2004/05/04 Lecture 10 Naturalistic Philosophy in Theory and Practice Naturalism One question: what kind of theory should the “philosophy of science” (hereafter, POS) try to develop? Logical empiricists (hereafter, LE): the POS is concerned above all with the logic of science. But, by the middle of 1970s, LE’s view broke down. POS had to go beyond logical analysis, but what should be done instead? Naturalism: “philosophy should be continuous with science.” But, what does it really mean? Reject the idea that philosophy should be sharply separated from other fields. There should be some kind of close connection between scientific theories and philosophical theories, but the topic that what this connection should be like is debatable. Philosophy should be “continuous” with science. But, what does this “continuity” mean for actual scientific practices? A useful summarized idea of naturalism may answer the question: philosophy can use results from the sciences to help answer philosophical questions and can do this even in the philosophy of science itself. Criticism of vicious circularity: to use scientific ideas when theorizing about science involves a vicious circularity. The main reason is that we should not assume, at the outset, the reliability of the scientific ideas that we are trying to investigate and assess. We have to stand outside of science when we are trying to describe its most general features and assess the integrity of its methods. Foundationalist attack: we should do the POS from an external and more secure standpoint. Requirements: no assumptions be made about the accuracy of particular scientific ideas when doing POS. The reason is that, before our philosophical theory is established, the status of scientific work is in doubt. So naturalism is generally described as opposing to foundationalism. Naturalism: the project of trying to give general philosophical foundations for science is always doomed to fail. A philosophical foundation is not something science needs 1 in any case. Instead, we can only hope to develop an adequate description of how knowledge and science work if we draw on scientific ideas as we go. And the description of knowledge and science that results will be no more certain or secure than the scientific theories themselves. The aforementioned sketch of naturalism would be agreed by most philosophers who call themselves naturalists. From there on, there is a lot of disagreement. The term “Naturalism” suggests that one’s theories contain “no artificial ingredients.”—> there is a risk that naturalism as a movement will be swamped by the overuse of the term and will dissolve into platitudes. Despite this risk, naturalism can be regarded as one possible way of hoping for solving the core problems of POS. Quine, Dewey, and Others The roots of contemporary naturalistic philosophy: Dewey: a pragmatist, but turned to naturalism from roughly 1925 onward (the later part of his career) Quine: Epistemology Naturalized (1969)—the birth of modern naturalism In this paper, Quine made the following claims: We should not expect philosophers to give “foundations” for scientific knowledge. Epistemological questions are so closely tied to questions in scientific psychology that epistemology should not survive as a distinct field at all, epistemology should be absorbed into psychology. The only questions asked by epistemologists that have any real importance are questions best answered by psychology itself. Philosophers should expect that psychology will eventually give us a purely scientific description of how beliefs are formed and how they change, and we should ask for no more. —> science as the only proper source of questions as well as the source of answers. Another version of naturalism: there is such a thing as philosophical question, distinct from the kinds of questions asked by scientists. A naturalist can think that science can contribute to the answers to philosophical questions, without thinking that science should replace philosophical questions with scientific questions. If we think that philosophical questions are important and also tend to differ from those asked by scientists, there is no reason to expect a replacement of epistemology by psychology and other sciences. Science is used as resource for philosophy, not as a replacement. What might be examples of these questions that remain relevant in naturalist 2 philosophy but which are not directly addressed within science itself? Example 1: Normative questions—questions that involve a value judgment. If epistemology was absorbed by psychology, we might get a good description of how beliefs are actually formed, but apparently we would not be told which belief-forming mechanisms are good and which are bad. We would not be able to address the epistemological questions that have to do with how we should handle evidence, and how we can tell a good argument from a bad one. For the naturalist, the answers to these questions will often depend on facts about psychological mechanisms and the connections that exist between our minds and the world. But the naturalist expects that it will remain the task of philosophy to actually try to answer these questions. The sciences tend to concern themselves with different issues. Normative naturalism—naturalistic views that want to retain the normative side of epistemology. ( this term was coined by Larry Lauden (1987))—>toward the end of his career, Quine modified his view and brought it closer to normative naturalism. —accepts many of the normative questions that have been passed down to us from traditional epistemology. What is the basis for making these value judgments? What is the basis for a distinction between good and bad policies for forming beliefs?—> the old and difficult problem of locating values in the world of facts. Normative naturalists chose a simple reply—the value judgments relevant to epistemology are made in an instrumental way. In philosophical discussions of decision-making, an action is said to be instrumentally rational if it is a good way of achieving the goal that the agent is pursuing, what ever that goal might be. When assessing actions according to their instrumental rationality, we do not worry about where the goals come from or whether they are appropriate goals. We just ask whether the action is likely to achieve the outcome that the agent desires. And if some action A is being used as a means to B, it is a factual matter whether or not A is likely to lead the agent to B. So it is a factual matter whether or not action A is instrumentally rational for that agent. Other related questions: is instrumental rationality the only kind of rationality? Among a person’s ultimate goals, which are justifiable? Dewey’s handling of the question of epistemological norms and values (1937, Logic): In Dewey’s epistemology, claims of “good” and “bad” reasoning are intended in the same way that we would understand claims about “good” and “bad” farming. Everyone is aware that some farming techniques are better than others at achieving 3 the usual sorts of goals that farmers have. The likely consequences of different farming decisions are a factual matter, and we learn about these consequences from experience. The methods of farming that we presently regard as good ones are not perfect, and they might be improved further in the future. But there is no philosophical problem with making value judgments of this kind. Dewey says that the same is true of value judgments in epistemology. Example 2: What kind of match (or mismatch) is there between our commonsense or everyday view of the world, on one hand, and the scientific picture of the world, on the other? Or What relationship is there between the common-sense or everyday picture of human knowledge, and a scientific description of our real contact with the world? → One of the fastest-moving and most interesting parts of naturalistic philosophy in recent decades has been the naturalistic philosophy of mind: How does the everyday picture of the human mind and its contents (thoughts, beliefs, desires, memories) compare with the picture of the mind that is emerging from psychology and neurobiology? Example 3: Questions about the relations between different sciences: The various (special) sciences each give us fragments, based on empirical work, of what the world is like and how it runs. But do the fragments tend to fit together neatly, or are there mismatches and tensions between them? The research in this topic can result in philosophical criticism of particular scientific ideas, but the criticism is made from the point of view of our overall scientific picture. A naturalistic position: Naturalism in philosophy requires that we begin our philosophical investigations from the standpoint provided by our best current scientific picture of human beings and their place in the universe. We begin from this picture, and we do not try to give a general justification, from outside of science, for our entitlement to use it. The science we rely on is not completely certain, of course, and may eventually change. The questions we try to answer, however, need not be derived from the sciences; our questions will often be rather traditional philosophical questions about the nature of belief, justification, and knowledge. 4 Science is a resource for settling philosophical questions, rather than a replacement for philosophy or the source of philosophy’s agenda. Philosophy’s another unusual and useful role in intellectual culture—acted as an incubator for novel, speculative ideas, giving them room to develop to a point where they may become scientifically useful. Philosophy often benefits from its somewhat loose organization and open-ended agenda. We never know what new ideas, issues, or approaches might appear. But to the extent that we can expect to solve the big problems in fields like epistemology, naturalism is probably the right approach. So, what questions should we address in naturalistic philosophy of science? Recall two sets of questions mentioned in Chapter 1: (1) a general understanding of how humans gain knowledge of the world around them, and (2) an understanding of what makes the work descended from the Scientific Revolution different from other kinds of investigation of the world. The notion of “responsiveness” to the world: -Theories of science proposed by some sociologists of science: no role the notion of responsiveness” can play in establishing a theory of scientific change. The reason is that experiments would be no more than expensive “public relation” exercises, and theories would change via a process of negotiation between factions. -How do we know that some science is not like this? In order to resolve this question, we need to distinguish some “in principle” questions and some “in practice” questions. In principle questions: does the nature of human thought and perception allow that scientific belief can be made responsive to the real structure of the world? In practice questions: Even if this is possible in principle, do actual scientific communities operate in a way that makes this responsiveness occurs in practice? -Suppose: we are indeed able to vindicate the idea that science is responsive to the world; then what sort of contact with the world do our successful theories achieve? It is familiar to think of truth as the goal that we set for our theories; a good theory is one that represents the world truly. But is the traditional concept of truth a coherent and useful one here? Does it help us understand scientific progress at all? In recent decades, philosophical discussions of science have become more responsive to a variety of sources of ideas. This broadened perspective on the kinds of 5 information that might be helpful has been a notable feature of recent philosophy. The Debate about the “Theory-Ladenness of Observation” -whether observational evidence can be considered an unbiased or neutral source of information when choosing between theories, or -whether observations tend to be “contaminated” by theoretical assumptions in a way that prevents them from having this role. -The problem is especially important for people who want to develop empiricist views, the reason is that advocates of radical theories of science have often seen the theory-ladenness of observation as a powerful argument against mainstream empiricism. -This problem can be much more easily settled if it is approached from a naturalistic point of view. → this issue gives us a hint of how naturalistic philosophy works in practice. -Empiricists have agreed that observation is our source of knowledge about the world. Observation has generally been seen as theory-neutral. This neutrality (=absence of bias) is often the basis for the claim that observation is an “objective” way to settle disagreements. -Anti-Neutrality argument (works by Hanson, Kuhn, Feyerabend): observation cannot function as an unbiased way of testing theories (or larger units like paradigms), because observational judgments are affected by the theoretical beliefs of the observer. Therefore, traditional empiricist views about the role of observation in science are false. The possible topics in the debate: 1. Arguments about observation concern theory’s influence: -Observation is guided by theory, because theories tell scientists where to look and what to look for. This claim is true, but this fact does not affect the capacity of observation to act as a test of theory, unless scientists are refusing to look where unfriendly observations might be found. All empiricists would regard that as a breakdown of fundamental scientific procedures. -Scientists must use theoretical assumptions to decide which observations to take seriously. Some apparent observations might involve malfunctions or mistakes of various kinds and can be disregarded. The observations that affect theory choice are “filtered” through a process in which some data are discarded. Because theoretical beliefs affect this filtering, there is the possibility of bias here. 6 2. Arguments about observation concern language: When a scientist has an experience, ho or she can only make this experience relevant to science by putting it into words. The vocabulary used, and the meanings of even innocent-looking terms, will be influenced by the scientist’s theoretical framework. Given the interconnections between the meanings of words in a language, there is no part of language whose application to phenomena is totally “theory-free”. -But, simply to show that the language of observation is in some sense “theoretical” is not sufficient to claim that empiricism is dead. In working out the relevance of the issue to more modern forms of empiricism, everything depends on (1) which kinds of theories affect the language of observation and on (2) the nature of this effect. -For example, maybe observational reports assume “theories” that are so low-level that the testing of real scientific theories will never be affected. → Example: the effect of the (theoretical) assumption that objects retain their shape when we are not looking at them on the observation reports does not usually matter to testing in science. (for condition (1)) -Suppose that observation reports are affected by the kinds of theories that are themselves being tested. This kind of effect may or may not be philosophically important. A theory might contribute the concepts used to express an observation, without this affecting the capacity of an observation report to test the theory in question. Not every result described in terms of the concepts preferred by theory T will be an observation report that is favorable to theory T. → Example: An observation of rabbit fossils in Precambrian rocks would be a massive shock to evolutionary theory. In this example, it is clear that the fact that observation reports are expressed using concepts derived from a theory ahs no effect on the capacity of nature to say NO to a conjecture. (for condition (2)) 3. Arguments about observation concern experiences: Some people argue that even the experiences themselves that a person has are influenced by their beliefs, including their theories. Not just the use of observation reports in assessing theories, and not just the linguistic form of the reports are affected, but the perceptual experiences themselves are. There is NO STAGE in the processes of observation in science where theories do not play a role. (This is the most important aspect of the criticism against empiricism) -Using the results of psychological research to refute a “passive” view of perception and replacing it with a view holding that perception is active and intelligent. → Argument: Due to the fact that there are multiple ways in which a pattern of stimulation on the retina could be caused by objects in the world, theoretical 7 assumptions must be used by the visual system to make a choice. People have taken the result from the study of the Müller-Lyer illusion to show a kind of theory-ladenness in perception—we do not realize it, but our general and implicit beliefs about the world are affecting what we see. Counter argument (Jerry Fodor): -Although it is true that the illusions seem to be produced by the effects of unconscious theory, some pieces of theory or background knowledge seem to have no effect on perception. → Example: the illusion is not affected by the knowledge that it is an illusion, or by knowledge of the theory of illusions. Those pieces of background knowledge do not make the illusion go away. -Fodor links this argument to a research program in psychology that posits modules in the explanation of perception and some other tasks. Modules are automatic, innate pieces of mental machinery that do their processing unconsciously and make use of a fixed subset of a person’s background knowledge. In perception, modules send their output to the “central” cognitive mechanisms. These central mechanisms have access to all a person’s theories and ideas when working out what to do with the observation. So, although the later stages of responding to observation are affected, in principle, by all the theories a person might have, the output of the perceptual module is not. The module’s operation—which determines how things seem to a person—is not biased by whether the person accepts one scientific theory or another. -Fodor reminded that even if observation itself is not biased by commitments to scientific theories, there is still the issue of what a person does with the observation. That takes us back again to the problem of holism about testing. The aforementioned discussion about the role of observation in science provides support for a naturalistic approach to POS—Observation is a natural phenomenon, studied by fields like psychology and psychophysics. Those disciplines tell us what perceptual mechanisms are like and what kind of connection we have to the world via these mechanisms. Naturalistic philosophers can put these results to use in working out how observation operates in science generally. A version of empiricism that follows a naturalistic approach to the role of observation: -What is the role of observation in science? → Need to understand the actual role of observation in the sociological patterns of scientific activity. -How is observation used as a resource in science? -How is it used in the settlement of controversies? 8 → Start to feed in results from the scientific study of observation. Given (1) the kind of connection to the world that observation provides, and (2) the role of observation in science, -What kind of contact does science itself have with the world? If observation is the channel by which theory makes contact with reality, -What kind of channel is it? →This is a question that we can only answer by drawing on the empirical sciences that deal with observation and perception. If empiricism about science is vindicated by the answers to these questions, it will be a form of empiricism that differs from traditional forms. Observation: a form of physical contact between our minds and the world. This contact is the product of evolution, and it has whatever degree of reliability it has because of our evolutionary history and the contingent relationships between our structure and that of our surroundings. Science: an attempt to exploit this contact between our minds and the world. Science is also motivated by the limitations that result from our relations to the world; we need science because much of the world is not accessible to ordinary observation. Science works by taking theoretical ideas and trying to find ways to expose them to observation. The scientific strategy: an action to construe ideas, to embed them in surrounding conceptual frameworks, and to develop them, in such a way that this exposure is possible even in the case of the most general and ambitious hypotheses about the universe. A naturalistic empiricism: This is a form of empiricism in which naturalism is primary. In this form of empiricism, the advantages of empiricist philosophical ideas are not shown or established by philosophy alone; they are shown or established also by various other scientific disciplines that feed in their relevant research results to the construction of the content of this form of empiricism. 9