Ontology and Bodily Systems Igor Papakin1, Barry Smith, PhD1,2, Katherine Munn1, Werner Ceusters3, MD 1 Institute for Formal Ontology and Medical Information Science Faculty of Medicine, University of Leipzig, Leipzig, Germany 2 Department of Philosophy, University at Buffalo, Buffalo, NY 3 Language & Computing nv, Zonnegem, Belgium ABSTRACT Contemporary medical science represents the human body as a system made of systems. Why is this so? And what does the term ‘bodily system’ mean? On what principle do we divide the body into systems as we do? Such questions must be answered if we are to translate our informal knowledge of the medical domain into a form that is useable by computers. We provide a framework for a definition of the term ‘bodily system’ that is able to do justice to the ways in which standard rosters of bodily systems differ amongst themselves. The framework can be extended to provide an ontology of the anatomical domain within which also the functions of anatomical features can play a role. INTRODUCTION AND BACKGROUND Ontology plays an increasingly significant role in work on terminology and knowledge management systems in the biomedical domain and we hold that ontology will play an essential part in the medical informatics of the future. The term ‘ontology’ must, however, be understood in the right sort of way.1 The dominant paradigm might be referred to as ‘applications ontology.’ This holds that the ontologist should focus primarily on the construction of ontologies as working applications; the expressive power of an ontology is thereby limited effectively to that of one or other version of Description Logic.2 This means that an ontology, when applied to complex domains such as those of biomedicine, is forced to deal with simplified models. There is, however, a second ‘reference ontology’ school of thought, which focuses primarily on the development of ontological theories of the entities in given domains. Such theories are marked by a high degree of representational adequacy and are designed to be used as controls on the results achieved by working applications rather than as substitutes for these working applications themselves.3 Three levels of reference ontology can be distinguished in the biomedical domain: 1. formal ontology: a top-level domain-independent theory involving the use of concepts such as: object, process, identity, part, location; 2. domain ontology: a top-level theory applying the structure of a formal ontology to the medical domain, involving concepts such as: body, disease, therapy, organ, tissue, cell, and so forth; 3. terminology-based ontology: a very large lowerlevel system, based on medical terminologies such as UMLS, and involving specific concepts such as: inflammatory change in the gastric mucosa. The present paper is a contribution to medical ontology under heading 2, focusing on the question: what is a bodily system? It thus supplements the work of Rosse,4 who evaluates the Terminologia Anatomica,5 as a starting-point for generating machine-understandable representations of biomedical concepts. It also fills a gap in the work of the Digital Anatomist Project, whose definitions6 use the notion of ‘system’ but leave this notion unanalyzed. BODILY SYSTEMS IN MEDICINE Contemporary medical science represents the living human body (the human organism) as a system made of systems. The body’s systems serve as major provinces in our maps of human anatomy and thus they play a central role also in a variety of domains, from medical pedagogy and dynamic modeling to computer visualization. An understanding of the concept system is moreover a necessary part of any understanding of cognate concepts such as organ and function, and it is a prerequisite for the understanding of systemic diseases, both those which are localized in single systems and also those, such as diabetes, which affect a plurality of systems simultaneously. In constructing a domain ontology of medicine we need to start with the results of medical science as set forth in standard textbooks. Unfortunately the medical literature provides at best informal definitions of terms such as ‘bodily system’, ‘organ’, and so forth, and this helps to explain why there is a less than perfect agreement on the rosters of bodily systems, organs, etc. provided by different sources. Medical textbooks rest on tacit knowledge concerning such highly general concepts. That is, while their authors understand perfectly well how the living human body is organized and what the functions of bodily systems are – they deal with such systems and their workings every day of their lives – they do not formulate this knowledge in an explicit way. We do not wish to impose spurious precision in an area that is marked intrinsically by a certain vagueness and informality. But where for human beings such informality is acceptable, it becomes problematic where the reasoning of human beings must be simulated inside a computer. The analyses presented below are intended as a first step towards making up this gap. *** The following overview of the adult human body’s repertoire of systems has been distilled from the Terminologia anatomica, the National Library of Medicine classification7 and Wolf-Heidegger’s Atlas of human anatomy.8 Supportive Systems: These provide the multi-chambered framework (body, container) within which the other systems are located: The skin system separates and isolates the organism from its surroundings and participates actively in maintaining the organism’s internal environment. Its functions include thermoregulation, tactile sensitivity, participation in the maintenance of water balance, and defence against bacteria and viruses. The musculoskeletal system is an ordered assembly of bones, muscles and ligaments that is responsible for maintaining the body’s shape and for allowing movement in counteraction with external forces such as gravity. It also creates an internal framework of support for the organs of the body. Systems for Substance-Exchange: These support the normal (‘legal’) ways in which the organism exchanges substances both within itself and with the surrounding world: The digestive system includes inter alia the oral cavity, the esophagus, stomach, duodenum, small and large intestines and salivary glands. It ensures that solid and liquid substances are absorbed into the body in such a way that they can serve as energy source and as building blocks for other body systems. The respiratory system includes the nasal cavity, larynx, lungs, trachea and bronchus and serves the body’s gas exchange (absorption of oxygen, excretion of carbon dioxide). The circulatory system includes the heart and blood vessels and microcirculatory vessels, as well as blood itself. It serves as a universal transporter of substances to the cells of the body via two circuits: the pulmonary and the systemic. The former exchanges gases with the external medium in the lungs. The latter supplies all the organs of the body with oxygenated blood and provides for gas exchange between the blood and the cells of other organs. 4. The urogenital system includes the kidneys, the ureters, the urinary bladder, and the urethra. It is responsible for excretion from the body of surplus water and of the waste products that appear in the cells of the body as a result of physiological processes, and for regulating the body’s ion balance. Systems for Regulation: These act as supervisors and coordinators in the work of the other body systems: The immune system includes the thymus, bone marrow, spleen, lymphatic nodules and lymphatic vessels as well as the lymphatic tissue in the pharynx, the intestine, and a population of the immunocompetent cells working through the body. Its first task is to recognize and break down or eliminate substances that are dangerous to the body’s integrity. The nervous system includes the brain and spinal cord (the central nervous system), together with the peripheral nerves, ganglia, plexi and sensory organs. It regulates all the body’s systems and provides the sensitive (sensory) functions of the body. The endocrine system consists of the endocrine glands and of the active endocrine tissue in other glands. Together these serve as a battery of transmitters that broadcast instructions to all the cells of the body. Note that the above is provided not as a definitive partition, but rather merely as a benchmark for the discussions which follow. TOWARDS AN ONTOLOGY The task of ontology is not to replace medical science. Rather, its job is to provide a framework within which medical knowledge can be formalized in a way which supports causally predictive theories and at the same time counteracts the effects of terminological and other inconsistency and imprecision. Such a framework must start out from the ways medical knowledge is formulated in the medical literature, and one criterion of a good definition of ‘system’ is that it yields a roster of systems that is very like the standard rosters. As we have seen, however, it needs to go beyond textbook formulations if it is to achieve the sort of formal clarity we need for the purposes of reference ontology. How, then, are we to define the notion of a bodily system? The discipline of systems theory is of little help to us here, since its definition of a system as a complex of interacting parts9 is far too general for our purposes and is made more specific only by the use of mathematical tools which leave unanswered precisely those questions pertaining to the nature of bodily systems which we are called upon to answer. We can make some progress, on the other hand, if we examine how the word ‘system’ is most commonly used in both technical and non-technical contexts by speakers of English. The Oxford English Dictionary defines ‘system’ under the principal heading of ‘an organized or connected group of objects,’ or more precisely: ‘A set or assemblage of things connected, associated, or interdependent, so as to form a complex unity; a whole composed of parts in orderly arrangement according to some scheme or plan.’ Under the heading ‘Biology’ it gives: A set of organs or parts in an animal body of the same or similar structure, or subserving the same function, as the nervous, muscular, osseous, etc. systems, the digestive, respiratory, reproductive, etc. systems … One might be critical of such definitions on the grounds that a system is not a mere set or aggregate but rather something dynamic (think of the solar system). We can do justice to such criticisms, however, by distinguishing systems themselves from the processes in which they are involved, or in other words from the functioning of systems.10 Systems, on this view, are no more dynamic in nature than organisms. Indeed organisms are systems on the analysis we shall defend. Examining our list of systems above, we see that each of them consists of a certain organized or somehow connected group of objects – including bodily organs and also certain associated tissues and populations of cells – to which some complex function is ascribed. Unfortunately there are very many organized collections of bodily parts, including every single cell of the body, with which functions can be associated. To make an analysis along these lines work, therefore, we need to provide a more precise specification of the specific notion of ‘function’ that is at issue here. THE BODY’S MODULAR HIERARCHY A toolbox is sold in the hardware store as ‘a system for keeping your tools safe.’ Why is the toolbox a system, rather than merely an object – a part of inert reality? Could we designate a rock we find in the forest as ‘a system for cracking open walnuts’? One reason why the toolbox deserves the name system is its complexity: the box is divided into compartments of varying sizes and shapes. Each bodily system, too, enjoys a certain complexity, and its parts are interconnected in certain ways – but the same is true also of the rock, which may manifest an elaborate internal structure of crystal forms and cleavage planes. Every complex organism has parts at many levels of granularity. The brain contains neurons, the neur- ons contain organelles, etc., the organelles contain molecules which are composed of atoms which are composed in turn of subatomic particles. We can, in other words, partition complex organisms into causally relevant portions (organs, cells, macromolecules, and so forth) by employing grids of different sizes and levels of granularity.11 We can partition bodily functions, too, on a number of different levels. Thus the function of the kidney is to excrete urine, but the execution of this function is a composite process that consists of smaller interrelated processes that occur on lower levels of granularity (the excretion of urea and creatinine, absorption of ions and water, and so forth). As the philosopher Roman Ingarden expressed the matter, each multicellular organism is a relatively isolated system of a very high order, and as such contains in itself very numerous, likewise relatively isolated, systems of lower and lower levels, which are hierarchically ordered and variously situated within the organism, and are at the same time both partially interconnected and also partially segregated, as a consequence of which they can exercise the specific functions which are characteristic to them relatively undisturbed.12 Our task here is to provide the beginnings of an account of this modular hierarchy and of the successsive granular layers from out of which it is built, from macromolecules via cells and organs through to the whole organism. To anticipate somewhat we can say that the highest level of this modular organization immediately beneath that of the whole organism is provided precisely by the body’s complement of bodily systems. ELEMENTS AND FUNCTIONS When we make an assay of the parts of the body on any given level of granularity then we can distinguish certain special sorts of parts, which we shall call elements, which are marked out by the fact that they are relatively causally isolated from the surrounding parts (for example as a result of their possession of some membrane or covering which at the same time allows certain kinds of influences and substances to encroach into their interiors). The body as a whole is then organized in modular fashion out of the assemblages of elements arrayed on each distinct level of granularity. We can now define: X is an element of Y if and only if: (i) X is a proper part of Y and Y exists on a higher level of granularity than X; (ii) X is causally relatively isolated from the surrounding parts of Y; (iii) one or more specific functions are ascribed to X; (iv) X is maximal, in the sense that X is not a proper part of any item on the same level of granularity satisfying conditions (i) to (iii). Thus the heart and kidneys are elements, but the upper hemisphere of the heart is not an element, because it is not maximal. In bodily systems we can distinguish many levels of elements. The coarsegrained elements of the digestive system include the esophagus and stomach; finer grained elements are the specific glands in the stomach wall, the serous membrane, the layers of smooth muscular tissue. Assigned functions are: constricting, producing hydrochloric acid and pepsin. One problem with our definition is that the notion of our ‘ascribing’ a function to an element seems to involve an element of subjectivity which conflicts with our goal of contributing to the formulation of causally predictive theories. To solve this problem we need to have some notion of the function which an object, for example a mechanism, realizes when it is doing what it is supposed to do. The toolbox exists only because it has been designed to perform a certain function. Something similar can be said about bodily systems, though we must here speak not of design but rather of the workings of evolutionary processes. Each bodily system has an internal structure which is such that (1) there are various interconnected elements on different levels of granularity within the system as a whole and (2) these interconnected elements perform certain specialized functions which contribute to the functioning of the system as a whole and (3) these elements and the whole which they form exist and have the structure they do in order to allow for this functioning. A DEFINITION OF ‘BODILY SYSTEM’ In order to understand this last phrase we need to exploit the notion of proper function introduced by Ruth Millikan.13 The proper function of the heart is to pump blood. This is so even though, due to some defect, a given heart may fail to perform this function because each heart exists in virtue of the fact that its immediate evolutionary predecessors were successful in carrying out this function. The proper function of a sperm’s tail is to propel the sperm to an egg, and this is so even though only a small fraction of sperm tails realise this function to completion. Technically, we can say that for products of evolution in mature species such as ourselves: An item X has proper function F if and only if: (i) X is a reproduction of some prior item that, because of the possession of certain reproduced properties, actually performed F in the past (ii) X exists because of this performance. What, now, are the proper functions performed by bodily systems? Before we answer this question we must note one apparent difference between bodily systems on the one hand and those elements of the body’s modular hierarchy which we have distinguished at lower levels of granularity. Macromolecules, cells and organs are separated from each other by real physical discontinuities; they are analogous to the body as a whole in manifesting a high degree of (topological) connectedness and selfcontainedness. The body’s systems, in contrast, may be topologically highly complex and they may even, as in the case of the endocrine system, consist of disconnected parts. One crucial difference between the toolbox and our bodily systems is this: the toolbox is a single substance in its own right in relation to which no demarcation problem arises. A toolbox is a connected whole, with its own bona fide boundary. The demarcation lines between bodily systems, in contrast, are to a degree a matter of fiat;14 they are boundaries inserted by human beings – like the boundaries between the midbrain, pons, medulla and spinal cord – for the purposes of constructing predictively powerful causal theories. Why, then, do we partition the body into its maximal elements in just the way that we do? To answer this question we need to introduce a further notion, that of criticality (a term which we use in a somewhat non-standard sense). The human body has a great deal of redundancy; this means that many of its elements can cease to function for longer or shorter periods and yet the human being still survive. Some elements, however, are critical; if they are not present, or if their functions are not executed, then the body dies. We can define this notion more precisely as follows: An item X is a critical element for an organism Y if and only if: (i) X is an element of Y (ii) there is a proper function F of X; (iii) X performs F and no other part of Y performs F; (iv) the continuing to exist of the organism Y is causally dependent on the continued performance by X of F. Of course there are critical functions performed also by single organs of the body (for example the maintenance of acid base by the kidney). Note, however, that each single kidney is not itself in normal circumstances a critical element of the human organism. This is because of the presence of a second kidney. More generally, we can assert that all performance of critical functions by single organs and other subsystem elements are contributions to the performance of critical functions on a higher level of granularity. Eventually we reach some maximal level, where we are dealing with critical functions performed by parts of the organism that are such as to make a contribution to the functioning of no larger part except the organism as a whole. We can then define: X is a bodily system for organism Y if and only if: (i) X is a critical element for Y; (ii) X is not a proper part of any larger critical element for Y. Of course, the body’s systems are, in spite of being relatively causally isolated, still also massively causally interconnected. Thus if one system ceases to function then so also, by virtue of the ensuing death of the whole organism, do all the other systems. Experience shows, however, that there is a sequentiality to this interdependence, so that the pathologist is normally able to establish which system was responsible for causing the organism’s life processes to cease. CONCLUSION The first piece of evidence for the correctness of our account is that it yields a roster of bodily systems which corresponds very well to those given in the standard reference sources. Such sources do not, for example, classify the visual and other perceptual systems as bodily systems alongside those given in our list above, and the majority do not separate out the (male and female) reproductive systems at all. The former are classified as modules of the nervous system; the latter as modules of the urogenital system. This corresponds to the fact that the functioning of the perceptual and reproductive systems are not critical to the existence of the human organism (though reproduction – and indeed perception – are critical to the existence of the species as a whole). Our approach suggests also how we might formulate an explanation of the reason why some textbooks of anatomy include both bones and joints in the skeletal system, while others, including both the Nomina15 and the Terminologia Anatomica4 represent bones and joints as two separate systems – and it may even perhaps give us a means to determine which classification is correct. As we saw, there is a certain sequentiality to the interdependence of bodily systems. If one system ceases to function, then others will follow in its train and in a certain order. If two putatively distinct systems always cease to function simultaneously – as in the case of the pulmonary and the systemic components of the circulatory system, for example – then they are for this reason parts of the same system rather than systems in their own right. As Rosse points out, ‘The practical benefit of explicitly defining a “system” in a knowledge source, which is organized according to systems, is that the definition can provide the logical basis for consistently assigning to the appropriate system those anatomical entities which share a set of inherent properties.’4 We have sought to set out some ontological tools for providing an analysis of the needed sort, in a way that will do justice to the way the term ‘system’ is used in existing standard sources while at the same time providing the necessary degree of formal precision to provide the basis for an anatomical domain ontology of the future. REFERENCES 1. Smith B. Ontology. In: L. Floridi (ed.), Blackwell guide to philosophy, information and computers, Oxford: Blackwell, 2003. 2. Baader F. et al. The description logic handbook. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003. 3. Borgo S, Gangemi A, Guarino N, Masolo C, Oltramari A. Ontology roadMap: Ontology infrastructure for the Semantic Web, http://wonderweb.semanticweb.org/deliverables/documents/D15.pdf. 4. Rosse C. Terminologia anatomica; Considered from the perspective of next-generation knowledge sources, Structural Informatics Group, http://sig.biostr.washington.edu/publications/online/CRTAnat.pdf. 5. Terminologia anatomica: International Anatomical Terminology, Federative Committee on Anatomical Terminology (FCAT), Stuttgart: Thieme, 1998. 6. DAUW definitions, http://sig.biostr.washington.edu/research/ai/definitions.html. 7. World Health Organization training course on National Library of Medicine classification, http://www.emro.who.int/HIS/VHSL/Doc/NLM.pdf. 8. Köpf-Maier P, ed., Wolf-Heidegger’s Atlas of human anatomy, Vol. 1, 5th edition, Berlin, 2000. 9. Bertallanfy L. General system theory, New York: George Braziller, 1968. p. 17. 10. Smith B. Basic formal ontology, http://ontology.buffalo.edu/bfo, 2003. 11. Bittner T, Smith B. A theory of granular partitions. In: Foundations of geographic information science, London: Taylor & Francis, 2003. 12. Ingarden R. Man and value, Munich: Philosophia, 1983, p. 87. 13. Millikan RG. Language, thought, and other biological categories. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1984. 14. Smith B. Fiat objects, Topoi, 20, 2001, 131–148. 15. Nomina anatomica, 4th ed., Amsterdam: 1977. Acknowledgements: This work was supported by the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation under the auspices of its Wolfgang Paul Program. Our thanks go also to David Hershenov, Anand Kumar, Ingvar Johansson and Rainer Schubert.