R. Barney Spring 2009 Method and Genre in Aristotle’s Metaphysics, A.3 1. The standard scholarly line is that Metaphysics A.3-10 should not be read as ‘history of philosophy’: but that denial is based on some oddly narrow assumptions about what history of philosophy must be. Let’s look at the text with an open mind: 2. Aristotle’s project in A.3 is, as announced, to survey his predecessors in order to see whether his theory of the four causes adapted for principles) (as expounded use as needs a in theory to be the of Physics first II, causes supplemented. and and here first Though it superficially resembles other predecessor-surveys near the beginnings of the De Anima, Physics and On Generation and Corruption, A.3ff. is unlike them in its argumentative function and its strategy. Formally, it is a search for alternatives or additions to an account already offered. Through its completeness failure, and this adequacy of search will that account, confirm roughly the as follows: ‘P. One might propose instead Q, R, S, or T; but Q, R, S and T can all be reduced to P. Therefore P (and P alone).’ 3. Aristotle’s principles: presentation a diairesis interweaves two (‘division’) structural of earlier philosophers according to which archai (first principles) they recognised, and how many; and a historical narrative. 4. Aristotle’s presentation is also partially determined by his two reference texts: Hippias’ Sunagôgê and Plato’s R. Barney Spring 2009 dialectical account of previous theories of being (ta onta) in the Sophist. Aristotle’s reliance on Hippias is shown in his treatment of Thales and Hippo. The Sophist seems to have been Aristotle’s model for combining the diairetic and narrative modes. 5. Aristotle’s engagement with earlier thinkers in A.3-10 is, like Plato’s treatment of the ‘gods and giants’ in the Sophist, an exercise in Eudemian dialectic: a kind of constructive refutation or correction of endoxic views in order to make them usable as a starting-point for dialectical inquiry into principles. 6. Key components of Eudemian dialectic include interpretive charity and a dialogic mode of presentation: earlier views are canvassed for their distinctive positive contributions to the discovery of the truth, and their proponents are presented as amenable to rational correction through discussion. 7. Aristotle’s adoption of the historical mode in A.3 is shaped by his commitment to the internal logic claim, viz that the truth (or the subject-matter) itself provoked and shaped further inquiry into the principles (particularly in the discovery of the efficient cause). Versions of the internal logic claim are uncommon in Aristotle, and not easily understood -- though they must express Aristotle’s general progressivism about the arts and sciences, and his (still more general) epistemic optimism. 8. Aristotle’s use of historical narrative in A.3 must also be shaped by his broad interest in the progressive R. Barney Spring 2009 historical revealed development by of Peripatetic the arts studies of and the sciences, as history of mathematics, medicine etc. 9. Conclusion: Eudemian dialectic and progressivist historical narrative combine easily, and both are canonical genres of ‘history of philosophy’. That Aristotle is engaged in history of philosophy of a quite familiar sort is also suggested by various details of his procedures, e.g. his concern with canon-formation. Since there are no plausible candidates for a predecessor text combining these generic features, we should read Metaph. A.3-10 as the text in which Aristotle philosophy’. invents the discipline ‘history of