The New York Times 11 May 2002 So God’s Really In the Details? by Emily Eakin Economists use probability theory to make forecasts about consumer spending. Actuaries use it to calculate insurance premiums. Last month, Richard Swinburne, a professor of philosophy at Oxford University, put it to work toward less mundane ends: he invoked it to defend the belief that Jesus was resurrected from the dead. “For someone dead for 36 hours to come to life again is, according to the laws of nature, extremely improbable,” Mr. Swinburne told an audience of more than 100 philosophers who had convened at Yale University in April for a conference on ethics and belief. “But if there is a God of the traditional kind, natural laws only operate because he makes them operate.” Mr. Swinburne, a commanding figure with snow-white hair and piercing blue eyes, proceeded to weigh evidence for and against the Resurrection, assigning values to factors like the probability that there is a God, the nature of Jesus’ behavior during his lifetime and the quality of witness testimony after his death. Then, while his audience followed along on printed lecture notes, he plugged his numbers into a dense thicket of letters and symbols — using a probability formula known as Bayes’s theorem — and did the math. “Given e and k, h is true if and only if c is true,” he said. “The probability of h given e and k is .97” In plain English, this means that, by Mr. Swinburne’s calculations, the probability of the Resurrection comes out to be a whopping 97 percent. While his highly technical lectures may not net Christianity many fresh converts, Mr. Swinburne’s efforts to bring inductive logic to bear on questions of faith have earned him a considerable reputation in the small but vibrant world of Christian academic philosophy. Thanks to the efforts of Mr. Swinburne and a handful of other nimble scholarly minds — including Alvin Plantinga at the University of Notre Dame and Nicholas Wolterstorff at Yale — religious belief no longer languishes in a state of philosophical disrepute. Deploying a range of sophisticated logical arguments developed over the last 25 years, Christian philosophers have revived faith as a subject of rigorous academic debate, steadily chipping away at the assumption — all but axiomatic in philosophy since the Enlightenment — that belief in God is logically indefensible. “They are the first group within 20th-century Anglo-American philosophy to tackle questions of religious faith using the tools of philosophy,” said Brian Leiter, a professor of law and philosophy at the University of Texas at Austin and editor of the Philosophical Gourmet Report, which ranks academic philosophy departments. “It would be accurate to say that it’s a growth movement.” Mr. Wolterstorff, who retired from Yale in December and in whose honor the conference was organized, agreed. “And it’s not just graybeards,” he added, referring to the dozens of younger scholars and graduate students in attendance. “Within the general discipline, this development of the philosophy of religion has been extraordinary.” To be sure, not all of the movement’s philosophers agree with one another, use the same tactics or even hold the same religious beliefs. Some, including Mr. Swinburne, for example, are what’s known as evidentialists: they accept the Enlightenment doctrine that a belief is justified only when evidence can be found for it outside the believer’s own mind. According to the classic evidentialist argument, for faith to be considered rational it has to be supported by independent proof, and there simply isn’t any. (Asked what he would say if God appeared to him after his death and demanded to know why he had failed to believe, the British philosopher and staunch evidentialist Bertrand Russell replied that he would say, “Not enough evidence, God! Not enough evidence.”) In “The Existence of God” (Oxford University Press, 1979), Mr. Swinburne, a Greek Orthodox Christian, tried to meet the evidentialist challenge using Bayes’s theorem. Supplying pages of intricate, technical argumentation to back up his claims, he wrote that many natural phenomena — including the universe itself — are, well, if not incontrovertible proof of God’s handiwork, at least “more probable if there is a God than if there is not.” (Mr. Swinburne, it turns out, is not the first to enlist Bayes’s theorem in defense of religion. In a 1763 paper presented to the British Royal Society, the minister Richard Price used it to show there was good evidence in favor of the miracles described in the New Testament.) More influential at the moment, however, are the “reformed epistemologists” led by Mr. Plantinga and Mr. Wolterstorff, who are Calvinists. These scholars reject the evidentialist insistence on independent proofs. After all, they point out, the ability to distinguish good evidence from bad requires reason, but why trust our ability to reason? Where’s the proof that our reason is any good? For the evidentialists, reason is considered a “basic belief,” one that doesn’t require additional evidence to be true. But if reason can be considered a basic belief, then so, too, say the reformed epistemologists, can faith in God. Accepting faith as a basic belief, they say, does not make faith irrational. On the contrary, they insist, a belief can lack independent evidence and still be rational. Some beliefs are simply selfevident. Most people know that 1 + 1 = 2, Mr. Wolterstorff points out, just as they accept beliefs about their bodily state — like “I feel dizzy” — without having to consult other sources. “We believe lots of things that don’t have publicly formulated arguments,” Mr. Wolterstorff said. “Reformed epistemology challenges the need for arguments.” To buttress their case, the reformed epistemologists lean on Thomas Reid, an 18thcentury Scottish “common sense” philosopher, who, arguing that many legitimate beliefs are simply instinctual, complained: “Are we to admit nothing but can be proved by reason?” But despite their intricate arguments, some critics — including Christians — worry that reformed epistemologists make it far too easy to justify any belief, no matter how absurd. Mr. Plantinga calls this the Great Pumpkin Objection. As he stated the problem in a seminal 1983 essay, “Reason and Belief in God”: “If belief in God is properly basic, why cannot just any belief be properly basic? What about voodoo or astrology? What about the belief that the Great Pumpkin returns every Halloween? Could I properly take that as basic?” The answer, as you’d expect, is “certainly not.” But explaining why turns out to be a formidable challenge. Mr. Plantinga has devoted three thick volumes and the last 20 years to the effort, stressing, among other things, that for a belief to be justified, it must be held by a person whose mental faculties are functioning properly. More aggressively, he has suggested that our capacity for true beliefs is proof that a divine creator — rather than Darwinian natural selection — is behind evolution: if human beings evolved by random process from mentally primitive creatures, how could we be sure that any of our beliefs — including our belief in evolution — are true? At the Yale conference, however, neither Darwin nor the Great Pumpkin Objection seemed any more pressing than conundrums that have dogged Christianity far longer — occasionally giving the event the aura of a medieval synod. If God is omnipotent and wholly good, why does he permit evil to occur? the philosophers wondered. And if God ultimately decides what happens in the world, in what sense can human beings be said to have free will? Mr. Swinburne also came in for his share of questions. “Bayes’s theorem provides a model of learning from experience,” one philosopher observed. “As time goes by, it seems you would accumulate more evidence against the Resurrection because the expected Second Coming doesn’t occur.” Mr. Swinburne acknowledged the point was worth considering. But he wasn’t about to concede it entirely. When Jesus spoke about the Second Coming, “he might have said soon but he certainly didn’t say when,” Mr. Swinburne insisted, adding, “I don’t think you have a very strong case there.”