1 Abstracts Professor Andrzej Bronk Department of Methodology and Philosophy of Science Faculty of Philosophy John Paul II Catholic University of Lublin Method as a distinguishing characteristic of science Since Greek antiquity method and methodicalness have been seen as typical features of scientific procedure and sometimes as the most important formal characteristics (next to language) of science, responsible for the growth of scientific knowledge. If a discipline does not have a method of its own, its scientific autonomy is suspected. A scientist is not only a person with detailed knowledge of a particular field, but first and foremost a person with competence and skill in a research method. It is believed that even if a methodical procedure does not automatically guarantee arrival at the truth it can increase the effectiveness and economy of search for truth. The recurrent use of the notion of scientific method might suggest that – at least in science – it has a precise meaning but this is not the case. Both its intension and its extension are the subjects of lively discussion among philosophers. Contemporary contexts of the use of the notion of scientific method are so different that it is almost impossible to find their common denominator. Of great importance to methodological discussions of the notion of scientific method has been the fact that both the notion of science and the notion of scientific method itself have mostly been shaped after the example of (natural) sciences, which are seen as the paradigm for scientific research. When the notion of science was also applied to the humanities (litterae humaniores, Geisteswissenschaften), it supported a wider understanding of science and scientific method. Ultimately it is the understanding of the nature of science itself that is involved in the discussion of the scientific method and here – as is well known – there is no general consent among philosophers as to what makes a given kind of cognition a scientific procedure. In order to present the debate on the notion of scientific method, to explicate its various contemporary meanings, and to determine the importance of the scientific method for scientific endeavor, I address the following issues: 1. The notion of method and the types of methods, 2. The definition of scientific method, 3. The history of the notion of scientific method, 4. The neo-positivistic notion of scientific method and its critique, 5. The nature of scientific method, 6. Types of scientific methods. Yannick Chin LPHS - Archives Poincaré Université Nancy 2 (France) 2 Expérience perceptive : intuitions communes et explications scientifiques Lorsque nous voyons un arbre, il est naturel pour nous de considérer que c'est l'arbre que nous percevons, et pas autre chose comme un sense-datum, une idée ou quoi que ce soit d'autres. Notre conception de l'expérience perceptive est en ce sens "naïve" : nous croyons que l'arbre lui-même (dans le monde extérieur) est le véritable objet de notre expérience. Pourquoi croyons-nous cela ? Simplement, parce que comme le fait remarquer P. F. Strawson, "l'expérience sensible mature (en général) se présente, en termes kantiens, comme une conscience immédiate de l'existence des choses en dehors de nous"1. En d'autres termes, dans l'expérience perceptive, il nous semble que le monde lui-même nous est présent. Ainsi, c'est un élément de notre conception intuitive de l'expérience perceptive que son caractère dépend essentiellement de l'existence et de la nature des objets externes que nous percevons. Et, en général, lorsque nous voulons décrire cette expérience, la meilleur façon pour nous de le faire est de décrire l'objet même que nous percevons (ou que nous pensons percevoir). Contre cette conception naïve de l'expérience perceptive, certaines personnes ont soutenu que cette conception ne rendait pas justice aux faits scientifiques concernant la perception. En effet, la science a montré que lorsque nous percevons les choses il y a une chaîne compliquée d'événements physiques qui sont impliqués. Et, par conséquent, il est tentant de concevoir l'expérience perceptive comme une conséquence causale de ces événements physiques. Mais peut-être est-il possible de dire plus que cela : que ce que nous percevons n'est pas, comme nous le pensons intuitivement, l'objet externe lui-même, mais plutôt les effets qu'il produit en nous. Cette conclusion est-elle acceptable ? La science a-t-elle prouvé que la conception du sens commun à propos de la perception est fausse ? Je tenterai de montrer que ce n'est pas le cas. En fait j'essayerai de soutenir l'idée selon laquelle notre manière intuitive de comprendre l'expérience perceptive (comme une manière d'être en contact direct avec les objets externes) n'est pas contradictoire avec l'idée que cette expérience dépend de processus physiques variés qui la causent. Ce que pense le sens commun au sujet de la perception n'est pas incompatible avec ce que le discours scientifique est susceptible de nous apprendre à son propos. Ainsi, s'il y a une séparation entre les descriptions du sens commun et les explications scientifiques de la perception, cette séparation n'est pas telle que les unes fourniraient des raisons de penser que les autres sont fausses ou négligeables. (Englisch version) Perceptual Experience : Common Intuitions and Scientific Explanations When we see a tree, it is natural to consider that the object of our perception is a tree, and not anything else like a sense-datum, an idea, or whatever. In that sense our conception of perceptual experience is “naive”: we do believe the tree (in the external world) is the very object of our experience. Why do we believe so? Simply because, as P.F. Strawson makes the point, “mature sensible experience (in general) presents itself as, in Kantian phrase, an immediate consciousness of the existence of things outside us”1. In other words, in perceptual experience, the world itself seems to be presented to us. Thus, being essentially dependent on the existence and nature of external objects that we perceive, is part of our intuitive conception of perceptual experience. And generally speaking, when we wish to describe perceptive experience, the best way to proceed is to describe the very object that we perceive (or that we think we perceive). 1 Perception and its Objects in J. Dancy (ed.), Perceptual Knowledge, New York, Oxford University Press, 1988, p. 99. 3 In reaction to this naive conception of perceptual experience, some philosophers have argued that it doesn’t do justice to scientific facts about perception. Indeed, science has shown that when we perceive things, a complicated chain of physical events are involved. Consequently, one may be tempted to conceive perceptual experience as a causal consequence of such physical events. But it may be possible to go further, and to argue that what we perceive is not the external object, as we intuitively assume, but rather the effects that it produces on us. Is such a conclusion tenable? Has science shown the falsity of the commonsense conception of perception ? I’ll try to argue that this is not the case. I will attempt to support the idea that our intuitive way of understanding perceptual experience – i.e. as a way of being in some direct contact with external objects – is not contradictory to the idea that experience depends on various physical processes in a causal way. What common-sense tells us about perception is not incompatible to what science can teach us about perception. There is certainly a gap between common-sense descriptions and scientific explanations of perception. But it doesn’t mean that each kind of discourse would provide one with reasons to think that the other is false or negligible. Katarzyna Gan-Krzywoszyńska Institute of Philosophy Department of Logic and of Methodology of Science Adam Mickiewicz University, Poznań LPHS-Archives Poincaré (UMR 7117 CNRS) Université de Nancy2 On Natural Language: From Myth to Free Philosophy. One of the fundamentals of Jules Vuillemin’s a priori classification of philosophical systems is a radical cut between myth (mythical thought) connected with the problem of Weltanschauung (world perspective) and free philosophy. Principles of philosophical systems are directly connected with linguistic categories and with the primitive elementary sentences by which they are expressed. According to Vuillemin, natural language as an open and universal code of communication contains five exclusive classes of elementary sentences: pure predication, substantial and accidental predication, circumstantial predication, judgments of methods, and judgments of appearances. Every form of predication becomes an ontological principle of a genuine philosophical system. Between classes of philosophical systems Vuillemin singles out dogmatic systems such as: realism, conceptualism, nominalism of things, nominalism of events and systems of examination: intuitionism and skepticism. Systematic ontology, in Vuillemin’s sense, requires that (1) there must be given a minimal set of indefinable concepts and indemonstrable principles and all elements of the world will be derived from them, (2) this derivation should proceed according to legitimated rules, and (3) rival ontologies should be explained away as mere appearances. Dr hab. Adam Grzeliński Institute of Philosophy Nicolaus Copernicus University Toruń Chair of Cultural Studies WSG Bydgoszcz 4 Between common sense and philosophical language. David Hume’s science of human nature The most outstanding British philosophers of the eighteenth century often claimed that what they wrote was just a defense of common sense. The defense had different forms like Berkeley’s immaterialism or Reid’s banishment of metaphysical speculations. One of the philosophers who saw clearly the problem of the relation between technical, philosophical language and everyday experience was David Hume. One cannot be misled by the philosophical credo found in the opening sections of Treatise of Human Nature that we must glean up our experiments in this science [of human nature] from a cautious observation of human life, and take them as they appear in the common course of the world, by men’s behavior in company, in affairs, and in their pleasures. The phrase taken literally would suggest that there is no difference between systematical philosophical explanation of human nature and the natural experience of a vulgar. When we look closer at terminology used by Hume, we quickly discover how precise it is and how far from the common language heard around. That’s why Hume’s philosophy gives an opportunity to set up the problem: why is the natural, native language of everyday experience not sufficient, why must such an experience be given a philosophical explanation in abstract, technical language? Seen from another angle the question could be formulated as follows: must a philosophical system respect the commonsensical experience? In the present paper I am trying to show two main scopes of the task undertaken by David Hume. The first is a complex, thorough philosophical description of various aspects of human nature. The other is providing a philosophical basis of the common sense. To attain the task I am going to explain Hume’s meaning of the common sense itself and his notion of philosophical system. Then I want to show how Hume demonstrated why man must believe in the existence of the world and other selves (the belief being crucial for commonsensical standpoint), furthermore, he found out that full explanation of such a belief is impossible on the grounds of pure empirical method. Nevertheless, even if it is inexplicable in the speculative philosophy, such existence of other people and of one’s own ego is a necessary postulate in practical philosophy. Thus it is the human practice rather than the theory and speculation which requires commonsensical belief in the reality of facts and existence. Seeking the correct philosophical description of every day practice Hume describes anew the relation of the passions and reason, and shows the impossibility of proving the existence of God, of the world and of human soul. The latter case does not affect only the metaphysics as such, but has special reference to social and political practice. Reason itself, not respecting the common sense can be a source of various kinds of superstition. The proper description of human nature was for Hume a cure for them. It should also be mentioned that trying to reject superstitions Hume follows the path traced by Hobbes and Locke. If Hume could paraphrase a very well-known Kantian saying, he would willingly assert that common sense without philosophical explanation does not know anything whereas the philosophical reason lacking the common sense is blind. But he would also be very careful: not every explanation does justice to common sense. Some of them are even quite pernicious for our social and political life. Professor Gerhard Heinzmann, Department of Philosophy, Laboratoire de Philosophie et d'Histoire des Sciences—Archives H. Poincaré, 5 UMR 7117 du CNRS Nancy-University, France Common sense in philosophy and science Thesis: According to Wittgenstein, common sense in Philosophy is not only a postulate concerning beliefs, but also and more deeply a form of common life. I will argue in this paper for a similar thesis concerning common sense in Science. Anti-realists and realists often supported the thesis affirming that it was hopeless to look for a relation between science and common sense theory because this relation has been broken. Nevertheless, Strawson gives a strong argument against the opinion that there is a common sense theory, which is in disagreement with a scientific theory. So, the very question does not concern the distinction between the common sense theory (the theory about phenomenal pictures) and the scientific theory but concerns the distinction between common sense and scientific theory. In other words, there is not an elementary or evident first level theory on what there is, independent from all scientific activity, and which is only afterwards substantiated and developed by scientific explanation. Rather, the scientific explanation concerns already the articulation and the expansion of the common sense schema. This is the reason why the terms “knowledge of” and “knowledge that” should be replaced by “object-competence” and “metacompetence”: these new terms underlie that there are not two different kinds of knowledge but only two co-relational aspects. This naturally does not imply that there could not exist common sense sentences, which are true or false from a higher level or scientific point of view. Indeed, their truth or falsehood was rather the expression of their adequacy regarding a choice of a scientific system. Herewith truth in science became in principle hypothetical in character (Poincaré). Such a position was denounced as a scientistic view. But I think one can effectively limit arbitrary relativism by the adoption of a dialogical framework. In doing so, one can distinguish a “primary” dialogical game where the practical skills of object-competence and meta-competence are a source of knowledge without being knowledge. I exemplify this model in elementary arithmetic. Associate Professor Ihor Karivets’ Chair of Philosophy at L’viv Politechnic University 6 On the nature of common and scientific knowledge. Post(non)classical research. In the paper we would like to suggest that common and scientific knowledge derive from the thirst to know, which is based on the principle of pleasure. People are ruled by the principle of pleasure in their everyday life. We compare common and scientific knowledge and make conclusion that both of them have something in common. They are both limited, incomplete, repeated, experienced, practical. We can say that the destiny of man is enlightened ignorance. An ordinary man seeks compensation for his own ignorance in the every day repeatition of known facts, habits, stereotypes and schemes of cognition. Also, we emphasize that common and scientific knowledge are not completely reflexive, therefore they contain non-reflexive elements. Aristotele said that human is a creature who thirsts for knowledge even without realizing it. The aspiration to know the world makes the man dependent on the knowledge and then cognition becomes a drug. As it is known from psychoanalysis, the man is ruled in his/her life by the principle of pleasure. When the scientist discovers laws of nature or something new, he/she gets satisfaction from it. When an ordinary man discovers for himself/herself new countries or drinks his/her first glass of wine, then by getting new impressions and emotions, he/she also gets satisfaction from it. So we can make a preliminary conclusion that common and scientific knowledge are based on the the principle of pleasure, which evokes in man a thirst to know the world. That is why, the so-called pure theoretical knowledge is impossible, because it is also based on the thirst for truth (Plato said that Eros pushes a man to cognition; Eros is the cause of such a thirst). The common ground of the common and scientific knowledge is the principle of pleasure. There is no division between them in this aspect, because both depend on the wish to know. Igor Ly LPHS-Archives Poincaré (UMR 7117 CNRS) Université de Nancy2 « Espace commun et espace géométrique dans la philosophie de Poincaré » « Common space and geometrical space in Poincaré's philosophy » Au sein de ses écrits philosophiques relatifs à l’origine de la notion mathématique d’espace, Poincaré distingue ce qu’il appelle « l’espace sensible » – qui n’est en rien spatial – de l’espace géométrique, le premier étant précisément à l’origine du second. Ce point est fort connu. Si l’on prend par ailleurs en considération les nombreuses affirmations par lesquelles Poincaré oppose le sens commun et la connaissance scientifique, et en particulier la composante mathématique de celle-ci, on peut se demander quel statut peut être assigné au sein de sa philosophie à ce que nous appellerons l’espace commun, c’est-à-dire aux notions 7 spatiales non mathématiques, associées notamment aux termes spatiaux des langues usuelles comme ceux de « lieu », de « direction », de « distance », etc. Il ne fait en effet guère de doute que nous possédons de telles notions qui préexistent à l’élaboration mathématique de la géométrie. Poincaré rend-il compte de cela et réserve-t-il une place à cet espace commun ? L’objet de notre communication est de montrer que l’on peut donner une réponse positive à cette question. Pour ce faire, nous examinerons deux articles de Poincaré consacrés à la géométrie, dans lesquels apparaît explicitement la mention d’un « espace grossier » qui ne saurait s’identifier ni à l’espace sensible ni à l’espace géométrique. Nous tâcherons de montrer que cet espace correspond à l’espace commun et qu’il joue un rôle – parfois implicite – dans la façon dont Poincaré conçoit l’élaboration de la notion mathématique d’espace à partir de l’espace sensible. Un tel examen éclaire cette conception en permettant notamment de distinguer de façon précise ce qui relève de catégories spécifiquement mathématiques au sein de l’élaboration de la notion d’espace géométrique. Ce sont ainsi des éléments de réponse à la question de savoir ce qui distingue, selon Poincaré, la connaissance commune de la connaissance mathématique que nous espérons dégager de cette étude. Sébastien Réhault LPHS-Archives Poincaré (UMR 7117 CNRS) Université de Nancy2 Aesthetic properties in a physical world If one adopts the view called physicalism, roughly speaking the view that only science can tell the truth about what the world is like, then a lot of what commonly counts as knowledge falls short. In fact all propositions containing non physical predicates, although very useful and meaningful in human life, become literally false : the qualities and properties which they denote can’t really exist. Among the many predicates used by common sense that cannot be construed in a realist way from a physicalist point of view, we find aesthetic predicates such as « beautiful », « ugly », « delicate » or « garish ». The way such predicates are commonly used suggests that the properties they denote are really within things and not only expressions of feelings or other mental states. But that can’t be the case if one endorses an ontology that only admits physical properties and entities. One must eliminate that kind of properties from the fabric of the world or construe them as projections of mental states, themselves reducible to physical processes. As a consequence our ordinary aesthetic practice and the normativity that attaches with it looks quite irrational, because none of our aesthetic attributions can be objectively true. Common aesthetic discussions will inevitably be replaced by psychological explanations, themselves replaced by physical explanations. My aim is to defend aesthetic realism and the possibility of aesthetic knowledge against physicalism : aesthetic properties are real and our ordinary aesthetic attributions can bear on an independent reality when made in appropriate conditions. I argue that all attempts to eliminate or reduce aesthetic properties are untenable, leading to absurdities or 8 unconvincing explanations, and that correct aesthetic attributions grasp fundamental aspects of the world. But in no way do I argue for a Platonic view of aesthetic properties : they do not constitute a realm detached from the physical world. Neither do I argue for a strong antirealist conception of science, namely the view that the scientific conception of the world must be construed in a strictly instrumental way. The link between the physical and the aesthetic levels of reality will be understood in terms of supervenience and human dispositions. The supervenience thesis is essential to make aesthetic realism plausible: it does preserve the irreducibility of the aesthetics properties while conforming to the intuition that physical properties have a kind of ontological priority to non physical properties. I also discuss the thesis endorsed by Eddy Zemach that physical explanations take aesthetic considerations into account and that physicalism can’t deny the cognitive function of aesthetic attributions without contradiction. The purpose of this investigation is of course not to survey all the questions that arise from the dualism of common knowledge and scientific knowledge. But the case of aesthetic properties can be seen as paradigmatic, for aesthetic knowledge actually exhibits all the defects of common knowledge in their pure form. So if anti-physicalism succeeds here, it should succeed elsewhere. While modest in scope, the results of this reflection should benefit other fields of common knowledge containing non physical information about the world. Dr Fabien Schang Do they refer to the same “thing”? On the identity of logical constants For ‘a man in the street’ it is commonsensical both that either it is raining or not, on the one hand, and that it cannot rain and not rain at the same time, on the other hand. In contrast, for the ‘man in the university’ the above statements fail in some non-classical logical systems, especially intuitionist and paraconsistent logic. Who is right? Both, and neither… as long as the following data are not clearly defined: truth, falsity, negation, i.e. logical constants in a formal system (1) As against the actual widespread view, it will be noticed that the rejection of the law of excluded middle (hereafter: LEM) and the law of non-contradiction (hereafter; LNC) is not so obvious even for a non-classical logician. After all, did intuitionists really challenge the principle or “law” of excluded middle as such, or a similar but not identical formula? The same question can be addressed to paraconsistentists concerning the “principle” of non-contradiction. Quine nad Slatyer argued that paraconsistentists do not know the meaning of negation when they reject LNC; in contrast Béziau and Restall reply that the pure properties of negations are not constrained to the sole truth-conditions for the classical negation. Now, do LEM and LNC rule anything else than classical negation, that is, contradictory propositional relations? (2) In order to settle the problem, three-valued logics will be used while reinstating some more complex versions of LEM and LNC within a modal logic of truth, by the way, intuitionist logic can be viewed either as a weak extension of or as a deviation from classical logic. But how can one and the same logic include and be included in another logic? Is it still the same object? Think about the metaphysical problem of cross - 9 identity for individual constants through possible worlds; the same does here, as the logical problem of cross-identity for logical constants through possible systems. (3) The aim of this talk is not to argue definitely for or against logical pluralism, but to ask questions about the identity of logical systems and their formulas. Should we employ a syntactic or semantic criterion for this purpose? Such a problem is meaningful unless it is impossible to ensure the meaning of logical constants; as a particular but crucial case in point, we’ll consider the putative ‘pure’properties of logical negation and relate it with the notion of dichotomy, or complementation. Is there just one logical and, if not, what makes a distinction between the several ones? Dr habil. Anne-Françoise Schmid (INSA de Lyon et Archives Poincaré) La question du sens commun en épistémologie des théories et en épistémologie des modèles On connaissait bien les problématiques des rapports entre les sciences et le sens commun dans l’épistémologie dont le concept central était la théorie, rapport à la fois de « coupure » (la science critique les objets du sens commun) et de continuité (la science, comme le sens commun, admet son rapport au réel sans le problématiser). Les « objets » y sont « théoriques », au sens où les traits pertinents sont construits en fonction d’une théorie (mécanique, électricité, etc…). Avec la modélisation, les objets deviennent de plus en plus concrets et proches du sens commun : l’environnement, l’eau, le cancer, selon l’énumération de l’ancien président de la République Française. Plus un objet est concret, plus il demande des stratégies interdisciplinaires, et devient complexe. Qu’en est-il dans ce nouveau contexte du rapport de la science au sens commun ? Où se situent les frontières entre le commun et le complexe ? Ce sont elles qui détermineront les rapports des stratégies modélisatrices et du sens commun, maintenant souvent informé. On en tirera quelques conséquences sur la question de l’identité et des critères de la science face au sens commun. Dr Marek Pepliński Institute of Philosophy and Sociology Gdańsk University Chair of Philosophy WSG Bydgoszcz Is there one unique set of epistemic desiderata? Let us call, as William Alston does, the features of beliefs that are positively valuable from epistemic point of view “epistemic desiderata”. There are some candidates for epistemic desiderata; the set of such desiderata could contain such things as being true, being justified (in different meanings of that term), being instances of knowledge, being based on adequate evidence, being reliably formed, being instances of wisdom etc. First, Im m going to examine Alston’s proposition to alter the meaning of this term. Next, I want to consider the claim that there is only one set of such positively valuable features of belief or features that are epistemically valuable in general and argue that it is false. 10 Professor Roger Pouivet Nancy-Université, Université Nancy 2, LPHS Archives Poincaré, (CNRS, UMR 7117) Epistemic Circles, Common Sense, and Epistemic Virtues According to Thomas Reid, one principle of common sense is: . . . that the natural faculties, by which we distinguish truth from error, are not fallacious. If any man should demand a proof of this, it is impossible to satisfy him. For suppose it should be mathematically demonstrated, this would signify nothing in this case; because, to judge of a demonstration, a man must trust his faculties, and take for granted the very thing in question. (An Essay on the Intellectual Powers of Man, VI, 5). This paper comments on Reid’s claim, focusing on the notion of epistemic circularity implicit in it. Contrary to what Foundationalists and Skeptics think, epistemic circularity can be “benign”, and not a bad thing from the epistemological point of view. In a certain sense, benign epistemic circularity and common sense are one and the same. The reliability and trustworthiness of our faculties are common sense intuitions that permit knowledge, rather than posing obstacles to scientific knowledge. It may be asked, “What is common to scientific and common knowledge?” Not their objects or their methods, which are admittedly quite different. Yet, Gaston Bachelard, for example, was wrong to think that there is a great gap between them. They both depend on the same human faculties, and upon the best use of these faculties, which characterize our intellectual life and represent the highest development of our human nature. Such a life may be called an “epistemically virtuous life”. Dr Monika Walczak Department of Methodology and Philosophy of Science Faculty of Philosophy John Paul II Catholic University of Lublin Science and Common Sense in the Philosophy of Bernard Lonergan (1904-1984) T The paper discusses relations (similarities and differences) between science and common sense in the context of the philosophy of a Canadian philosopher and theologian Bernard Lonergan, especially in his Opus vitae: Insight: A Study of Human Understanding (London 1957, the Critical Edition: Toronto 1992). Lonergan's philosophy is located at the crossroads of different philosophical traditions: thomism, transcendentalism of I. Kant, phenomenology and existentialism. It is interpreted as a form of transcendental thomism, or as a version of phenomenology (self-appropriation phenomenology). The main subject matter of Lonergan's philosophy is knowing, a cognitional activity of a particular knowing subject. His 11 basic thrust is toward "methodology". He tries to understand how the human mind works, and/or should work in the act of knowing and the process of building up a body of knowledge. Lonergan's transcendental method is seen as epistemology with the ambition of giving methodological and metaphysical grounds for philosophy, theology and contemporary science and culture. Lonergan tries to answer the question about the conditions of the possibility of knowledge and about the role of the human subject in the acquisition of knowledge that claims to be concerned with reality. He looks for answers in a phenomenological analysis of the human subject in the entire range of his/her conscious and intentional life. Science (mathematics and the natural sciences) is treated by Lonergan as a paradigmatic pattern of knowing. Although the dynamic structure of knowing (experiencing, understanding, judging) and generating knowledge is immanent and recurrently operative in every human cognitional activity, it is science – with its method – which is most effective in achieving valuable epistemic results in investigating the world. The dynamic structure of knowing is also operative in common sense (common sense knowing), but its range of interests and its aims are more diverse than in science. The most important difference between science and common sense consists in the degree of realization of the intellectual pattern of experience. The scientist as such – more than other people – develops a habit (a disposition) of discriminating between his/her purely epistemic (intellectual) activities and the many other, "existential" concerns that invade and mix with the operations of the mind. The scientist is interested in being an objective knower and in a self-appropriation, i.e. the process of getting oneself into the intellectual pattern of experience in order to attain a detached, disinterested, unrestricted desire to know. The desire to know manifests itself in dissatisfaction with the actual state of knowledge and the raising of new questions. To discuss Lonergan's position I address the following issues: (1) Lonergan's intellectual biography, (2) a general account of his philosophy, (3) his characteristics of science, (4) his position on common sense, and (5) his views on relations between science and common sense. Professor Jan Hertrich -Woleński Institute of Philosophy (Jagiellonian University, Kraków) Does ‘common’ mean the same in ‘common sense’, ‘common knowledge’ and ‘common law’ ? The adjective “common” plays an important role in jurisprudence and philosophy. As far as the matter concerns philosophical issues, we have Scottish philosophy of common sense (Thomas Reid) and G.E. Moore’s famous essay “In Defence of Common Sense”. British as well as American legal system is usually called “common law” and contrasted with continental legal culture. For my talk it is not particularly important that common law is made by courts and precedents and continental law develops mainly by issuing statutes. I am interested in the meaning of “common” in “common law” and “common sense”. A typical legal explanation is that common law consists of rules shared by a community (lex communis). However, we have also the term “sensus communis” used by ancient and medieval philosophers. If we look for principles of legal interpretation embodied by common 12 law, we can say that they appeal to elementary rational principles of justice and rationality assumed to be common to all people. Moore argued that some strange idealistic philosophical views can be refuted by using evident common belief. It is a temptation to interpret philosophical “common sense” as “ordinary”. This seems incorrect. We should rather think about “common sense” as natural rationality of humans. Associate Professor dr hab. Renata Ziemińska Institute of Philosophy Szczecin University Common Knowledge and Scientific Knowledge: Difference and Interdependence Common and scientific knowledge are two kinds of human knowledge (justified true beliefs). Scientific knowledge, approximately, is knowledge with specific features: new in the world, gained by using established methods, rationally justified on a basis of empirical data and in a system of other accepted beliefs (systematic), expressed in inter-subjective and precise language, and self-improving (critical and fallible). Common knowledge contains all information we encounter in everyday life and reasonably accept as our beliefs (the standards of reasonability are not very demanding; hurry and emotions are tolerated). It probably (if the condition of truth is fulfilled) encloses most of our everyday beliefs about the world, maybe some popular religious, moral and esthetical beliefs, some practical knowledge how to earn money or get food, how to communicate and make decisions etc. The common beliefs are practical and useful but difficult to express in exact language. Scientific knowledge is different from common knowledge (language, justification, method). But the strict demarcation is a problem. Many philosophers say that science has no method, no superiority over other kinds of knowledge and that the demarcation is artificial. We must admit that science is small part of human life and culture and that practical knowledge is more fundamental for everyday survival and happiness. But we also see that scientific practices are better than any set of non-scientific practices for reliable and effective predictions. There is a dynamic interdependence between those two kinds of human knowledge. First, scientific knowledge is dependent on common knowledge both as source and everyday support. Second, scientific knowledge is more effective and reliable and in this sense superior to common knowledge. Scientific knowledge provides intellectual enrichment and leads to technological advances. Third, applied and popularized scientific knowledge is taught at schools and partly incorporated into common knowledge. But, fourth, common sense must still supervise science to avoid effects like environmental degradation. Common knowledge usually supervises our activities, so it also supervises scientific practices.