Comments on Brandon Watson’s “The Universe of the Imagination: Malebranche’s Walking-Soul Argument and Treatise 1.2.6” It is generally acknowledged that Hume’s philosophical debt to Malebranche is enormous. On 26th August 1737, shortly after leaving La Flèche where he wrote most of his Treatise of Human Nature, Hume wrote a letter to a friend in Britain suggesting four works which would be of help in understanding the metaphysical parts of his reasoning, the first of which being Malebranche’s The Search After Truth.1 While the influence of Malebranche on Hume has been duly recognized in the areas of causation, selfknowledge, and natural belief, Watson argues in his interesting paper that there is a further link between these two philosophers in the area of external existence which has up until now gone unrecognized in Hume scholarship (p. 1). I will first briefly summarize Watson’s argument, and then offer two comments. In the second part of the third book of the Search After Truth, devoted to the nature of ideas, Malebranche argued for his famous doctrine of the vision in God. More precisely, the thesis is that we see external objects by means of ideas in God. The argument for this thesis begins with the claim that it is universally agreed upon that we do not directly perceive external objects themselves, since we see the sun and the stars and it can hardly be the case that “the soul should leave the body to stroll about the heavens” to see the objects present there (Search 217). What we perceive instead are ideas. The minds immediate object thus when it sees the sun is not the sun, but an idea of the sun. Watson first points out that a passage in Hume’s account of external existence at Treatise 1.2.6 sounds very much like Malebranche’s own claim that it is only through the presence of The other works that Hume mentions in the letter to his friend included Berkeley’s Principles of Human Knowledge, the more metaphysical articles of Bayle’s Dictionary (such as those on Zeno and Spinoza), and finally Descartes’s Meditations on First Philosophy. 1 1 ideas that we can perceive material bodies (page 8). Here Hume presents a universal principle that, “nothing is ever really present with the mind but its perceptions or impressions and ideas, and that external objects become known to us only by those perceptions they occasion” (THN 1.2.6.7; SBN 67). Since the mind has nothing but perceptions in front of it, even when we focus our attention “to the heavens, or to the utmost limits of the universe; we never really advance a step beyond ourselves, nor can conceive any kind of existence, but those perceptions” (THN 1.2.6.8; SBN 67). Watson further claims that recognizing Malebranche’s influence on Hume “sheds interesting light on the passage in question” (page 10). The passage in question presents a “short elegant argument that indicates the impossibility of our having any ideas of external existence not of the same kind as our perceptions” (page 11). Hume can be seen as pointing out the consequences of the walking-soul argument by turning Malebranche’s argument against all views that place a “veil of ideas” between our minds and external objects, including Malebranche’s own favored theory of intelligible extension (page 11)! Watson presents an admirably clear and convincing case for seeing a connection between Malebranche and Hume on external existence, and a plausible interpretation of Treatise 1.2.6 in which Hume cleverly turns the tables on Malebranche’s own positive account of external objects. In response, I will confine myself to two comments. The first comment concerns Watson’s claim that Malebranche’s influence on Hume in the area of external existence at Treatise 1.2.6 has, to his knowledge, gone unnoticed in scholarship. To my knowledge, also, this is an original point about this particular passage in the Treatise, although there is one secondary source I would recommend. John P. Wright in The Skeptical Realism of David Hume considers the 2 background to Hume’s account of our idea of external existence in physiological theories of perception, deriving in large part from Malebranche, and argues in favor of a “close connection” between Hume and Malebranche on the existence of the external world.2 Both philosophers, he argues, make a clear distinction between internal perceptions and independent external objects, and stress that we are only directly aware of our own perceptions.3 Wright’s evidence for this connection is not drawn from Treatise 1.2.6, however, but rather from ‘Of scepticism with regard to the senses’ at Treatise 1.4.2. He points to Hume’s denial that our own bodies are perceived in space on the grounds that when we perceive our bodies, we perceive only “certain impressions, which enter by the senses,” and claims that “Hume’s doctrine that we do not directly perceive the parts of our own bodies seems to be taken over” from Malebranche’s Search After Truth.4 Wright also draws attention to the role that natural belief plays in their respective accounts of external existence. He argues that both philosophers believe that we have a strong natural propensity to believe that a world of external objects exists, and that this propensity, by its very existence, gives some justification for the belief that these objects exist.5 The second comment concerns the universal principle. The universal principle appears three times in Book 1 of the Treatise (in 1.2.6.7 ‘Of the idea of existence, and of external existence,’ in ‘Of skepticism with regard to the senses’ at 1.4.2.21, and in ‘Of the immateriality of the soul’ at 1.4.5.15). The principle also turns up again in Book 2 in his theory of the passions (in ‘Experiments to confirm this system’ at 2.2.2.22), and in his moral theory in Book 3 (in ‘Moral distinctions not deriv’d from reason’ at 3.1.1.2). The 2 The Sceptical Realism of David Hume, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1983, see chapter 2, especially p. 42. 3 The Sceptical Realism of David Hume, p. 42; see also p. 87. 4 The Sceptical Realism of David Hume, p. 42 5 The Sceptical Realism of David Hume, pp. 74-5. 3 principle also appears in the final section on skepticism in An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding (Enquiry 12.9-16; SBN 152-5). Given that the principle plays such an important part in his system, examining those philosophers who might have influenced Hume on this point is no small matter. Now Watson is certainly not committed to the claim that Malebranche is the only possible influence here (pp. 9 and 11n.8), however, in order to arrive at a sound judgment about the extent of Malebranche’s influence on Hume in this passage, it would be worthwhile to consider some of the other philosophers that Hume might have had in mind. There is for example good evidence to suggest that Arnauld and Nicole’s The Art of Thinking also influenced Hume when he wrote the Treatise; indeed, he mentions this work as one of “the common systems of logic” alongside Malebranche’s Search After Truth and Locke’s Essay Concerning Human Understanding in the Abstract to the Treatise.6 Some philosophers have even compared Book 1 of Hume’s Treatise with The Art of Thinking.7 The important point is that Arnauld and Nicole begin their discussion of the nature and origin of ideas with a claim similar to the upshot of the walking-soul argument, that “we can have no knowledge of what is outside us except by means of the ideas in us.”8 Then there is Locke to consider. Watson acknowledges in a footnote that Locke offers something like the walking-soul argument in the second book of the Essay on the origin of ideas (II.1.24), although he argues that the parallel is not as close (page 11n.8). There are certainly other passages in Locke’ Essay however that are very See the fourth paragraph of the Abstract to the Treatise. For an excellent account of Hume’s acquaintance with The Art of Thinking and other logic texts, see Charles Echelbarger’s “Hume and the Logicians,” in Logic and the Workings of the Mind: The Logic of Ideas and Faculty Psychology in Early Modern Philosophy, volume 5, edited by P. Easton, Ridgeview Publishing Company: Atascadero California, 1997. 7 See Hendel’s introductory essay in Arnauld and Nicole, The Art of Thinking, translated by J. Dickoff and P. James, Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1964. 8 Antoine Arnauld and Pierre Nicole, Logic or The Art of Thinking (1662), translated by J. V. Buroker, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996, p. 25. 6 4 suggestive of the same point as the walking-soul argument. In the famous discussion of primary and secondary qualities, he defines an idea as the “immediate object of perception” (Essay 2.8.8). He goes on to say at the very beginning of the fourth book on human knowledge that, “Since the Mind … hath no other immediate Object but its own Ideas, which it alone does or can contemplate, it is evident, that our Knowledge is only conversant about them” (Essay 4.1.1). It stands to reason that Locke’s focus when explaining our knowledge of the existence of external objects is our ideas, as it is the “actual receiving of Ideas from without that gives us notice” of the existence of external things (Essay 4.11.2). It is not part of Watson’s argument that Hume only has Malebranche in mind at Treatise 1.2.6, but there is no doubt that exploring some of the other philosophers who also embraced the universal principle will assist in determining the exact nature of Malebranche’s influence on Hume. The next step would then be to see how well their views fit the view criticized by Hume at Treatise 1.2.6 (page 11n.8). Angela M. Coventry Portland State University 5