. L., ‘Individualizing Justice through Multiculturalism: The Liberals’ Dilemma’, Columbia Law Review, vol. 96 no. 5, June 1996, pp. 1093 - 1167 Dryzek, J., Deliberative Democracy and Beyond, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2000 Fraser, N., ‘From Redistribution to Recognition?’, Dilemmas of Justice in a “Postsocialist” Age’, in Fraser, N., Justice Interruptus: Critical reflections on the “Postsocialist” Condition, New York, Routledge, 1996, pp. 11-39 Kukathas, C., The Liberal Archipelago, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2003 Kymlicka, W., Liberalism, Community and Culture, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1989 Meisels, T., ‘Territorial Resolutions in Divided Societies’, in Daniel A. Bell and Avner deShalit (eds.) Forms of Justice: Critical Perspectives on David Miller’s Political Philosophy, Lanham, Rowman and Littlefield, 2003, pp. 183-203. Miller, D., ‘In what sense must Socialism be Communitarian?’, Social Philosophy and Policy, 6 (1988/89), pp. 51 - 73 - On Nationality, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1995 - Citizenship and National Identity, Oxford, Polity Press, 2000 29 - ‘A Response’, in Daniel A. Bell and Avner de-Shalit (eds.), Forms of Justice: Critical Perspectives on David Miller’s Political Philosophy, Lanham, Rowman and Littlefield, 2003, pp. ??? - ??? Philips, A., The Politics of Presence, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1995 Renan, E., ‘What is a Nation?’ in Zimmerman, A. (ed.), Modern Political Doctrines, London, Oxford University Press, 1939 Scruton, R., The Meaning of Conservatism, London, MacMillan, 1980 - ‘In Defence of the Nation’, in Scruton, R., The Philosopher on Dover Beach, London, St. Martin’s Press, 1990, pp. 299-328. Tamir, Y., Liberal Nationalism, Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1993 Young, I. M., Justice and the Politics of Difference, Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1990