Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 1 Chapter 2: Ideas, Principles, and Terminology about God as One, Creator, and Trinity in the Fourth Century before Augustine Introduction It would not be possible to do a comprehensive survey of fourth century writings relevant to the influence of ideas about creation on the development of trinitarian doctrine, or on belief in one God, understood as Creator and Trinity.1 In this chapter, the writings examined are on creation, such as hexaemeral sermons, or related to ideas about whether or how the ‘Persons’ of the Trinity came into being, such as writings ‘against’ Eunomius of Cyzicus, who thought God was Unbegotten (agennétos), and the Son, who was begotten (gennéthenta) and monogenés, was different in substance (heteroousios) from God.2 The writings examined are primarily from the 350s to 380s, the period in which trinitarian doctrine and theologies considered compatible with Nicene principles, including those 1 Sources consulted for background on fourth century trinitarian doctrine, with abbreviations, include Lewis Ayres, Nicaea and its Legacy: An Approach to Fourth-Century Trinitarian Theology (New York: OUP, 2006); Morwenna Ludlow, The Early Church, I. B. Tauris History of the Christian Church, ed. by G. R. Evans (London: I. B. Tauris, 2009); Khaled Anatolios, Retrieving Nicaea: The Development and Meaning of Trinitarian Doctrine, with a foreword by Brian E. Daley (Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Academic, 2011); Jaroslav Pelikan, The Christian Tradition: A History of the Development of Doctrine, 5 vols (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1971-1989; paperback edn, 1975-1991), I; J. N. D. Kelly, Early Christian Creeds, 3rd edn (London: Continuum, 2006); R. P. C. Hanson, The Search for the Christian Doctrine of God: The Arian Controversy, 318-381 (London: T&T Clark, 1988; first paperback edn, Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Academic, 2005); Tarmo Toom, Classical Trinitarian Theology: A Textbook (New York: T&T Clark, 2007); Frances Young, Lewis Ayres, and Andrew Louth, eds., The Cambridge History of Early Christian Literature (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004; first paperback edn, 2007) (abbreviated CHECL here); Frances Young with Andrew Teal, From Nicaea to Chalcedon: A Guide to Its Literature and Its Background, 2nd edn (Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Academic, 2010); Lloyd P. Gerson, ed., The Cambridge History of Philosophy in Late Antiquity, 2 vols (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), I (abbreviated CHPLA here). 2 As note earlier, ‘Persons’ is used for convenience. Hexaemeral writings are on the six days of creation according to Gen. 1. The word agennétos means unbegotten, ingenerate, or ungenerated; gennéthenta (begotten, from gennaō) and monogené (only-begotten or meanings discussed below) are in the creeds of the 325 Council of Nicaea and 381 Council of Constantinople. G. W. H. Lampe, ed., A Patristic Greek Lexicon (New York: Oxford University Press, 1961; 18th impression, 2004), pp. 15-16, 148, 311, 553; Ludlow, The Early Church, pp. 128-130; J. N. D. Kelly, Early Christian Creeds, pp. 215-216, 297-298; John Anthony McGuckin, The Westminster Handbook to Patristic Theology, Westminster Handbooks to Christian Theology (Louisville, KY: Westminster John Knox Press, 2004), pp. 127-128; Ayres, Nicaea and its Legacy, pp. 144-149; Anatolios, Retrieving Nicaea, p. 21; Christopher A. Beeley, Gregory of Nazianzus on the Trinity and the Knowledge of God: In Your Light We Shall See Light, Oxford Studies in Historical Theology, ed. by David C. Steinmetz (New York: Oxford University Press, 2008), pp. 21-23. Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 2 represented in the creeds of the 325 Council of Nicaea and 381 Council of Constantinople, came into fuller development.3 The fourth century Christians whose writings will be examined here were bishops and supporters of Nicene theologies at times in their careers. The primary focus is on Greek and Alexandrian ideas, principles, and terminology, which will be represented by writings, sermons, or orations of Athanasius of Alexandria and two of the Cappadocian ‘Fathers’, Basil of Caesarea and Gregory of Nazianzus. However, some attention will be given to the other Cappadocian ‘Father’, Gregory of Nyssa, and to Ambrose of Milan, who wrote in Latin, as well as to the creeds from the 325 and 381 councils. This chapter addresses three primary questions, in three major sections, with a few special questions integrated into the discussions in ‘case studies’. The first question, dealt with in major section 2.1, is what the known and likely sources are which orthodox / catholic thinkers drew upon as they formulated trinitarian positions, including works and ideas of their opponents. The second question, addressed in section 2.2, is ‘how did ideas, principles, and terminology related to creation influence trinitarian ideas about the consubstantiality, relations of origin, and unity and distinctions of the Persons within the Godhead?’. Most of the topics addressed are related to the ‘immanent Trinity’, but included is a discussion of trinitarian principles of unity and distinction that apply to the immanent and ‘economic Trinity’.4 These terms are anachronistic for this period, but are used as aids for being able 3 This period allows for examining writings in the 350s that illustrate how ideas about principles about creation may have influenced trinitarian principles. Ayres, in Nicaea and its Legacy, establishes the 360s to 380s as the period of what he calls ‘pro-Nicene’ theologies (which are defined below). In Augustine and the Trinity, Ayres views the Latin pro-Nicene period as 360 to 390. Barnes, in ‘The Fourth Century’, dates the start of the Western ‘reinterpretation’ of Nicaea to the early 360s (he includes Hilary’s writings from the late 350s), and the Eastern ‘reinterpretation’ to the early 370s, with the works of the Cappadocians. Ayres, Nicaea and its Legacy, pp. 6, 239240; Lewis Ayres, Augustine and the Trinity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), pp. 42-71; Michel René Barnes, ‘The Fourth Century as Trinitarian Canon’, in Christian Origins: Theology, Rhetoric and Community, ed. by Lewis Ayres and Gareth Jones (Abingdon, UK: Routledge, 1998; transferred to digital printing, New York: Routledge, 2005), pp. 47-67 (pp. 61-62, 66-67); see also Michel René Barnes, ‘De Trinitate VI and VII: Augustine and the Limits of Nicene Orthodoxy’, Augustinian Studies, 38, no. 1 (2007), 189-202 (p. 196 FN 19). 4 This is not to be confused with ideas about the economic Trinity up through the early fourth century. McGuckin says these early ideas were ‘based within the standpoint of pre-Nicene’ Monarchianism, and it was held that ‘God is ultimately one, and only became “threefold” for the purposes of creation and redemption’. McGuckin, The Westminster Handbook, pp. 111-112. Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 3 to respond in later chapters to debates over how the immanent Trinity and the principle of consubstantiality were understood by the Cappadocians and Augustine.5 The third question, responded to with examples offered in section 2.3, is ‘how are the Persons said to be involved in acts of creation in writings about creation, and what is said about relations within the Godhead and between God and creation?’. Basil’s hexaemeral homilies will be used in a case study to see how he responds to these questions, and again the topics will be related to both the immanent Trinity and economic Trinity. A few special ‘what if?’ questions will be posed in the discussions of the primary questions, including questions about Philo’s influence, alternative interpretations of Prov. 8. 22, and whether the word monogenés meant, or only meant, only-begotten in the fourth century. These questions and discussions, which are set apart in case studies, are offered to illustrate connections between ideas about creation and the Trinity, and to suggest possibilities for alternative translations and further research. Some ideas, principles, terminology, and writings to be discussed were known to Augustine when he began writing on creation in the 380s,6 and Augustine could have heard Ambrose’s hexaemeral sermons during Holy Week, either in the year of Augustine’s conversion (386) or his baptism by Ambrose (387).7 Therefore, the period covered here, which ends with the middle 380s, overlaps with the period covered in the next chapter. 5 See Ayres, Augustine and the Trinity, pp. 1-3; Colin E. Gunton, The Promise of Trinitarian Theology, 2nd edn (London: T&T Clark, 1997, 2003; repr. 2006), pp. xvii-xix, 3-4; 9-11, 38-42. 6 Michael Fiedrowicz, ‘General Introduction’, trans. by Matthew O’Connell, in Saint Augustine: On Genesis: A Refutation of the Manichees, Unfinished Literal Commentary on Genesis, The Literal Meaning of Genesis, trans. and notes by Edmund Hill and ed. by John E. Rotelle, Augustinian Heritage Institute, WSA, Part I – Books, vol 13 (Hyde Park, NY: New City Press, 2002), pp. 13-22 (pp. 13, 18-19); Carol Harrison, Rethinking Augustine’s Early Theology: An Argument for Continuity (New York: Oxford University Press, 2008), pp. 79-80. 7 Fiedrowicz, Hunter, Teske, and Harrison say Augustine may have heard them; Savage implies it. However, in his Confessions, Augustine mentions Ambrose’s Sunday, not Holy Week, sermons. Fiedrowicz, Saint Augustine: On Genesis, p. 26; David G. Hunter, ‘Fourth-Century Latin Writers: Hilary, Victorinus, Ambrosiaster, Ambrose’, in CHECL, pp. 302-317 (pp. 310, 316 FN 59); Roland J. Teske, ‘Genesis Accounts of Creation’, in ATTA, ed. by Allan D. Fitzgerald (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1999; paperback edn, 2009), pp. 379-381 (p. 379); C. Harrison, pp. 79-80; John J. Savage, translation and introduction, Saint Ambrose: Hexameron, Paradise, and Cain and Abel, by Ambrose, FOTC, 42 (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1961), pp. v-vi; Roy J. Deferrari, translation and introduction, Saint Ambrose: Theological and Dogmatic Works, by Ambrose, FOTC, 44 (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1963; first paperback repr. 2002), p. xix; Augustine, Confessions, trans. with an introduction and notes by Maria Boulding and ed. by John E. Rotelle, Augustinian Heritage Institute, WSA, Part I – Books, vol 1 (Hyde Park, NY: New City Press, 1997), Book VI, 4, pp. 138-139. Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 4 2.1 Survey of sources of ideas about creation and the Trinity in the fourth century This major section provides a survey of known and potential sources drawn upon by the authors whose works will be examined below. Also included here is a case study that raises questions about the availability, and perhaps choices, of translations of Prov. 8. 22, and which calls for further research into Philo’s potential influences. The orthodox / catholic authors to be discussed were involved in church life, as bishops, through preaching and pastoral activities, and through participation in councils or synods. They argued against Christian opponents, as did Christians in earlier centuries, and Athanasius was sent into exile himself, as will be commented on below.8 Some also engaged in forms of Christian living outside the church structure. Basil and Gregory of Nazianzus, for example, tried to live an ascetic or ‘philosophic’ life for a while, Basil for much longer than Gregory, before they were ordained as priests in the early 360s.9 Basil’s ongoing ascetic ideals can be viewed as a source of ideas in his hexaemeral sermons, as he is known to have used his homilies to encourage his listeners to behave in ways that fit with his moral ideas.10 In light of these roles and experiences, Christian sources for these authors include creeds; liturgical formulae;11 scripture; doctrines, such as of creatio ex nihilo; writings and ideas of opponents and orthodox / catholic Christians; and influences that stem from their lifestyles or places of exile. Writers of this period often did not identify their sources, and it is not always known whether they had direct or mediated access to works. Basil, for a typical example, was On Athanasius’s many exiles, see Khaled Anatolios, Athanasius, ECF, ed. by Carol Harrison (London and New York: Routledge, 2004; transferred to digital printing, 2010), pp. 12-13. 9 Gregory, according to Rousseau and McGuckin, is the source of much of our information on Basil’s ascetic or monastic experiences, and of the phrase ‘philosophical life’, the heading of one of Rousseau’s chapters. Both Rousseau and McGuckin write of both Basil and Gregory. Philip Rousseau, Basil of Caesarea (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1994; first paper edn, 1998), pp. 61-92; John Anthony McGuckin, St Gregory of Nazianzus: An Intellectual Biography (Crestwood, NY: St Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 2001), pp. 56, 76-81, 87-107. 10 Rousseau, Basil of Caesarea, pp. 46-47, 80-81, 84, 324, 327; Agnes Clare Way, translation and introduction, Saint Basil: Exegetic Homilies, by Basil of Caesarea, FOTC, 46 (Washington DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1963), pp. x-xi; Morwenna Ludlow, ‘Power and Dominion: Patristic Interpretations of Genesis I’, in Ecological Hermeneutics: Biblical, Historical, and Theological Perspectives, ed. by David G. Horrell, Cherryl Hunt, Christopher Southgate, and Francesca Stavrakopoulou (London: T&T Clark, 2010), pp. 140-153 (p. 141). 11 Basil argues about the Spirit based on the use of the preposition ‘with’ in doxologies. St Basil the Great, On the Holy Spirit, trans. and introduction by Stephen Hildebrand, Popular Patristics Series, 42 (Yonkers, NY: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 2011), ch. 25, 58-60, pp. 96-99. 8 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 5 influenced by Origen, although he rejected Origen’s allegorical methods of interpreting Genesis, but he rarely cites Origen by name.12 Ambrose, for an egregious example, was criticised even in his day, by Jerome, for what we would call plagiarism, including for borrowing, in his The Holy Spirit, from Basil of Caesarea and Didymus the Blind.13 One also cannot assume that authors discussed here, whose lives were contemporaneous to some extent, influenced each other. Differing opinions exist, for example, on whether the Cappadocians were influenced by Athanasius, although they probably knew of some of his ideas through the Homoiousian Basil of Ancyra, another contemporary.14 There were, on the other hand, ideas or sources shared between authors. Origen was known to the authors who wrote in Greek,15 and to Ambrose, who drew on Origen in his Ayres and Radde-Gallwitz say Basil rarely names sources, and that he rejected ‘Origen’s more speculative readings of Genesis’. Ludlow writes of Basil’s disinterest in Origen’s allegorical methods of interpreting Gen., and Louth says Basil, in his hexaemeral homilies, rejects some of Origen’s interpretations, although Basil does not mention him by name. DelCogliano and RaddeGallwitz say Basil does not name Origen and other sources in Against Eunomius. Lewis Ayres and Andrew Radde-Gallwitz, ‘Basil of Caesarea’, in CHPLA, I, pp. 459-470 (pp. 459-461); Morwenna Ludlow, ‘Power and Dominion’, pp. 141-142, 144-145; Andrew Louth, ‘The Cappadocians’, in CHECL, pp. 289-301 (p. 294); Mark DelCogliano and Andrew Radde-Gallwitz, translation and introduction, Against Eunomius, by Basil of Caesarea, FOTC, 122 (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2011), pp. 60-62; Way, pp. ix-x; Frank Egleston Robbins, The Hexaemeral Literature: A Study of the Greek and Latin Commentaries on Genesis (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1912), 44. 13 Jerome, ‘Jerome’s Prologue to the Book of Didymus on the Holy Spirit’, in Works on the Spirit: Athanasius and Didymus, trans. and with an introduction and annotations by Mark DelCogliano, Andrew Radde-Gallwitz, and Lewis Ayres, Popular Patristics, 43 (Yonkers, NY: St Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 2011), pp. 139-141; Ayres, Nicaea and its Legacy, p. 264; Deferrari, p. 32. 14 M. Barnes says it is not known if the Cappadocians had read anything of Athanasius’s. Hanson and DelCogliano and Radde-Gallwitz think the Cappadocians knew Athanasius’s ideas through Basil of Ancyra. Beeley suggests Gregory of Nazianzus shared aspects of an ‘agenda’ with Athanasius, although Beeley says Gregory had never met him, and does not seem to have known his work ‘firsthand’. On the other hand, Lienhard says Basil wrote letters to Athanasius asking, unsuccessfully, for his help in persuading ‘Westerners’ to adopt Basil’s position on matters related to Marcellus of Ancyra. M. Barnes, ‘The Fourth Century’, pp. 53-54; Ayres, Nicaea and its Legacy, pp. 143, 236-240; Richard Hanson, ‘The Achievement of Orthodoxy in the Fourth Century AD’, in The Making of Orthodoxy: Essays in Honour of Henry Chadwick, ed. by Rowan Williams (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989; first paperback edn, 2002), pp. 142-156; DelCogliano and Radde-Gallwitz, pp. 63-64; Beeley, Gregory of Nazianzus, pp. 27, 277, also pp. 8, 24-25, 278-284; Joseph T. Lienhard, ‘Basil of Caesarea, Marcellus of Ancyra, and “Sabellius” ’, Church History, 58, no. 2 (1989), 157-167 (pp. 161-162). 15 See, e.g., Khaled Anatolios, Athanasius: The Coherence of His Thought, Routledge Early Christian Monographs (London and New York: Routledge, 1998; first paperback edn, 2005), pp. 24-25; Meredith, ‘Gregory of Nyssa’, in CHPLA, I, pp. 471-481; John A. McGuckin, ‘Gregory of Nazianzus’, in CHPLA, I, pp. 482-497 (p. 485); McGuckin, St Gregory of Nazianzus, pp. 57-58; Beeley, Gregory of Nazianzus, p. 7. 12 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 6 hexaemeral sermons.16 Didymus the Blind, of Alexandria, may have influenced Basil of Caesarea and Ambrose through Didymus’s On the Holy Spirit.17 Moreover, Didymus18 and Athanasius19 are each credited with being the first to offer full treatments of the Spirit, while Ambrose is said to be the first do so in Latin.20 The Western Jerome contributed to exchanges of ideas by translating texts into Latin and through his ‘exegetical’ work, and his translations of and comments on Genesis and the Gospel of John are significant here.21 Jerome also heard Gregory of Nyssa read from Against Eunomius at the 381 Council of Constantinople,22 and had contact with Gregory of Nazianzus.23 Exchanges of ideas also could take place during exiles, and Alexandria and Rome are thought to share some trinitarian traditions, because of Athanasius’s time spent in exile in Rome.24 Other common sources for authors were the ideas and writings of their opponents. Eunomius, who was a Cappadocian, and his followers, called Heterousians because they believed the Son was heteroousios (different in substance) from the Father,25 are addressed by Basil and Gregory of Nyssa in their treatises Against Eunomius,26 and Gregory of 16 See Hunter, pp. 309-310; McGuckin, The Westminster Handbook, p. 9. Mark DelCogliano, Andrew Radde-Gallwitz, and Lewis Ayres, translation, introduction, and annotations, Works on the Spirit: Athanasius and Didymus, Popular Patristics, 43 (Yonkers, NY: St Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 2011), pp. 37-42; Mark DelCogliano, ‘Basil of Caesarea, Didymus the Blind, and the Anti-Pneumatomachian Exegesis of Amos 4:13 and John 1:3’, Journal of Theological Studies, NS, 61, no. 2 (2010), pp. 644-658. 18 DelCogliano, Radde-Gallwitz, and Ayres, p. 42; DelCogliano, ‘Basil of Caesarea, Didymus the Blind…’, pp. 657-658. 19 R. P. C. Hanson, The Search, p. 748; Anatolios, Athanasius, ECF, p. 82. 20 Michel René Barnes, ‘Latin trinitarian theology’, in The Cambridge Companion to the Trinity, ed. by Peter C. Phan (New York: CUP, 2011), pp. 70-84 (p. 77). 21 See Vesey on Jerome’s translations, exegetical work, and commentaries. Mark Vessey, ‘Jerome and Rufinus’, in CHECL, pp. 318-327 (p. 319). 22 Anthony Meredith, ‘Gregory of Nyssa’, in CHPLA, I, pp. 471-481 (p. 472); see also McGuckin, St Gregory of Nazianzus, pp. 349-350. 23 Beeley, Gregory of Nazianzus, p. 321. 24 M. Barnes, ‘The Fourth Century’, pp. 56, 61; see also Young and Teal, pp. 40, 51. 25 Beeley refers to Eunomius and his followers as ‘Heterousians’ and says they did not ‘claim that the Son is unlike the Father in all respects’. McGuckin says Heterousians was their preferred title, and it was their opponents who called them Anhomoians, an accusation that Eunomius and others thought that the Son was ‘completely unlike’ the Father. Beeley, Gregory of Nazianzus, p. 21, including FN 58; McGuckin, ‘Gregory of Nazianzus’, in CHPLA, I, p. 489; Richard Paul Vaggione, Eunomius: The Extant Works, Oxford Early Christian Texts, ed. by Henry Chadwick (New York: Oxford University Press, 1987), pp. xiii-xvii. 26 Basil of Caesarea, Against Eunomius, trans. and with an introduction by Mark DelCogliano and Andrew Radde-Gallwitz, FOTC, 122 (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2011); Gregory of Nyssa, Against Eunomius, trans. by William Moore and Henry Austin Wilson, 17 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 7 Nazianzus in his ‘theological orations’, although he often does not name them.27 There also were groups who believed the Spirit was created and not divine, including the ‘Tropikoi’ or ‘Tropici’, whom Athanasius writes against in Letters to Serapion,28 and the slightly later Pneumatomachians or Macedonians, whom Basil and Ambrose address in their respective works On the Holy Spirit, and Gregory of Nazianzus in some orations.29 Orthodox / catholic authors can be the main extant witnesses to the ideas or texts of their opponents or creeds. For example, Athanasius’s ‘On the Council of Nicaea’,30 where he writes about the 325 creed, is, as David Gwynn says, one of the few extant writings about the council.31 In the case of Eunomius, whose works were condemned at the end of the fourth century, only two works are extant, according to Richard Vaggione, because they were ‘bound up with’ copies of Basil’s and Gregory’s treatises: Liber Apologeticus (The Apology of Eunomius or his first apology), to which Basil responds in his Against Eunomius, and Expositio Fidei (The Confession of Faith), to which Gregory of Nyssa responds in his own Against Eunomius.32 Eunomius’s Apologia Apologiae (An Apology for the Apology or his second apology), is not extant, with Vaggione saying it is ‘preserved in Gregory of Nyssa: Dogmatic Treatises, Etc., NPNF, 2nd series, 5, ed. by P. Schaff and H. Wace (1893; Oak Harbor: Logos Research Systems, 1997 [on CD-ROM]). 27 On Gregory not naming his opponents in his ‘theological orations’, see Wickham, who calls them ‘Anomeans’ or ‘Eunomians’. Lionel Wickham, translation (with Frederick Williams), introduction, and notes, On God and Christ: The Five Theological Orations and Two Letters to Cledonius, by Gregory of Nazianzus, Popular Patristics Series, 23, ed. by John Behr (Crestwood, NY: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 2002), pp. 14-15; Beeley, Gregory of Nazianzus, p. 91; Christopher A. Beeley, ‘Divine Causality and the Monarchy of God the Father in Gregory of Nazianzus’, in Harvard Theological Review, 100, no. 2 (2007), 199-214 (p. 204). 28 Athanasius, ‘Letters to Serapion on the Holy Spirit’, in Works on the Spirit: Athanasius the Great and Didymus the Blind, trans. and with an introduction and annotations by Mark DelCogliano, Andrew Radde-Gallwitz, and Lewis Ayres, Popular Patristics Series, 43, ed. by John Behr and Augustine Casiday (Yonkers, NY: St Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 2011), pp. 51-137 (1.10.4, p. 69; 1.1.2, p. 53); DelCogliano, Radde-Gallwitz, and Ayres, pp. 21-22; Ayres, Nicaea and its Legacy, pp. 211-214, 217-218; R. P. C. Hanson, The Search, pp. 748-752, 762-763. 29 Basil speaks of ‘Spirit-fighters’. St Basil the Great, On the Holy Spirit, chs. 10-11, pp. 55-58; Hildebrand, On the Holy Spirit, p. 58 FN 49; Ayres, Nicaea and its Legacy, pp. 214-218; R. P. C. Hanson, The Search, pp. 760-763; Toom, Classical Trinitarian Theology, pp. 127-128; Pelikan, The Christian Tradition, I, p. 212; Deferrari, pp. 31-32; Beeley, ‘Divine Causality’, p. 204. 30 Athanasius, ‘On the Council of Nicaea (De Decretis)’, trans. and ed. by Khaled Anatolios, in Athanasius, by Khaled Anatolios, ECF, pp. 176-211. 31 David M. Gwynn, The Eusebians: The Polemic of Athanasius of Alexandria and the Construction of the ‘Arian Controversy’, Oxford Theological Monographs (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007), pp. 4-5, 8-9, 241; see also J. N. D. Kelly, Early Christian Creeds, p. 212. 32 Vaggione, pp. xv-xvii, 79-81, 89-94. Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 8 only in the quotations’ of it in Gregory of Nyssa’s Against Eunomius.33 Vaggione does not mention Gregory of Nazianzus, but his orations are a source of references to Eunomian ideas, if not to his works.34 One has to consider, as will be done, whether the accounts of these authors are likely to not be faithful representations of other writings, ideas, or events, and, even if so, whether the accounts have theological value and value for tracing the history of theological ideas. A few comments can be made about philosophical backgrounds and potential sources. Athanasius, who may have had little formal education, was familiar with Platonist and Stoic ideas.35 Basil, who studied in Athens, knew of Plato, Plotinus, Porphyry, Aristotle, and Stoicism.36 Gregory of Nyssa, who studied under Basil, drew on Platonist and Stoic ideas, but is said rarely to refer directly to philosophical sources.37 Gregory of Nazianzus, who also studied at Athens, knew Greek classics, philosophy, and rhetoric, and refers to Plato and Aristotle in his works.38 Gregory seems to have known Plotinian ideas, which he draws on in discussing differences between philosophical ideas about ‘emanation’ and Christian ideas about begetting and procession within the ‘Godhead’.39 On the Latin side, Ambrose was well educated and read Greek and may have had philosophical training.40 All could have taken in philosophical ideas through Origen’s writings. Philo’s ideas were probably more influential in the fourth century than is currently 33 Vaggione, pp. xvii, also 79-81, 89-94. Beeley, ‘Divine Causality’, p. 204. 35 Anatolios, Athanasius, ECF, p. 4; Andrew Louth, ‘The Fourth-Century Alexandrians: Athanasius and Didymus’, in CHECL, pp. 275-282 (p. 275); R. P. C. Hanson, The Search, p. 422. 36 Ayres and Radde-Gallwitz, pp. 459, 461, 463; Way, pp. x-xi; Rousseau, Basil of Caesarea, p. 28; Robbins, pp. 42-43. 37 Meredith, ‘Gregory of Nyssa’, in CHPLA, I, pp. 471-473; Anthony Meredith, Gregory of Nyssa, ECF, ed. by Carol Harrison (London: Routledge, 1999; transferred to digital printing, 2005), p. 3. 38 McGuckin, ‘Gregory of Nazianzus’, in CHPLA, I, pp. 484-485; see also McGuckin, St Gregory of Nazianzus, pp. 56-60; Beeley, Gregory of Nazianzus, pp. 8-9. 39 Gregory’s references to the ideas about emanation of the ‘non-Christian philosopher’ are similar to those expressed by Plotinus in his Enneads V.2. Gregory of Nazianzus, ‘The Third Theological Oration: Oration 29’, in On God and Christ: The Five Theological Orations and Two Letters to Cledonius, trans. by Lionel Wickham, with introduction and notes by Lionel Wickham, Popular Patristics Series, 23, ed. by John Behr (Crestwood, NY: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 2002), pp. 69-92 (2, p. 70); Plotinus, Enneads, trans. by A. H. Armstrong, Loeb Classical Library, ed. by Jeffrey Henderson, 7 vols (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1969-1988), V (1984), V. 2, pp. 58-61; see also Wickham, pp. 70 and 89 FN 3; McGuckin, St Gregory of Nazianzus, pp. 57-58. 40 McGuckin, The Westminster Handbook, p. 9; Boniface Ramsey, Ambrose, The Early Church Fathers, ed. by Carol Harrison (London: Routledge, 1997), p. 18. 34 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 9 known, and can be sources of theological and philosophical ideas.41 Based on similarities to be presented here and below, more research is warranted on how some Christians in the fourth century may have been influenced by his ideas. Philo’s ‘On the Creation of the Cosmos according to Moses’ (Opif.), discussed in the first chapter, may have been one of Basil’s sources for his hexaemeral homilies, but this has not been proven.42 Gregory of Nyssa knew Philo’s works well enough to claim, in his Against Eunomius, that Eunomius borrowed Philo’s words,43 and there are potential borrowings from Philo in Gregory’s hexaemeral writings, De virginitate, and De vita Moysis, enough for David Runia to conclude that he had works of Philo in his library.44 Ambrose, in keeping with his style of not citing sources, is said by Runia to draw on Philo about 600 times, mentioning his name once.45 However, Ambrose was dependent on Basil in his hexaemeral sermons, so any influences of Philo on these works could have come through Basil.46 It also is possible that Basil, Athanasius, Gregory of Nazianzus, and others who seldom, if ever, mention Philo, were influenced by his ideas through Origen’s commentary on Genesis.47 Philo also is important as a potential source of ideas, because he is a predecessor to the Christian tradition of offering interpretations of the Genesis creation accounts.48 This tradition was participated in by Origen in the third century, and Basil, Gregory of Nyssa, Ambrose, Augustine, and others in the fourth and fifth.49 Basil, in one of his hexaemeral 41 See David T. Runia, Philo in Early Christian Literature: A Survey, Compendia Rerum Iudaicarum ad Novum Testamentum, Section 3, Jewish Traditions in Early Christian Literature (Minneapolis, MN: Fortress Press, 1993), pp. 194-196, 241, and other pages cited in this discussion. (This work is abbreviated PECL.) 42 Philo’s account of the six days of creation starts with Opif., 13. Runia says the possibility that Philo’s Opif. was one of four sources for Basil for his hexaemeral homilies was put forth by Armand de Mendieta, who died before he was able to publish the work to support his assertions. Runia, PECL, pp. 236-237, also 251-252; Philo, ‘On the Creation’, trans. by Runia, p. 49. 43 Gregory of Nyssa, Against Eunomius, Book VII, 1; Runia, PECL, pp. 261, 244-249. 44 Runia, PECL, pp. 261, 249-261. 45 Runia, PECL, p. 295. 46 See Runia, PECL, pp. 294-295, 309-310; Robbins, pp. 42, 57-58; Savage, pp. vi-vii; Way, p. viii; Ayres, Nicaea and its Legacy, p. 317. 47 See Runia, PECL, pp. 236-238, 194-196, 241-243. 48 Robbins, pp. 1, 24-35. 49 Robbins, pp. 36-42, 53-72; Fiedrowicz, Saint Augustine: On Genesis, p. 17; Isabella Sandwell, ‘How to Teach Genesis 1.1-19: John Chrysostom and Basil of Caesarea on the Creation of the World’, Journal of Early Christian Studies, 19, no. 4 (2011), pp. 539-564; Paul M. Blowers, Drama of the Divine Economy: Creator and Creation in Early Christian Theology and Piety, Oxford Early Christian Studies, ed. by Gillian Clark and Andrew Louth (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012), pp. 109-110. Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 10 homilies, offers an interpretation of Gen. 1. 2 that also comes from other Greek or Syrian thinking on Genesis, and was known in Latin writings, as will discussed below.50 Basil’s homilies, which he may have preached in 377 or 378, not long before his death,51 influenced his Cappadocian associates52 and Ambrose, and possibly Jerome53 and Augustine.54 Given the variety of sources upon which Basil drew, and that these homilies were sources for others, and are explicitly about creation, they are used in the final major section here, to illustrate connections between thinking on creation and the Trinity. 2.1.1 Case study: interpretations of Prov. 8. 22 and the potential influences of Philo A case study will be offered here to suggest that further research be undertaken on a line of transmission of Philo’s terminology, and its possible influence on interpretations of Prov. 8. 22. While the arguments presented here are original, they build on work done by Mark DelCogliano, and Runia’s survey of Philo’s influences on early Christians. Philo, in the first century, and Basil and Gregory of Nyssa in the fourth, were aware of the same alternative to the key phrase ‘ektisen me’ (created me) from an LXX translation of Prov. 8. 22. Philo uses ‘ektésato me’ (‘obtained me’) in one instance,55 and this possible wording was mentioned by Basil in his Against Eunomius (without reference to Philo).56 50 Basil of Caesarea, On the Hexaemeron, in Saint Basil: Exegetic Homilies, trans. and with an introduction by Agnes Clare Way, FOTC, 46 (Washington DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1963), 3-150 (Homily 2, 6, pp. 30-31). 51 Ayres suggests the homilies were ‘probably’ delivered in 378. Hildebrand suggests 377 or 378. Rousseau says they may be dated to 377 or 378, but the dating depends on the date of Basil’s death, which had been assumed to be 1 January 379, but may have been slightly earlier. Other scholars, according to Way, give earlier dates, but she says the dating is uncertain. Ayres, Nicaea and its Legacy, p. 314; Stephen Hildebrand, translation and introduction, On the Holy Spirit, by St Basil the Great, Popular Patristics Series, 42 (Yonkers, NY: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 2011), p. 21; Rousseau, Basil of Caesarea, pp. 318-319, 360-363; Way, p. ix. 52 Gregory of Nyssa’s hexaemeral treatise of 379 or 380 defended criticisms of Basil’s homilies. Gregory of Nyssa, Traité sur les six jours, trans. by Timothée Lecaudey and Jean Rousselet, October 1999 [accessed 20 August 2012 from <http://www.gregoiredenysse.com/?page_id=66>]; Meredith, ‘Gregory of Nyssa’, in CHPLA, I, pp. 471-472; Way, pp. vii-viii. 53 Potential connections between Jerome and Basil are discussed in the case study below. 54 See Way, pp. vii-viii; Fiedrowicz, Saint Augustine: On Genesis, pp. 18-19; Teske, ‘Genesis Accounts of Creation’, p. 379; Ayres, Nicaea and its Legacy, pp. 317-318. 55 Runia mentions Philo’s use of this phrase, but does not make the connections discussed here. Runia, PECL, p. 193 FN 51; Philo, ‘On Drunkenness’, in Philo: Volume III, trans. by F. H. Colson and G. H. Whitaker, Loeb Classical Library, ed. by Jeffrey Henderson (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1930; repr. 2001), pp. 307-435 (pp. 334-335) (this treatise is referred to as Ebr.). 56 Basil of Caesarea, Against Eunomius, 2.20, pp. 160-161; Mark DelCogliano, ‘Basil of Caesarea Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 11 Philo may have known a Greek translation of Prov. 8. 22 that used ‘ektésato me’, given that he was known to not always use the same LXX texts.57 Basil, as DelCogliano says, attributes his own knowledge of ‘obtained me’ to ‘other translators, who have hit upon the meaning of the Hebrew words in a more appropriate way’.58 Gregory of Nyssa knew that the Hebrew word translated as ‘created’ also could mean ‘obtained’, ‘possessed’, and ‘constituted’, so ‘created’ is not necessarily a wrong translation, just not the only one. 59 The Hebrew word is said to be ‘ambiguous’ by Jennifer Dines, and she includes the meaning ‘begot’ along with ‘created’ and ‘acquired’, meanings she says overlap with LXX translations that use the ‘creation verb, ktizō’.60 The idea that Prov. 8. 22 might be saying something about the Word or Son being begotten is a meaning that Basil infers from ‘acquired’ as it is used in Gen. 4. 1, an interpretation which DelCogliano argues Basil adapts from Eusebius of Caesarea’s understanding of ‘acquiring’.61 DelCogliano, in his arguments about Basil being dependent on Eusebius for other translations of Prov. 8. 22, says that Eusebius was the first to use the translation ‘ektésato me’ in debates about this verse, which DelCogliano attributes to Eusebius’s use of the Greek translations of the scriptures by Aquila, Symmachus, and Theodotion.62 However, an intriguing possibility, which DelCogliano does not mention and can only on Proverbs 8:22 and the Sources of Pro-Nicene Theology’, Journal of Theological Studies, 59, no. 1 (2008), pp. 183-190 (pp. 187-188). 57 As discussed in the first chapter, Dines says Philo’s ‘LXX sources were not homogenous, as the nature of his citations makes clear’. That he used an alternative to typical LXX translations when he used ‘ektisen me’ can be inferred from Colson and Whitaker. Jennifer M. Dines, The Septuagint, Understanding the Bible and Its World series (London: T&T Clark, 2004; repr. 2005), pp. 70, 6-7, 97; F. H. Colson and G. H. Whitaker, ‘Appendix to De Ebriate’, in F. H. Colson and G. H. Whitaker, trans., Philo: Volume III, Loeb Classical Library, ed. by Jeffrey Henderson (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1930; repr. 2001), pp. 500-509 (p. 501, note 31). 58 Basil’s statements are cited by DelCogliano. DelCogliano, ‘Basil of Caesarea on Proverbs 8:22, p. 187; Basil of Caesarea, Against Eunomius, 2.20, p. 160. 59 Gregory of Nyssa, Against Eunomius, Book I, 22; Book II, 10; Book III, 2; see also Raymond C. Van Leeuwen, ‘The Book of Proverbs: Introduction, Commentary, and Reflections’, in The New Interpreter’s Bible, 5, ed. by Leander E. Keck and others (Nashville, TN: Abingdon Press, 1997), pp. 17-264 (p. 92). 60 Dines, p. 147. 61 DelCogliano, ‘Basil of Caesarea on Proverbs 8:22’, pp. 187-189; Basil of Caesarea, Against Eunomius, 2.20-21, pp. 160-161. 62 DelCogliano says that Eusebius cites these three Greek translators in his Ecclesiastica theologia. Young and Teal consider Eusebius’s ‘frequent discussion of Greek versions other than the LXX’ to be one of the ‘striking’ features of his Old Testament exegesis. DelCogliano, ‘Basil of Caesarea on Proverbs 8:22’, pp. 183-184, 187-188; Young and Teal, p. 22; see also DelCogliano and RaddeGallwitz, p. 160 FN 105. Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 12 be conjectured here in this case study, is that Eusebius might also have been influenced by Philo. Eusebius, as mentioned in the discussions of Philo in the previous chapter, assisted Pamphilus in cataloguing and preserving Philo’s works in Origen’s library in Palestinian Caesarea, in the late third and early fourth centuries,63 and Eusebius lists Philo’s works in his Ecclesiastical History.64 Eusebius includes Philo’s book where ‘ektésato me’ appears, ‘On Drunkenness’, in a grouping of Philo’s works ‘that have come into my hands dealing with Genesis’.65 In light of this, as well as Young and Teal’s statement that Pamphilus ‘was not just a collector of books, but one who engaged in collation, correcting and copying … and engaged his disciples in this oral and collaborative process’,66 it is worth asking whether Eusebius may have been aware of Philo’s use of ‘ektésato me’. This possibility suggests the need for further research into Philo and Eusebius, to add to the research DelCogliano has done on Basil and Eusebius. It is possible, based on the arguments and conjectures offered here, and if DelCogliano’s arguments about Basil and Eusebius are correct, that Basil may have been influenced by Philo through Eusebius. This leads to the posing of one of the ‘what if?’ questions relevant to the exploration of sources, texts, and translations. Prov. 8. 22, as is well known, was one of the scriptures used by Arius in the early fourth century to support his conviction that the Son was a creature, and debates over this verse contributed to Arian and Eunomian controversies for decades.67 Dines cites the ‘lexical choice’ made when Prov. 8. 22 was taken to read ‘created me’ as one of the ‘lexical choices’ in the ‘patristic use of the Bible’ that affected interpretations and ‘controversy’.68 Whether using ‘created me’ was a choice or dictated by available translations, one could ask what might have been different had Arius and others drawn on another translation or interpretation of Prov. 8. 22, one which did not imply, when read christologically, that the Son was created. This is just one example of 63 See the discussion in Chapter 1. Runia, PECL, pp. 16-24, 212-234. See the discussion in Chapter 1. Runia, PECL, pp. 17, 19; Eusebius, The History of the Church from Christ to Constantine, trans. by G. A. Williamson and revised and edited and with a new introduction by Andrew Louth (London: Penguin Books, 1989), 2.18, p. 54. 65 Eusebius, The History of the Church, 2.18, p. 54; Runia, PECL, pp. 17-22; 212-234. 66 Young and Teal, p. 21. 67 See Pelikan, The Christian Tradition, I, pp. 61, 191-200; Anatolios, Retrieving Nicaea, p. 37; Anatolios, Athanasius, ECF, pp. 19, 71, 110-111; Rowan Williams, Arius: Heresy & Tradition, rev. edn (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2002), pp. 107-112; Ayres, Nicaea and its Legacy, p. 4; Young and Teal, p. 46; DelCogliano, ‘Basil of Caesarea on Proverbs 8:22’. 68 Dines, pp. 147-148. 64 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 13 where the use of a particular translation or interpretation as a source may have been influential in fourth century writings on or controversies over the Trinity and creation. 2.2 Influences of ideas about creation on trinitarian ideas about consubstantiality, relations of origin, and unity and distinctions among the Persons Attention is often given to the word homoousios from the 325 creed and whether it was adopted, or homoiousios was preferred, or neither was ideal, for those, like Eunomius, who thought the Son was heteroousios from God. The authors whose works are examined here did not use homoousios often. Athanasius does not offer support for the word until the early to middle 350s, in ‘On the Council of Nicaea’.69 Basil did not offer much support for it until after he wrote Against Eunomius in the mid-360s,70 and it is seldom used by Gregory of Nyssa in his Against Eunomius, which he wrote from 381 to 383.71 Gregory of Nazianzus, in his theological orations, delivered in 380,72 is unusual in saying that both the Son73 and Spirit74 are ‘consubstantial’ with the Father, although Christopher Beeley argues that he often uses homoousios ‘as a response to the arguments of others.’75 However, it will be argued in this major section that these authors did write in support of the concept of the Son, and sometimes the Spirit, being consubstantial or of the same nature with the Father.76 Their ideas about substance or nature were related to ideas about Athanasius’s ‘On the Council of Nicaea’ is dated to the early to middle 350s and is said to be the first work where he defends the word homoousios. Lewis Ayres, ‘Athanasius’ Initial Defense of the Term homoousios: Rereading the De Decretis’, Journal of Early Christian Studies, 12, no. 3 (2004), 337-359 (pp. 337-338, 340); Ayres, Nicaea and its Legacy, pp. 140-144; Anatolios, Athanasius, ECF, p. 176; Anatolios, Retrieving Nicaea, p. 21; R. P. C. Hanson, The Search, p. 419; Louth, ‘The Fourth-Century Alexandrians’, p. 277; Young and Teal, pp. 65, 49; Gwynn, pp. 29-33, 239; J. N. D. Kelly, Early Christian Creeds, pp. 257-259. 70 On Basil’s use of ‘homoousios’, see DelCogliano and Radde-Gallwitz. They date his Against Eunomius to 364 or 365, Ayres to 363-364. and Vaggione to 362-365. DelCogliano and RaddeGallwitz, pp. 16, 33, 120 FN 112; Ayres, Nicaea and its Legacy, p. 191; Vaggione, pp. 5, 8-9. 71 On Gregory’s use of ‘homoousios’, see Barnes, and on the dating, Anatolios. M. Barnes, ‘The Fourth Century’, pp. 59-60; Anatolios, Retrieving Nicaea, p. 158. 72 The dating is from Beeley, Gregory of Nazianzus, p. 39. 73 Gregory of Nazianzus, ‘The Third Theological Oration’, 16, pp. 83-84; 10, p. 78. 74 Gregory of Nazianzus, ‘The Fifth Theological Oration: Oration 31’, in On God and Christ: The Five Theological Orations and Two Letters to Cledonius, trans. by Lionel Wickham, with introduction and notes by Lionel Wickham, Popular Patristics Series, 23, ed. by John Behr (Crestwood, NY: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 2002), pp. 117-147 (10, pp. 123-124). 75 Beeley, Gregory of Nazianzus, p. 213. 76 Kelly, in defending Athanasius for not using homoousios earlier, cites examples of how he wrote of similar concepts (e.g., ‘ “intimately united with the Father’s substance” ’). Kelly says these 69 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 14 how the Son and Spirit were ‘from’ the Father, and, in the Eunomian controversies, what names, especially names indicating origins, say about the nature of what they designate. It also will be argued, in a case study, that monogenés, which is in the 325 and 381 creeds, may not refer to the Son’s being only-begotten. It will be argued that this word may not have been intended to support the principles that the Son is homoousios with or begotten by the Father, which are principles of unity, but rather to speak of the Son’s uniqueness. Throughout the discussions and analyses presented in this major section, it will be argued where trinitarian ideas may have been influenced by the doctrine of creatio ex nihilo and other ideas about creation. This section concludes with summaries of trinitarian principles of unity and distinction which relate to the immanent and economic Trinity. 2.2.1 Athanasius on the Son and Spirit being ‘from’ the Father Athanasius’s ‘On the Council of Nicaea’; his Letters to Serapion, which are dated to 359-361;77 and a later letter he may have co-authored, ‘To the Bishops of Africa’;78 are drawn upon here to illustrate arguments about the Son and Spirit being ‘from’ the Father, and how these arguments were grounded in principles related to the doctrine of creation. ‘On the Council of Nicaea’ is used here with caution, given that Athanasius is said to have misrepresented his opponents in some writings.79 These representations include, according to Gwynn, his grouping and labeling opponents as ‘Eusebians’, after the fourth century Eusebius of Nicomedia,80 and, as Khaled Anatolios says, his ‘conflating all antiNicene factions as “Arians” ’81 The practice adopted here is to examine Athanasius’s writings about the 325 creed to see what they reveal about his theological perspectives in the 350s. This is compatible with approaches taken by Anatolios, who looks at Athanasius expressions are ‘really synonyms of the Nicene teaching’. Similar examples will be offered here, taken from arguments about creation. Kelly, Early Christian Creeds, p. 260. 77 DelCogliano, Radde-Gallwitz, and Ayres, p. 29. 78 This letter was written by Athanasius and other bishops, according to its heading. Hanson dates it to 369 and raises the question of its authenticity. Athanasius, ‘To the Bishops of Africa’, trans. by Archibald Robertson and Cardinal Newman, in St. Athanasius: Select Works and Letters, NPNF, 2nd series, 4, ed. by Philip Schaff, Henry Wace, and Archibald Robertson (1892; Oak Harbor: Logos Research Systems, 1997 [on CD-ROM]), 1; R. P. C. Hanson, The Search, p. 420. 79 Gwynn, pp. vii-viii, 1-10, and throughout; DelCogliano, Radde-Gallwitz, and Ayres, pp. 15-17; Ayres, Nicaea and Its Legacy, pp. 105-111; Young and Teal, pp. 49-52. 80 Gwynn, p. 6 and throughout; see also Anatolios, Athanasius, ECF, pp. 176-178. 81 Anatolios, Athanasius, ECF, pp. 176-178. Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 15 as a ‘theologian in his own right’,82 and Lewis Ayres, in his analysis of ‘On the Council of Nicaea’.83 Given the interest here in orthodox / catholic theologies, however, it also is relevant that Gwynn cautions that what Athanasius deems to be ‘orthodox’ or Nicene theology should not be taken to represent ‘the traditional and universal faith of the Church that he wished to claim’.84 With these caveats in mind, it should be noted that Athanasius did attend the 325 council,85 and some of his accounts of the council could be historical. Athanasius, in ‘On the Council of Nicaea’, purports to explain why the council had included ‘ “from the essence” (ek tés ousias) and “one in essence” (homoousios)’ in its creed.86 He claims that the council, to respond to the ‘Arians’, had wanted to use words from scripture to convey ‘that the Son is not from non-being but from God … neither creature nor something made, but from the Father as his own (idion) offspring’.87 He says that ‘Arians’ or ‘the party of Eusebius’ had thought that ‘from God’ referred not only to how the Son came into being, but also to how human beings did (‘from’ was understood in different ways in scripture).88 The council therefore was compelled to say, according to Athanasius, that ‘ “the Son is from the essence of the Father” (ek tés ousias tou theou)’, so that the Son or Word was ‘from God’ in a unique way.89 Ayres shows that Athanasius’s ideas that the Son is ‘from the essence of the Father’ and ‘ “proper” to the Father’s substance’ appear in his earlier Orations against the Arians, which Anatolios dates to 339-343.90 Similar ideas are expressed in the later ‘To the Bishops of Africa’, where another purported explanation is given of why the 325 council had said the Son is ‘coessential’ with the Father.91 In this letter, it is said that the council, to counter ideas about the Son being a creature ‘made of nothing’ and there having been a time ‘when He was not’, had sought to establish that ‘the Son alone might be deemed 82 Anatolios, Retrieving Nicaea, pp. 12-13; see also Young and Teal, pp. 51-52. Ayres, ‘Athanasius’ Initial Defense of the Term homoousios’. 84 Gwynn, p. 170, also pp. 6, 239-244. 85 Anatolios, Athanasius, ECF, pp. 11; Gwynn, 4. 86 English and Greek citations are from Anatolios’ translation. Athanasius, ‘On the Council of Nicaea’, 3, p. 180; see also 1, p. 178. 87 English and Greek citations here and for the rest of this paragraph are from Anatolios’s translation. Athanasius, ‘On the Council of Nicaea’, 19, pp. 196-197. 88 Athanasius, ‘On the Council of Nicaea’, 19, pp. 196-197. 89 Athanasius, ‘On the Council of Nicaea’, 19, pp. 196-197. 90 Ayres, ‘Athanasius’ Initial Defense of the Term homoousios’, pp. 342, 344-345; Anatolios, Athanasius, ECF, pp. 19-20. 91 Athanasius, ‘To the Bishops of Africa’, 5; R. P. C. Hanson, The Search, p. 420. 83 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 16 proper to the Essence of the Father’, because ‘this is peculiar [idion] to the one who is Only-begotten [monogenous] and true Word in relation to a Father’.92 Ayres argues that when Athanasius distinguishes between how the Son and creatures are ‘from God’, in ‘On the Council of Nicaea’, he draws on the relationship ‘by nature’ of a Father to his ‘offspring’ or Son.93 This passage also is of interest because Athanasius distinguishes between how creatures and the Son are ‘from God’, with creatures having been ‘made’, and the Son being ‘from the being of God’, because He is a son ‘by nature’: … if the Word is not from God as a genuine son who is from his father by nature, but is said to be from the Father in the same way that all creatures are said to be so, because of their having been created [by the Father], then indeed he is not from the being of the Father, nor is he a son according to essence [kat ousian], but because of virtue, as we are who are called sons by grace. But if he is alone from God as genuine Son, as indeed is the case, then it is well said that the son is from the being of God.94 In this passage, Athanasius can be seen as explaining how he (and perhaps also the 325 council, if his account is accurate95) was able to support the idea that the Son was ‘from’ the being of the Father, a similar concept to homoousios with the Father, for two reasons. First, a ‘genuine’ son must be of the same nature as the Father, and second, the Son cannot have come ‘from’ the Father in the same way creatures do. He does not offer much explanation, however, on what it means for the Son to come ‘from’ the Father. Athanasius discusses these matters in his later Letters to Serapion. He argues that there is a distinction between ‘makers’ and ‘begetters’, and between ‘creatures’ and ‘sons’, and that fathers, whether human parents or God, are ‘begetters’, and sons, including the Son, are sons ‘by nature’, who are ‘the same as our fathers in substance’.96 He does not explain how the Father’s begetting of the Son took place, but again associates the state of being begotten with that of being of the same essence as the begetter.97 He argues that while things that are made, such as a ‘house’ or ‘ship’, cannot be of the same ‘substance’ Athanasius, ‘To the Bishops of Africa’, 5. The words idion and monogenous are from Thesaurus Linguae Graecae, A Digital Library of Greek Literature, University of California, Irvine, 2035.049, from ‘Epistula ad Afros episcopos’, J.-P. Migne, Patrologiae cursus completus (series Graeca) (MPG) 26, Paris: Migne, 1857-1866: 1029-1048 (p. 1037, line 38). 93 Ayres, ‘Athanasius’ Initial Defense of the Term homoousios’, p. 347; Athanasius, ‘On the Council of Nicaea’, 22, pp. 199-200. 94 The English and Greek citations are from Athanasius, ‘On the Council of Nicaea’, 22, p. 200. 95 Athanasius, ‘On the Council of Nicaea’, 22, p. 200. 96 Athanasius, ‘Letters to Serapion’, 2.6.1, 112. 97 Athanasius, ‘Letters to Serapion’, 2.6.2-2.6.3, pp. 112-113. 92 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 17 as those who made them, ‘so too it is appropriate for someone to say that every son is the same as his own father in substance’.98 He then makes a similar point to points in ‘On the Council of Nicaea’: ‘So if there is Father and Son, then the Son must be Son by nature and in truth. But this is what it means to be the same as the Father in substance…’99 The expression ‘genuine son’ appears in the passage from ‘On the Council of Nicaea’. The word translated as ‘genuine’ is ‘gnésios’,100 and ‘genuine sonship’ is an implication of its first meaning, ‘belonging to the race, i.e., lawfully begotten, legitimate’.101 In the second instance it is used above, ‘monos’ appears: ‘ei de ek tou theou esti monos ōs uios gnésios’,102 and one might see a connection between monos and gnésios, and monogenés. The word monogenés can mean ‘single of its kind, only’, ‘the only member of a kin or kind’, or ‘uniqueness of being’,103 meanings which stem from ‘ “ of a single [monos] kind [genos]” ’, and do not say how a son comes into being.104 For Athanasius, the ‘genuine Son’, who is from the Father’s being ‘by nature’, is of the divine ‘race’ or ‘kind’, which includes Father and Son, so the Son is not the only one of this kind. The Son, moreover, is of this race or kind because he was begotten, and did not come ‘from the Father in the same way that all creatures are said to be’. So these meanings of ‘genuine sonship’ here are similar to, but not the same as, some meanings of monogenés to be discussed. Athanasius, ‘Letters to Serapion’, 2.6.3, p. 113. Athanasius, ‘Letters to Serapion’, 2.6.3, p. 113. 100 Thesaurus Linguae Graecae, 2035.003, ‘De decretis Nicaenae synodi,’ Epist., Concil., H.G. Opitz, Athanasius Werke, vol. 2.1. Berlin: De Gruyter, 1940: 1-45 (ch. 22, section 5, lines 1-2, 5-6). 101 Lampe, pp. 316-317. 102 Thesaurus Linguae Graecae, 2035.003, ‘De decretis Nicaenae synodi,’ (ch. 22, section 5, lines 5-6). 103 See the previous chapter. Dale Moody, ‘God’s Only Son: The Translation of John 3. 16 in the Revised Standard Version’, Journal of Biblical Literature, 72, no. 4 D (1953), 213-219 (pp. 213215); Raymond E. Brown, The Gospel According to John, 2 vols, Anchor Bible 29 and 29a (New York: Doubleday, 1966-1970), I (1966), pp. 13-14, 17; Leon Morris, The Gospel According to John, rev. edn, The New International Commentary on the New Testament, ed. by Ned B. Stone, F. F. Bruce, and Gordon D. Fee (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1995), p. 93; George R. BeasleyMurray, John, 2nd edn, Word Biblical Commentary, 36, ed. by Bruce A. Metzger, Ralph P. Martin, and others (Nashville, TN: Thomas Nelson, Inc., 2000), p. 14; Frederick William Danker, ed., A Greek-English Lexicon of the New Testament and Other Early Christian Literature, 3rd edn (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2000), pp. 839-842 (p. 658); Jaroslav Pelikan, What Has Athens to Do with Jerusalem?: ‘Timaeus’ and ‘Genesis’ in Counterpoint, Jerome Lectures, 21 (Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press, 1997), pp. 101-102. 104 This was discussed in the previous chapter. Raymond E. Brown, The Gospel, pp. 13-14; Beasley-Murray, p. 14; Leon Morris, p. 93; Moody, pp. 213-215 and entire article; see also Kevin Giles, The Eternal Generation of the Son: Maintaining Orthodoxy in Trinitarian Theology, with a foreword by Robert Letham (Downers Grove, IL: IVP Academic, 2012), pp. 64-65. 98 99 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 18 Whether Athanasius’s account in ‘On the Council of Nicaea’ is historical, the 325 creed appears to be grounded in the doctrine of creatio ex nihilo, which was established by the third century. The creed, in saying that Jesus Christ, the Son, was ‘begotten not made’ (gennéthenta ou poiéthenta), distinguishes his mode of generation from that of creatures, and goes further by saying that all things came into being through him (‘di’ ou ta panta egeneto’, from John 1. 3).105 The creed also condemns those who say, ‘There was when He was not, and, Before being born (gennéthénai) He was not’, and ‘He came into existence out of nothing’. The first condemnation applied to people like Arius, who said there was a time when the Son ‘was not’ (ouk én),106 which can be seen as a rejection of the attestation of John 1. 1 that the Word ‘was’ (én) in the beginning. The second applied to those who thought the Son came from the same origin as creatures: out of nothing.107 Athanasius makes similar arguments when he claims the council ‘made it manifestly clear that “from the essence” and “of one essence” are abrogations of the trite slogans of the impious: such as that he is a “creature” and “made” and something which has come into being (genéton) and changeable and that he was not before he was generated.’108 Athanasius took on issues about the non-created status and substance of the Holy Spirit, and, to a lesser extent, the discussion of how the Spirit is ‘from’ God, in his Letters to Serapion, where he argues against the ‘Tropikoi’ or ‘Tropici’, who thought the Spirit had been created and was not divine.109 Athanasius does use ‘homoousios’ with respect to the Spirit, when he says the Spirit is ‘proper to the one Word and proper to and the same as the one God in substance.’110 His ideas in these letters, however, are based more on the relationship the Spirit has with the Son, than with the Father. This is clear when he says the Spirit is of the substance of the Word: ‘Thus the Spirit is not a creature but is said to be 105 Greek and English words from the 325 creed in this paragraph are from J. N. D. Kelly, Early Christian Creeds, pp. 215-216. 106 These words are in the ‘creed of Arius’ as presented by Skarsaune. Oskar Skarsaune, ‘A Neglected Detail in the Creed of Nicaea (325)’, Vigiliae Christianae, 41, no. 1 (1987), 34-54 (p. 40); see also R. P. C. Hanson, The Search, p. 6; Anatolios, Athanasius, ECF, pp. 7, 9. 107 Anatolios says Eusebius of Nicomedia, Eusebius of Caesarea, and Asterius, early supporters of Arius, had distanced themselves from Arius’s position that the Son had come into being out of nothing, so this view was not pervasive at the time of the 325 council. Anatolios, Retrieving Nicaea, pp. 18-19. 108 Athanasius, ‘On the Council of Nicaea’, 20, p. 198. 109 Athanasius, ‘Letters to Serapion’, 1.10.4, p. 69; 1.1.2, p. 53. 110 Athanasius, ‘Letters to Serapion’, 1.27.3, p. 96; DelCogliano, Radde-Gallwitz, and Ayres, p. 96 FN 66; Toom, Classical Trinitarian Theology, p. 91. Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 19 proper to the substance of the Word and proper to God and in God’.111 He emphasises the relationship between the Spirit and Son again when he says that if the Spirit has ‘the same unity with the Son as the Son has with the Father’, the Spirit cannot be a creature.112 Athanasius does argue on behalf of the Spirit’s uncreated nature in a way that implies that the Spirit is of the same essence as the Father. He argues that ‘two distinct natures’ cannot be mixed in the Godhead, which would result if the Spirit was a creature.113 That there would be two natures, one shared by Father and Son, the other the created nature of the Spirit, is implicit in his statement that the Tropikoi accepted the ‘unity’ of Son and Father, without ‘dividing them’.114 He then argues that the Trinity cannot have anything ‘foreign’ mixed with it, because God cannot be a ‘compound’ and ‘the whole Trinity is one God’, which suggests the Spirit shares the essence of the Father and Son.115 This argument is similar to Philo’s idea that God is not comprised of parts or mixed with anything, which, as discussed, is grounded in the principle of divine simplicity.116 Philo’s idea that God would be ‘lessened’ if something inferior were to be ‘assimilated to him’117 is reflected in Athanasius’s claim that if the Spirit were a creature, the mixture that would occur in the ‘divinity in the Trinity’ would ‘rupture’ its unity, and ‘reduce it to the level of creatures’.118 So, in Athanasius’s arguments, he can be seen as defending the ‘unity of God’, including of God’s essence, while countering the belief that the Spirit is a creature.119 Athanasius offers a similar argument, with a clear trinitarian statement, when he says: ‘So, the Trinity is holy and perfect, confessed in Father and Son and Holy Spirit. It has nothing foreign or external mixed with it, not is it composed of Creator and creature, but is entirely given to creating and making. It is self-consistent and indivisible in nature, and it Athanasius, ‘Letters to Serapion’, 3.4.1, p. 132; see also Najeeb Awad, God without a Face? On the Personal Individuation of the Holy Spirit, Dogmatik in der Moderne, 2 (Tübingen, Germany: Mohr Siebeck, 2011), p. 85. 112 Athanasius, ‘Letters to Serapion’, 1.2.3, p. 55. 113 Athanasius, ‘Letters to Serapion’, 1.2.1-1.2.4, pp. 54-55; see also 1.17.1, p. 79. 114 Athanasius, ‘Letters to Serapion’, 1.2.1-1.2.3, pp. 54-55. 115 Athanasius, ‘Letters to Serapion’, 1.2.3-1.2.4, p. 55; see also 1.17.1, p. 79. 116 See the discussion in the previous chapter. Toom, Classical Trinitarian Theology, p. 22; Ayres and Radde-Gallwitz, p. 468; Ayres, Nicaea and its Legacy, pp. 280-282. 117 The translation is Winston’s. Winston, Philo of Alexandria, pp. 130-131; see also Philo, ‘Allegorical Interpretation of Genesis II, III’, in Philo: Volume 1, trans. by F. H. Colson and G. H. Whitaker, Loeb Classical Library, ed. by Jeffrey Henderson (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1929; repr. 2004), pp. 146-473 (II, 2-3, pp. 224-227). This treatise is referred to as Leg. All. 118 Athanasius, ‘Letters to Serapion’, 1.2.3-1.2.4, p. 55. 119 Athanasius, ‘Letters to Serapion’, 1.2.3, p. 55. 111 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 20 has one activity.’120 He says that the Trinity is ‘indivisible in nature’, both because of his reliance on the principle of divine simplicity, and his conviction that the Son and Spirit could not be created, because they take part in the activities of ‘creating and making’. He also puts forth other arguments, partly grounded in his belief that ‘our knowledge of the Spirit is derived from the Son’, and the attestation of John 1. 3 that ‘all things came to be through’ the Son, that ‘the Son is Creator like the Father’, and the Spirit ‘is not a creature but is involved in the act of creating’.121 These examples illustrate Athanasius’s belief that God is Creator and Trinity, and his use of ‘Creator’ for the Son will be brought up below. Athanasius is vague, however, about what it means for the Spirit to be ‘from’ God, as can be seen where he argues for the Spirit’s being ‘from God’ based on 1 Cor. 2. 11-12, which is not about creation or proceeding, but about the Spirit knowing ‘the things that belong to God’.122 He does draw on a principle of the doctrine of creatio ex nihilo when he says the Spirit cannot have ‘kinship’ with creatures, partly because it is ‘from God’ and hence ‘cannot be from nothing’, which indicates a connection between the Spirit’s mode of generation and substance.123 It is not obvious, though, how the Spirit’s being ‘from God’ differs from other ways that being ‘from God’ is presented in scripture, which he says prevented the 325 Council from using simply ‘from God’ language for the Son. A few final reflections on Athanasius’s ideas will be offered, to illustrate connections between the doctrines of creation and the Trinity. The Son’s coming ‘from’ God’s essence would have been the only option available as the source of the Son’s being, if one believed the Son was not a creature, and that creatures come ‘from’ nothing. Athanasius makes this connection when he says ‘inasmuch as the Son has no likeness to creatures but has all that belongs to the Father, that the Son must be the same as the Father in substance’, and otherwise the Son would be the same as creatures ‘in substance’, beliefs he attributes to the 325 council.124 He says neither the Son nor the Spirit could have come ‘from nothing’, because creatures are ‘from nothing’,125 another argument related to substance. Athanasius also gives roles in creation to the Son and Spirit, which precludes them from being ‘from’ Athanasius, ‘Letters to Serapion’, 1.28.1-1.28.2, pp. 96-97. Athanasius, ‘Letters to Serapion’, 2.13.4-2.14.1, pp. 123-124. 122 Athanasius, ‘Letters to Serapion’, 1.22.1, p. 87. 123 Athanasius, ‘Letters to Serapion’, 1.22.1, p. 87. 124 Athanasius, ‘Letters to Serapion’, 2.5.1-2.5.2, p. 111. 125 Athanasius, ‘Letters to Serapion’, 2.11.2, p. 120. 120 121 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 21 matter, which they would have taken part in creating. However, it is not clear what he thought being ‘from’ the Father meant with respect to how the Son and Spirit came into being, or their modes of generation. 2.2.2 Case study: translating or interpreting monogenés Before moving to discussing ideas about consubstantiality and relations of origin as they appear in writings and orations against Eunomius, another case study will be offered. Here the idea that the Son is ‘only-begotten’ will be examined, and other possibilities for understanding monogenés will be offered, given that this word is used by the Cappadocian ‘Fathers’ and Eunomius, as will be seen. Justification for relooking at monogenés comes from the opportunity to apply, to the text of the 325 and 381 creeds126 and to fourth century writings, the revised translations scholars have applied to the Gospel of John.127 The placement and intent of the word monogené is ambiguous in the 325 creed, or, as Oskar Skarsaune puts it, it has ‘rather unelegant positioning’ or seems ‘misplaced’.128 In J. N. D. Kelly’s text, it can be argued that monogené clarifies gennéthenta, when the creed says that Jesus Christ, Son of God, is ‘gennéthenta ek tou patros monogené, toutestin ek tés ousias tou patros’.129 This is translated as ‘begotten from the Father, only-begotten, that is, from the substance of the Father’.130 Skarsaune’s position that monogené is a ‘precision to’ gennéthenta is similar to the argument being made here, but he believes this yields the meaning ‘ “begotten as only-begotten” ’,131 while other arguments will be made below. Kevin Giles offers two translations of this part of the creed, using ‘only’ or ‘uniquely’ for monogenés, rather than ‘only-begotten’: ‘begotten [gennaō] of the Father, the only Kelly says, writing of the 325 creed, that ‘[w]e may pass over ONLY-BEGOTTEN (monogenés), although much ink has been expended in the discussion of it, because it was accepted by all parties in the Arian quarrel and no special dogmatic significance was read into it’, and cites as support an 1876 work. However, this work, Two Dissertations, by Fenton John Anthony Hort, published by Cambridge and available from Google Scholar (http://scholar.google.com/), is about the different textual traditions of John 1. 18, and the scholars cited in this and the previous chapter use more recent research. J. N. D. Kelly, Early Christian Creeds, p. 235, also 303-304. 127 Kevin Giles, who draws on Moody, applies some of the alternative translations of monogenés to the 325 creed and fourth century writings, and argues that these alternatives were accepted at the time. I do not think he offers enough evidence to support this, and he and I disagree at points, but he shares my interest in relooking at monogenés. Giles, pp. 27-28, 64-66, 69, 81, and elsewhere. 128 Skarsaune, pp. 34-35. 129 The Greek and English text are from J. N. D. Kelly, Early Christian Creeds, pp. 215-216. 130 J. N. D. Kelly, Early Christian Creeds, pp. 215-216. 131 Skarsaune, p. 36. 126 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 22 [monogenés] [Son] of the being [ousia] of the Father’,132 or ‘uniquely [monogenés] begotten [gennaō] of the Father, of the being [ousia] of the Father’.133 Giles says the first translation speaks of the Son as ‘begotten and unique’, and the second as ‘the uniquely begotten Son’, but, in either case, he says monogenés and gennaō were not intended to be ‘synonyms’.134 However, even Giles’s first option seems to suggest that monogenés is related to the Son’s mode of being, as being the only one ‘of’ the Father’s being. Skarsaune cites a creed he attributes to Arius, which uses ‘gennésanta uion monogené’ but with God as the subject, as seen in Skarsaune’s translation: ‘We know one God … who brought forth the only-begotten Son…’.135 Skarsaune argues that Arius thought that monogenés ‘has no other meaning than that God’s Son was brought forth directly by the Father without any mediator – unlike the rest of God’s creation, in which the Son was the Mediator’,136 which does focus on the Father and the Son. Skarsaune also notes that ‘the standard Arian exegesis’ of monogenés later came to be that ‘the monos applies primarily to the Father as sole begetter-creator of the Son’, and the ‘Son alone was brought forth from the Father alone, without any mediator’.137 This interpretation, with its emphasis on the Father as the begetter and one who is alone, will be relevant in discussing Eunomius. Skarsaune shows that Alexander of Alexandria, early in the fourth century, had a creed that countered Arius’s views, and which placed gennéthenta directly after monogenés.138 Skarsaune is aware of other meanings of monogenés, including ‘only one of its kind’, but he takes monogenés here again to be a ‘precision’ on gennéthenta, with the latter word being followed and further clarified by ‘ek tés ousias tou patros’.139 However, in the text of Alexander’s creed, monogené is part of ‘ton uion tou theou monogené’, and is separated from gennéthenta.140 This suggests that monogené may have suggested something else about the Son, which Skarsaune does not consider. Another proposal about how monogenés may have been understood at the time of 132 The brackets are from Giles. Giles, p. 147. The brackets are from Giles. Giles, p. 148. 134 Giles, pp. 147-148. 135 The Greek and English text are from Skarsaune, pp. 40-41. 136 Skarsaune, p. 41. 137 Skarsaune, p. 52 FN 22. 138 Skarsaune, pp. 42-44. 139 Skarsaune, p. 44. 140 Skarsaune, p. 42. 133 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 23 Arius comes from Tarmo Toom. Toom says that Arius probably could have agreed with the words in the 325 creed that come before ‘from the essence of the Father’, including monogenés, which Toom says Arius likely understood to mean ‘unique’, again using an alternative translation, but when monogenés was taken with the ‘clarifying clause’ of ‘from the essence’ of the Father, it meant the Son was consubstantial with the Father.141 As already discussed, the other possibilities for understanding monogenés, in addition to the traditional translation of ‘only-begotten’, include ‘single of its kind, only’, ‘the only member of a kin or kind’, ‘uniqueness of being’, or ‘only child’. It also can be used synonymously with agapétos (beloved) and suggest a ‘beloved child’, as it is in a work by an unknown author attributed to Athanasius.142 Any of these meanings, if they had been held by the 325 council when the creed was being crafted, might not have reinforced either that the Son was begotten or that He was of the substance of the Father. The Son could have been understood as unique or one of a kind, without saying how He came into being. The ambiguity of how monogené is placed in the creed does not permit conclusions here, but this possibility should be given consideration. Athanasius may have known some of these meanings, even if they are implicit in his writings. He uses monogenés in the writings discussed above and his earlier Orations against the Arians.143 In his Orations, he discusses the difference between the Word or Son being the ‘ “firstborn of creation” ’ and ‘only-begotten’.144 He says the former expression applies to someone born first who has siblings, and is related to the created order, but someone is called monogenés ‘because there are no other brothers’.145 That someone has no siblings does not say how he or she came into being, so this is not 141 Toom, Classical Trinitarian Theology, p. 93, see also 81. This was discussed in the previous chapter. The unknown author was writing in a work called Athanasius’s fourth discourse against the Arians. Beasley-Murray, p. 14; Colin Gunton, ‘And in One Lord, Jesus Christ … Begotten, Not Made’, in Nicene Christianity: The Future for a New Ecumenism, ed. by Christopher R. Seitz (Grand Rapids: MI: Brazos Press, 2001), pp. 35-48 (pp. 39, 230 FN 8); Athanasius, ‘Four Discourses against the Arians’, trans. by Archibald Robertson and Cardinal Newman, in St. Athanasius: Select Works and Letters, NPNF, 2nd series, 4, ed. by Philip Schaff, Henry Wace, and Archibald Robertson (1892; Oak Harbor: Logos Research Systems, 1997 [on CD-ROM]), IV, 24; Athanasius’s ‘Oratio quarta contra Arianos’, 2035.117, 25, in the Thesaurus Linguae Graecae; Lampe, p. 881. 143 Uses of monogenés in his works can be seen by searching the Thesaurus Linguae Graecae. 144 The expression ‘firstborn of creation’ is from Col. 1. 15. The citations from Athanasius in this paragraph are from Athanasius, Orations against the Arians (selections), trans. and ed. by Khaled Anatolios, in Athanasius, by Anatolios, ECF, pp. 87-175 (2.62, pp. 155-156). 145 The Greek is from the Thesaurus Linguae Graecae. Athanasius, Orations, 2.62, pp. 155-156. 142 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 24 necessarily about the Son’s unique mode of generation. Athanasius also says monogenés, Son, Word, and Wisdom are ‘terms that refer back to the Father and indicate the fact that the Son belongs to the Father’ [italics added], and he cites biblical passages that use these terms, including John 1. 14 and Mt. 3. 17 (‘ “This is my beloved Son” ’).146 He argues that ‘monogenés’ is more appropriate than ‘firstborn’ for the Word, because there is no other Word or Wisdom (thus, He is one of a kind), and ‘he alone is the true Son of the Father’,147 which is an earlier instance of his discussing the ‘true Son’ than in the works cited above. His mention of the ‘beloved Son’ and onlybegotten Son ‘in the bosom of the Father’ (John 1. 18) also may hint that he understood monogenés and agapétos to be related. He does also say that monogenés is used in ‘in reference to the generation from the Father’.148 However, his overall arguments in this section suggest that monogenés and the Son’s belonging to the father have other meanings for him, meanings about how the Son is special and unique, and loved by the Father. In the previous chapter, it was said that some biblical scholars believe the tradition of translating monogenés as ‘unigenitus’ (only-begotten) in the Latin text of John started with Jerome, as a result of his theological interests.149 However, it is possible that the idea that monogenés means only-begotten came about during the Eunomian controversies. This can only be argued and conjectured here, but it is noteworthy that Athanasius’s writings, in which he shows he may have held other ideas about monogenés, were a few decades earlier than Cappadocian writings and orations against Eunomian ideas. Basil and Gregory of Nyssa use monogenés frequently in their treatises Against Eunomius,150 although one has to consider the instances where they are citing Eunomius. Even so, there are instances where they show that they understand it to relate to the 146 Athanasius, Orations, 2.62, pp. 155-156. Athanasius, Orations, 2.62, pp. 155-156. 148 Widdicombe cites this section of his Orations, saying ‘it is clear’ Athanasius thinks ‘the prefix (monos) (“only,” “unique”) gives the interpretative key’ for monogenés. He also says Athanasius seems to think monogenés ‘was determinative of the sense in which “generated” is to be taken’, which suggests Athanasius had multiple meanings of monogenés in mind. Giles cites this section, and thinks monogenés conveys something about the eternal begetting of the Son, a unique way of coming into being. Giles is ambiguous, given that he also says the correct meaning of monogenés is unique or only. Widdicombe, ‘The Fathers on the Father’, p. 118; Giles, pp. 81-82. 149 See the arguments in the previous chapter. 150 Examples are numerous. See the Thesaurus Linguae Graecae; Pelikan, What Has Athens...?, p. 102; Lampe, pp. 880-882. 147 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 25 uniqueness of the Son’s mode of origin. In one place, where Basil is responding to what he considered Eunomius’s misuse of monogenés, Basil argues that ‘in common usage [monogenés] does not designate the one who comes from only one person [as Eunomius thought], but the one who is the only one begotten’.151 It is possible that Eunomius’s position, as reported by Basil, stemmed from what Skarsaune calls the later ‘standard Arian exegesis’, where ‘monos applies primarily to the Father as sole begetter-creator of the Son’. However, even if Eunomius was not thinking of the Son in his use of monogenés here, one sees that Basil himself thought monogenés referred to ‘the only one begotten’.152 Similarly, Gregory of Nyssa argues that ‘Only-begotten’ refers to ‘something unique and exceptional’ about the generation of the Son, which he says is ‘not in common with all begetting, and is peculiar to Him’.153 Gregory’s argument is related to the nature of what comes into being, because he says that if there were no distinctions in the begetting, there would be ‘mixture and community’ between the Son and ‘the rest of generated things’.154 His argument also is related to the doctrine of creatio ex nihilo, as evident when he says that ‘non-existence before generation is proper to all things that exist by generation’, but ‘this is foreign to the special character of the Only-begotten, to which the name “Onlybegotten” bears witness that there attaches nothing belonging to the mode of that form of common generation which Eunomius misapprehends’.155 Gregory of Nazianzus does not use monogenés often in his theological orations.156 However, in two cases where he may understand it as only-begotten, which is inconclusive in the texts, he lists it as one of many attributes for the Son or Jesus Christ, without saying 151 This passage is cited by Giles, who supplies the Greek for monogenés. Basil of Caesarea, Against Eunomius, 2.20, p. 159; Giles, p. 132. 152 Giles says he wrote to DelCogliano to ask why he and Radde-Gallwitz had chosen to use the translation ‘only-begotten’ for monogenés in Basil’s Against Eunomius. DelCogliano replied that they had considered using ‘only’ or ‘unique’, to be ‘ “in line with modern biblical translations” ’, but decided to use only-begotten, because they thought Basil ‘really understood the term in the sense of the ‘ “only offspring of the Father” ’ or ‘an “only child” ’. DelCogliano said they thought this was in accordance with ‘the traditional translation of “Only-Begotten” ’. In light of arguments I am presenting here, one could still say that neither only offspring nor only child speaks of how the offspring or child came into being. One can also argue, as I am, that other meanings could have been overlooked, either by Basil himself, or the translators, or both. Giles, p. 145 FN 124. 153 Gregory of Nyssa, Against Eunomius, Book VIII, 5. 154 Gregory of Nyssa, Against Eunomius, Book VIII, 5. 155 Gregory of Nyssa, Against Eunomius, Book VIII, 5. 156 This is shown in searching Gregory’s orations using the Thesaurus Linguae Graecae. Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 26 it is significant, and it is the translations that say his meaning was ‘only-begotten’.157 Eunomius uses monogenés often, sometimes ambiguously.158 The first instance is in a ‘profession of faith’ at the beginning of his first apology.159 The meaning is ambiguous, because his wording of the relevant clause is: ‘kai eis hena monogené uion theou, theon logon…’, where monogené modifies the Son of God, and ‘begotten’ does not appear, nor, of course, any mention of the Son’s being from the substance of the Father.160 Unless one knew that Eunomius understood monogenés alone, without other words that it clarified, to mean ‘only-begotten’, one could ask whether it is Vaggione’s translation that establishes this meaning: ‘And in one only-begotten Son of God, God the Word…’.161 DelCogliano and Radde-Gallwitz’s translation of Basil’s restatement of Eunomius’s profession of faith is the same as Vaggione’s.162 This could illustrate that translators make assumptions of what monogenés means. In this case, the choice of ‘only-begotten’ is not borne out by the text of Eunomius’s profession of faith, which, unlike Arius’s creed, as cited by Skarsaune, does not include a reference to the concept of being begotten. Other instances exist where Eunomius’s use of monogenés may be ambiguous, such as in 12.1, where he says ‘kai eis uios (monogenés gar)’, which Vaggione translates as ‘the Son too is one, being onlybegotten’, and 15.8, 13, where monogenés is set in the context of broader arguments.163 However, in other instances where Eunomius uses monogenés, he appears to use it as a title, probably in place of using ‘Son’, given that he did not like ‘Father’ and ‘Son’ terminology,164 as will be evident in the discussions below. One of Vaggione’s cautions about using Basil’s Against Eunomius as a witness to Eunomius’s first apology is that he suspects there were ‘mutual influences’ between these Gregory of Nazianzus, ‘The Third Theological Oration’, 17, pp. 84-85; Gregory of Nazianzus, ‘The Fourth Theological Oration: Oration 30’, in On God and Christ: The Five Theological Orations and Two Letters to Cledonius, trans. by Lionel Wickham, with introduction and notes by Lionel Wickham, Popular Patristics Series, 23, ed. by John Behr (Crestwood, NY: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 2002), pp. 93-116 (20, pp. 109-111); Thesaurus Linguae Graecae. 158 Vaggione provides an index entry for monogenés. Vaggione, p. 204. 159 Eunomius, ‘The Apology of Eunomius’, in Eunomius: The Extant Works, text and translation by Richard Paul Vaggione, Oxford Early Christian Texts, ed. by Henry Chadwick (New York: Oxford University Press, 1987), pp. 33-75 (4, p. 37). 160 Eunomius, ‘Apology’, 5.3, pp. 38-39. 161 Vaggione, p. 39. 162 Vaggione, p. 39; Basil, Against Eunomius, 1.4, pp. 88-89. 163 Eunomius, ‘Apology’, 12.1, pp. 46-47; 15.8, 13, pp. 52-53. 164 See the discussion below and Ayres and Radde-Gallwitz, p. 466. 157 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 27 two works.165 One of these influences could have been what monogenés meant, which Basil could have imposed on his interpretations of Eunomius, consciously or not. This cannot be explored further here, but it is possible that Jerome was not the only theologian in the second half of the fourth century to allow theology or controversies to influence interpretations of key terminology. It is possible that monogenés took on the meaning ‘only-begotten’ because of the ways it was used in Eunomius’s writings, and how Basil and Gregory of Nyssa chose to use it in their rebuttals. If so, the meaning of this word would have changed, as a result of the intense debates over whether or how the Son came into being, and the Son’s status with respect to the Father or the ‘Unbegotten’. On the other hand, it is possible that monogenés meant other things at the time, including to Eunomius, and it is the English translations that apply the meaning ‘only-begotten’. The creed adopted by the 381 Council of Constantinople refers to Jesus Christ as ‘ton uion tou theou ton monogené, ton ek tou patros gennéthenta’.166 Kelly points out that ton monogené stands in apposition to ‘the Son of God’ and has an article, which he considers among the ‘minor’ differences between the 325 and 381 creeds.167 However, the clause that contains monogené is identical to the clause in Alexander’s creed, cited by Skarsaune, although in the 381 creed, gennéthenta is at the end of the clause that follows, not the beginning, which further separates monogené from the idea that the Son is begotten. This could be a significant difference. The 381 creed, with this placement, may not have been intended to say the Son is ‘only-begotten’ or to refer to the Son’s substance, but may have held one of the other meanings of monogenés about the Son being unique, one of a kind, or beloved. If so, monogenés may not support the unity of Father and Son, or ideas about mode of generation or being of the same substance, but rather may speak of a unique attribute that distinguishes the Son alone. 2.2.3 Nature, relations of origin, unity, and distinction in Eunomian debates Here, illustrations and arguments will be presented to offer insights into how Basil of Caesarea and Gregory of Nazianzus wrote about ideas related to the consubstantiality and relations of origin of the three Persons, in their treatises or orations against Eunomian 165 Vaggione, pp. 25-26. J. N. D. Kelly, Early Christian Creeds, p. 297. 167 J. N. D. Kelly, Early Christian Creeds, pp. 303-305. 166 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 28 ideas. Also of interest is how they argue for the unity and distinction of the Persons. It should be noted that given that many of the debates over Eunomian ideas were related to Eunomius’s ‘naturalist’ understanding of ‘names’, which will be explained below, some of these debates also were over terminology to some extent. Basil’s Against Eunomius and Gregory’s orations will be used on their own merit, although with the cautions Vaggione advises. Basil’s Against Eunomius is a good source for understanding his early trinitarian thinking,168 and Gregory’s orations are the sources for understanding Gregory’s trinitarian thinking.169 Eunomius’s first apology, which is dated to 360-361, just before Basil started his rebuttal,170 also is used here. Vaggione says that Eunomius wrote his second apology in ‘intervals’ beginning in 378.171 So Gregory would have been responding to Eunomian ideas in his orations around the time Eunomius was writing his response to Basil’s earlier Against Eunomius. Some of Eunomius’s beliefs were introduced above, especially that he thought that God was Unbegotten (agennétos), and the Son, who was begotten (gennéthenta) and also monogenés, was different in substance (heteroousios) from God, ideas which have a legacy in Arius’s beliefs from earlier in the fourth century.172 Examined here will be Eunomius’s belief that the substances of the Father and Son were designated by their names, and could not be the same, because Eunomius held a ‘naturalist position’ in ‘names theory’.173 Also examined are Eunomius’s related ideas about the Holy Spirit. Of most significance is how Basil and Gregory of Nazianzus respond, in their arguments against Eunomius’s ideas. Eunomius’s preferred names, Unbegotten and Begotten or Only-begotten, designated, for him, not only whether or how the Father and Son had come into being, but also their 168 See Ayres and Radde-Gallwitz, p. 464. See Beeley, ‘Divine Causality’, pp. 204-211. 170 Vaggione, pp. 5-9. 171 Vaggione, p. 85. 172 See R. Williams, Arius, pp. 97-99; R. P. C. Hanson, The Search, p. 6; Young and Teal, pp. 43, 45, 47; Pelikan, The Christian Tradition, I, pp. 194-195. 173 As described by DelCogliano and Toom, a ‘naturalist position’ held that names reveal the nature of objects designated, and a ‘conventionalist’ position that names are not necessarily related to the nature of what they name. Mark DelCogliano, Basil of Caesarea’s Anti-Eunomian Theory of Names: Christian Theology and Late-Antique Philosophy in the Fourth Century Trinitarian Controversy, Supplements to Vigiliae Christianae, 103, ed. by J. den Boeft and others (Leiden: Brill, 2010), pp. 25-27, 32; Tarmo Toom, ‘Hilary of Poitiers’ De Trinitate and the Name(s) of God’, Vigiliae Christianae, 64, (2010), 456-479 (pp. 456-457, 460-461, 471, 479 FN 86). 169 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 29 substance.174 For Eunomius, ‘Unbegotten’ was not an attribute, but a name, for God, and this meant that being unbegotten or unoriginate was God’s substance. Eunomius believed, similarly, according to Gregory of Nazianzus, that the Son had to be ‘of a different substance’ from the Father, because the Son was called ‘begotten’, which designated the Son’s substance as not being unoriginate, and hence not the same as God’s substance.175 For Eunomius, there also was no possibility of there being more than one unoriginate,176 so, again, the Son’s substance could not be the same as the Father’s. Basil, in his Against Eunomius, argues against a related Eunomian idea that ‘ “the unbegotten has no comparison with the begotten” ’, because this idea set up opposition between ‘the very substance’ of the Father and Son.177 Basil counters that ‘whatever one may assign to the Father as the formula of his being, the very same also applies to the Son’, and ‘this is how divinity is one’, and he gives the example of the Father and OnlyBegotten sharing ‘light’ as their substance, an idea that could come from the 325 creed or prologue to John (John 1. 4-5).178 Basil also argues on behalf of the consubstantiality of the Son with the Father in the context of arguing on behalf of their co-eternity. He rebuts Eunomius’s claim that there is a temporal ‘order’ of first and second, between the Unbegotten and Only-Begotten, and says it would be impossible for ‘the God of the universe’ to be without ‘his image who has radiated light non-temporally’.179 Basil says here that both God and the image are eternal, and also that the Son or the image is ‘of the same substance’ with God.180 He bases his arguments on Heb. 1. 3, as can be seen when he says the Son is called ‘the radiance’ and ‘the character of his subsistence’ so that ‘we may learn that he is of the same substance’.181 Here Basil is drawing on scripture as a source for discussing the ontological question 174 See Ayres and Radde-Gallwitz, p. 466. Gregory of Nazianzus, ‘The Third Theological Oration’, 16, p. 83. 176 Eunomius, ‘Apology’, 10, pp. 46-47; Michel René Barnes, ‘Eunomius of Cyzicus and Gregory of Nyssa: Two Traditions of Transcendent Causality’, Vigiliae Christianae, 52, no. 1 (1998), 59-87 (p. 62). 177 Basil of Caesarea, Against Eunomius, 1.18, pp. 118-119. 178 Basil of Caesarea, Against Eunomius, 1.19, p. 120; J. N. D. Kelly, Early Christian Creeds, p. 215. 179 Basil of Caesarea, Against Eunomius, 1.20, p. 120. 180 Basil of Caesarea, Against Eunomius, 1.20, p. 120. 181 While this is said by DelCogliano and Radde-Gallwitz to be the only place in Against Eunomius where Basil uses homoousios for the Son, it should be said that Heb. 1. 3 uses ‘hupostaseōs’. Basil of Caesarea, Against Eunomius, 1.20, p. 120; DelCogliano and Radde-Gallwitz, p. 120 FN 112. 175 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 30 of the Son and Father being of the same substance, but Eunomius had drawn on scripture to argue the opposite view: that the image could not be of the same ‘essence of God’.182 Eunomius quotes the ‘blessed Paul’ and Col. 1. 15-16 (‘ “He is the image of the invisible God, the first-born of all creation, because in him all things were created…” ’), in order to, as Eunomius says, ‘safeguard the real meaning of the word “image” ’.183 Eunomius is arguing here that the Son ‘preserves his similarity to the Father’ because the Son is the ‘image’ of God, and that the idea of ‘image’ refers back to God’s ‘will’, which Eunomius understands as an ‘action’, not to God’s ‘essence’.184 Eunomius then argues that ‘the word “image” ’ is used ‘not as comparing the only-begotten Son and first-born to the Father, for the designation “Son” makes his own essence clear, while that of “Father” manifests the action of the one who begot him’.185 So here, among his other arguments, Eunomius is saying the Son and Father have different essences, because of being called ‘Son’ and ‘Father’, and because of the action of the Father having begotten the Son. His arguments also are based on his understanding of what the word ‘image’ designates with respect to substance or essence. The debate between Basil and Eunomius over whether an image is the same substance as what it images does not appear to be conclusively won on ontological grounds, given that scriptural sources were cited as justification. However, later orthodox / catholic authors draw on Heb. 1. 3 and the concept of ‘image’ to support the belief that the Son is of the same substance as the Father. These authors include Gregory of Nazianzus,186 and Ambrose, in a hexaemeral sermon,187 although the latter may be dependent on Basil. Basil expresses ideas about what ‘Son’ and ‘Father’ mean, and about unity and distinction within the Godhead, in his arguments against Eunomius. According to Basil, Eunomius called the Only-begotten ‘something begotten and something made’.188 Basil argues that it does not make sense ‘to designate the Maker of the universe as “something Eunomius, ‘Apology’, 24, p. 65. Eunomius, ‘Apology’, 24, p. 65. 184 Eunomius, ‘Apology’, 24, p. 65. 185 Eunomius, ‘Apology’, 24, p. 67. 186 Gregory of Nazianzus, ‘The Fourth Theological Oration’, 20, p. 110. 187 Ambrose, ‘The Six Days of Creation’, in Saint Ambrose: Hexameron, Paradise, and Cain and Abel, trans. and with an introduction by John J. Savage, FOTC, 42 (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1961), 3-283 (I, 5, 18-19, p. 17). 188 Basil of Caesarea, Against Eunomius, 2.1, p. 131. 182 183 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 31 made” ’, and it is illogical to think that different names necessarily suggest differences in substance.189 He argues, instead, that the names Father and Son ‘do not communicate substance but instead are revelatory of the distinguishing marks’ (tōn idiōmatōn),190 and ‘begotten and unbegotten’ are ‘distinctive features that enable identification and are observed in the substance’.191 These names differentiate what is common, without ‘sunder[ing] the substance’s sameness in nature’.192 Here Basil is describing his understanding of how the Son and Father can be of the same substance, but have distinctive features, and arguing that the names Son and Father do not refer to substance. Basil’s arguments could be evidence for a position put forth by Michel Barnes about a change that he argues took place in the second half of the fourth century, leading to the Father-Son relationship not being understood as being about their unity of substance, but about their distinctions, which were related to the principle of causation.193 Barnes, in these arguments, is making subtle distinctions between different decades in the second half of the fourth century.194 He argues that what he calls ‘Pro-Nicene’ theology, which he believes started later in the second half of the fourth century, as distinct from ‘Neo-Nicene’ theology, which he believes began in the 350s, no longer posited that the Father-Son relationship signified unity of substance, based on the belief that an offspring must have the same nature as the parent.195 Examples of such beliefs about the Father and Son being of the same nature, because the Son is the son of a father, are represented in some of the writings of Athanasius examined That ‘Maker of the universe’ (‘ton poiétén tōn holōn’) refers to the Son will be discussed. Basil of Caesarea, Against Eunomius, 2.3-2.4, p. 134; Thesaurus Linguae Graecae, 2040.019, line 27. 190 Basil of Caesarea, Against Eunomius, 2.3-2.5, pp. 134-136; DelCogliano and Radde-Gallwitz, p. 136, FN 33. 191 Basil of Caesarea, Against Eunomius, 2.28, p. 174. 192 Basil of Caesarea, Against Eunomius, 2.28, p. 174, also 2.29, pp. 175-176. 193 Michel René Barnes, ‘Divine Unity and the Divided Self: Gregory of Nyssa’s Trinitarian Theology in its Psychological Context’, Modern Theology, 18, no. 4 (2002), 475-496 (pp. 383384); M. Barnes, ‘De Trinitate VI and VII’, p. 196 FN 19; see also Ayres, Nicaea and its Legacy, pp. 236, 239-240. 194 Barnes’s colleague, Lewis Ayres, does not agree with Barnes on making these fine distinctions between the decades, and Ayres views ‘pro-Nicene theologies’ as beginning in the 360s. Ayres, Nicaea and its Legacy, pp. 236, 239-240. 195 M. Barnes, ‘Divine Unity and the Divided Self’, pp. 383-384; M. Barnes, ‘De Trinitate VI and VII’, p. 196 FN 19. 189 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 32 above, some of which are from the 350s.196 By contrast, Barnes argues that Gregory of Nyssa relies on whether one Person is the Cause, and another is ‘ “of the Cause” ’, as the basis for distinguishing between the hypostases of the Father and Son, and that Gregory does not use the Father-Son relationship to argue for their unity of substance.197 Basil’s arguments could support Barnes’s argument that this position was common after the 350s. However, Basil is not consistent. His argument about the ‘distinguishing marks’ or ‘distinctive features’ supports Barnes’s position, but his statement that ‘whatever one may assign to the Father as the formula of his being, the very same also applies to the Son’, does argue for Father and Son being of the same substance. Here it is relevant that Ayres, who takes issue with Barnes’s distinctions between Neo-Nicene and Pro-Nicene theologies, says, in commenting on Barnes’s arguments, that ‘pro-Nicene authors often incorporate earlier arguments alongside more fully developed pro-Nicene arguments’.198 Basil ends Against Eunomius by discussing the Spirit, and arguing against Eunomius’s belief that the Spirit did not have the same nature as the Father.199 Eunomius had argued that the Spirit is ‘third in nature’. 200 Eunomius draws on 1 Cor. 8. 6 and John 1. 3 to justify his conviction that the ‘Only-begotten God is not to be compared either with the one who begot him or with the Holy Spirit who was made through him, for he is less than the one in being a “thing made”, and greater than the other in being a maker’.201 So while Eunomius held a somewhat orthodox / catholic view about the role of the ‘Only-begotten’ in creation, he deviates by including the Spirit among the things ‘ made “through him” ’, which might represent the influence of Origen, who also drew on John 1. 3 to argue that the Spirit had been created.202 Moreover, this use of John 1. 3 to argue for the creation of the Spirit was an issue in both East and West in the second half of the fourth century. It is See Michel René Barnes, ‘Rereading Augustine’s Theology of the Trinity’, in The Trinity: An Interdisciplinary Symposium on the Trinity, ed. by Stephen T. Davis, Daniel Kendall, and Gerald O’Collins (New York: Oxford University Press, 1999; repr. 2004), pp. 145-176 (p. 156 FN 19). 197 M. Barnes, ‘Divine Unity and the Divided Self’, pp. 383-384. 198 Ayres, Nicaea and its Legacy, p. 236 FN 51. 199 Basil of Caesarea, Against Eunomius, 3, pp. 185-196; Eunomius, ‘Apology’, 25-27, pp. 66-73. 200 Eunomius, ‘Apology’, 25, p. 67; Basil of Caesarea, Against Eunomius, 3.1, p. 185. 201 Eunomius, ‘Apology’, 26, pp. 69, 71; see also Basil of Caesarea, Against Eunomius, 3.7, pp. 194-196; Gregory of Nyssa, Against Eunomius, Book I, 16. 202 Eunomius, ‘Apology’, 26, p. 71; Origen, Commentary on the Gospel According to John, Books 1-10, trans. by Ronald E. Heine, FOTC, 80, ed. by Thomas P. Halton and others (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1989), Book 2, 70-76, pp. 112-114. 196 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 33 alluded to by Gregory of Nazianzus in a 380 oration,203 and by Ambrose, in his 381 The Holy Spirit, where Ambrose is writing against ‘Macedonians’.204 Basil’s response to Eunomius does not reflect a mature trinitarian theology. He agrees with Eunomius that the Spirit is ‘below the Son in both rank and dignity’, although Basil takes issue with the Spirit’s being ‘of a foreign nature’.205 He also addresses the question of which side of ‘two realities’ the Spirit is on, ‘divinity’ or ‘creation’, and whether the Spirit has ‘a nature that is third and foreign’ to the nature of the Father and Son.206 He argues based on the names given to the Spirit, including ‘Holy’ and ‘Spirit’, which he says the Spirit shares ‘in common’ with Father and Son, and he claims that ‘the communion of names does not communicate the Spirit’s estrangement of nature, but rather his affinity with the Father and the Son’.207 However, these arguments do not address the question of whether or how the Spirit came into being. That his trinitarian thinking is not fully worked out here, including how the unity and distinctions of the Persons are held together, can be seen when he says: ‘Indeed, the account of singleness will be preserved in the Trinity in this way, by confessing one Father and one Son and one Holy Spirit’.208 Gregory of Nazianzus, in his orations, delivered fifteen years or more after Basil wrote Against Eunomius, responds to Eunomius’s arguments about how the names of the Father and Son, or Unbegotten and Begotten, say something about their substance. In his third theological oration, Gregory argues against the Eunomian belief that when one calls God or the Father ‘unbegotten’ or ‘unoriginate’, one says something about ‘God’s substance or activity’, which says something about the Son.209 Gregory’s rebuttal is that ‘Father’ designates the relationship between Father and Son, and the names Father and Son indicate ‘kindred and affinity’ and ‘sameness of stock, or parent and offspring’, as with human Gregory of Nazianzus, ‘The Fifth Theological Oration’, 12, p. 126. On the dating and Ambrose’s writing against the Macedonians in the West, see Deferrari. Ambrose, The Holy Spirit, in Saint Ambrose: Theological and Dogmatic Works, trans. and with an introduction by Roy J. Deferrari, FOTC: A New Translation, 44 (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1963; first paperback repr. 2002), Books I-III, pp. 35-214 (1, 2, 2731, pp. 46-48); Deferrari, pp. xvii, 31-32. 205 Basil of Caesarea, Against Eunomius, 3.1, p. 186. 206 Basil of Caesarea, Against Eunomius, 3.2-3.3, pp. 187-189. 207 Basil of Caesarea, Against Eunomius, 3.3, p. 189. 208 Basil of Caesarea, Against Eunomius, 3.6, p. 194. 209 Gregory of Nazianzus, ‘The Third Theological Oration’, 16, pp. 83-84. 203 204 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 34 beings.210 This is similar to Gregory’s saying, earlier, that the designations ‘begetter and begotten’ must be the same because ‘it is in the nature of an offspring to have a nature identical with its parent’s’.211 His argument, which combines idea about begetting and nature, offers evidence that the names Father and Son still said something about the nature of the Son in the early 380s, at least for Gregory of Nazianzus, if not Gregory of Nyssa. Gregory continues by arguing that even if ‘Father’ did refer to substance, this idea ‘will bring in the Son along with it, not alienate him’.212 This is a subtle argument for the unity of substance between Son and Father. Gregory is explicit when he says that if ‘Father’ is taken to refer to an activity or to mean ‘producer’, with the Son his production, the other option he says his opponents offered, the Father will have actively produced the ‘consubstantiality’ between the Son and Father.213 Gregory speaks of the Spirit as ‘consubstantial’ with God in his fifth theological oration, and says there is ‘one supreme nature’, even though there is a ‘Trinity’ of Father, Son, and Spirit.214 He argues that the ‘facts’ of not being begotten, being begotten, and proceeding ‘safeguard the distinctiveness of the three hypostases within the single nature and quality of the Godhead’.215 These words illustrate the maturity of his trinitarian thinking, with the Spirit being consubstantial and coequal with the Father and Son. His words also illustrate that all Persons are recognised as distinct, if only because of how they came into being, while they all are a single nature in the Godhead. However, while ‘being begotten’ and ‘proceeding’ specify relationships of origin, these terms do not suggest what begetting and proceeding mean, which Gregory admits in another oration is a mystery.216 So he, too, like Basil and Athanasius, leaves this mystery ‘on the table’. Gregory, in Oration 42, written after his resignation as president of the 381 Council of Constantinople,217 can be seen as still addressing Eunomian ideas and speaking about nature, while offering statements that reflect his own trinitarian theology. He writes: That which is without beginning, and the beginning, and that which is with the Gregory of Nazianzus, ‘The Third Theological Oration’, 16, pp. 83-84. Gregory of Nazianzus, ‘The Third Theological Oration’, 10, p. 78. 212 Gregory of Nazianzus, ‘The Third Theological Oration’, 16, p. 84. 213 Gregory of Nazianzus, ‘The Third Theological Oration’, 16, pp. 83-84. 214 Gregory of Nazianzus, ‘The Fifth Theological Oration’, 10, pp. 123-124. 215 Gregory of Nazianzus, ‘The Fifth Theological Oration’, 9, p. 123. 216 Gregory of Nazianzus, ‘The Fifth Theological Oration’, pp. 117-147 (8, p. 122). 217 McGuckin, St Gregory of Nazianzus, pp. 361-366; Beeley, Gregory of Nazianzus, pp. 54-58. 210 211 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 35 beginning – these are one God. Neither lack of beginning, nor lack of generation, constitutes the nature of that which has no beginning: for an entity’s nature is never constituted by what it is not, but by what it is; it is defined by positing what it is, not by removing what it is not. The beginning is not separated, by virtue of its being a beginning, from that which has no beginning: for beginning is not the nature of the former, nor is lack of beginning the nature of the latter. These are attributes of the nature, not the nature itself. … [T]he unoriginate has the name of Father; the originate has the name of Son; that which is with the originate is called the Holy Spirit. But these three have the same nature, namely, Godhead. The Father is the principle of unity; for from him the other two derive their being, and in him they are drawn together: not so as to be fused together, but so as to cohere. … [U]nity properly belongs to those who have a single nature and whose essential being is the same.218 As with his rebuttal of Eunomian ideas about names, here Gregory argues that the Son is not of a different nature from the Father, even though the Son is called ‘Beginning’ (which may reflect the influence of Origen’s interpretations of Gen. 1. 1 and John 1. 1), and the Father ‘without beginning’. His point, though, is that the Father’s being unbegotten does not say something about His nature, but is an ‘attribute’ of his nature, because it speaks of what He is not, not what He is. Here, Gregory’s understanding of ‘attribute’ may be similar to Basil’s earlier understanding of ‘distinguishing marks’ or ‘distinctive features’. What is noteworthy is that Gregory is arguing about the unity of the nature of all three Persons, while arguing, by contrast with Eunomian ideas, that the Father’s nature cannot be defined by something lacking, in this case a lack of beginning or generation. The same nature the Persons share is something that is, which, for Gregory, is ‘Godhead’. This nature is, moreover, the Father’s nature, ‘for from him the other two derive their being’. That Gregory argues these points in the early 380s does offer some evidence against Barnes’s argument that pro-Nicene theologies later in the second half of the fourth century did not posit that the Father-Son relationship signified unity of substance, based on the assumption that an offspring must have the same nature as the parent. John McGuckin does say that Gregory’s arguments here are not typical for him, and that Gregory ‘usually argues that ingeneracy describes only relationship, not nature’, thus not saying anything about the Son’s divine nature, but about the Son’s person or hypostasis.219 One might say, however, based on Gregory’s comments in the excerpt from Oration This excerpt from Gregory of Nazianzus’s Oration 42.15 is taken from Bettenson’s translation, which is reprinted by McGuckin. Bettenson, The Later Christian Fathers, pp. 119-120; McGuckin, We Believe in One Lord Jesus Christ, ACD, 2, ed. by Oden, p. 35. 219 McGuckin, We Believe in One Lord Jesus Christ, ACD, 2, ed. by Oden, p. 35 FN 57. 218 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 36 42 and the discussions above, that, for Gregory, the use of ‘uncaused’ for the Father does not function as the criterion of the nature of the Father, as it did for Eunomius. It could not serve as the criterion for Gregory, because it is about something that is not, about a lack of a cause, not something it is. At the same time, Gregory may be seen as saying that whether one uses the names Father, Son, and Holy Spirit, or names that specify whether they were originated, one is speaking of attributes of nature, not about the nature itself. So he is, in this way, arguing against the connection between names and essence, and he does so by arguing for both unity and distinction within the Godhead, including unity of nature. 2.2.4 Principles of unity and distinction and the immanent and economic Trinity Gregory was delivering his orations around the time that Eunomius and Heterousians were losing battles over Eunomius’s position that the Son and Spirit could not be of the same substance or nature as God, the Unbegotten. The creed attributed to the 381 Council of Constantinople does not use ‘homoousios’ in speaking of the Spirit and Father, but the Spirit is called ‘the Lord and life-giver’.220 In the next year, however, a letter was written in Constantinople and sent to Pope Damasus and bishops in the West, and the letter says that the Spirit is of the same substance as the Father and Son, and condemns positions held by Eunomians and others.221 The letter says that, according to the faith of Nicaea, ‘ “there is one Godhead (theotés), Power (dunamis), and Substance (ousia) of the Father and of the Son and of the Holy Spirit; the dignity being equal, and the majesty being equal in three perfect hypostases, i.e. three perfect persons (prosōpa).” ’ It condemns ‘ “the blasphemy of the Eunomians, of the Arians, and of the Pneumatomachi” ’, which ‘ “divides the substance (ousia), the nature (phusis), and the godhead (theotés), and superimposes onto the uncreated consubstantial and coeternal Trinity a separate nature, created, and of a different substance.” ’222 It has been observed that this letter does not use the actual expression ‘ “one ousia, three hypostaseis” ’, which often is attributed to the Cappadocians, even though it rarely 220 The Greek and English words are from J. N. D. Kelly, Early Christian Creeds, pp. 297-298. The citations are from Ayres’s translation. Ayres, Nicaea and its Legacy, p. 258; Theodoret, The Ecclesiastical History of Theodoret, trans. by Blomfield Jackson, in Theodoret, Jerome, Gennadius, Rufinus: Historical Writings, Etc., NPNF, 2nd series, 3, ed. by Philip Schaff and Henry Wace (1892; Oak Harbor: Logos Research Systems, 1997 [on CD-ROM]), Book V, ch. IX. 222 Ayres, Nicaea and its Legacy, p. 258. 221 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 37 appears in their writings.223 It also has been said that being of one substance is only one of the ways in which the letter says the Father, Son, and Spirit are ‘one’: they also are one Godhead and one power.224 One can see, though, that the letter does address the principle of consubstantiality, stating it in different ways: there is one ousia, neither the ousia nor the nature is divided, the Trinity is the ‘uncreated consubstantial and coeternal Trinity’. The letter also implies that that Son and Spirit could not have been created, on the grounds that if they were, the substance would be divided. Gregory of Nazianzus also offers a summary of trinitarian principles in his Oration 20, which he may have given in 379 or 380.225 His principles are helpful for the discussions here, because, in stating how ‘both to maintain the oneness of God and to confess three individual entities, or Persons, each with his distinctive property’,226 he offers principles that apply to both the immanent and economic Trinity. Gregory summarises some of his principles of unity when he writes: The oneness of God would … be maintained if both Son and Spirit are causally related to him alone without being merged or fused into him and if they all share one and the same divine movement and purpose [kinéma te kai bouléma] … and are identical in 223 This is pointed out by Lienhard. Hildebrand says Basil never uses the phrase, although he worked out many of the ideas. Beeley and Toom cite Gregory of Nazianzus’s use of the phrase in his Oration 21, which Beeley dates to 380. Joseph T. Lienhard, ‘Ousia and Hypostasis: The Cappadocian Settlement and the Theology of “One Hypostasis” ’, in The Trinity: An Interdisciplinary Symposium on the Trinity, ed. by Stephen T. Davis, Daniel Kendall, and Gerald O’Collins (New York: Oxford University Press, 1999; repr. 2004), pp. 99-121 (pp. 99-100, 120); Stephen M. Hildebrand, The Trinitarian Theology of Basil of Caesarea: A Synthesis of Greek Thought and Biblical Truth (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2007), p. 99; Beeley, Gregory of Nazianzus, pp. 277-279; Toom, Classical Trinitarian Theology, pp. 135-136; Gregory Nazianzus, ‘Oration 21: On the Great Athanasius, Bishop of Alexandria’, trans. by Charles Gordon Browne and James Edward Swallow, in S. Cyril of Jerusalem, S. Gregory Nazianzen, NPNF, 2nd series, 7, ed. by P. Schaff and H. Wace (1894; Oak Harbor: Logos Research Systems, 1997 [on CD-ROM]) (Oration 21, 35). 224 See Lienhard. Barnes argues that belief that the Persons are of one power (as well as of one substance), as evidenced in the unity of works, is characteristic of Latin thinking, beginning with Tertullian. Lienhard, ‘Ousia and Hypostasis’, p. 100; M. Barnes, ‘Latin trinitarian theology’. 225 Vinson says the dating is uncertain but could be 380, and that this oration is linked with Gregory’s theological orations. Beeley gives the date as 379. Gregory of Nazianzus, ‘Oration 20: On Theology and the Office of Bishops’, in St. Gregory of Nazianzus: Select Orations, trans. and with an introduction by Martha Vinson, FOTC, 107 (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2003), pp. 107-116 (7, p. 111); Martha Vinson, translation and introduction, St. Gregory of Nazianzus: Select Orations, by Gregory of Nazianzus, FOTC, 107 (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2003), p. 107 FN 1; Beeley, Gregory of Nazianzus, p. 35. 226 Gregory of Nazianzus, ‘Oration 20’, 6, p. 111. Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 38 essence [tés ousias tautotéta].227 Here, unity is maintained within the Godhead because of the ‘causal’ relations that exist between the Father, who is their cause, and the Son and Spirit, and all three are the same in essence. These principles speak of relations of origin and consubstantiality, and are related to the immanent Trinity. Unity also is maintained by the three being one in ‘divine movement and purpose’. This illustrates the economic principle of ‘unity of operations’, assuming the movement and purpose expresses itself in external acts. (The expression ‘unity of operations’ is used here because it is compatible with terminology used by Basil and Gregory of Nyssa, and does not entail all the principles Ayres associates with ‘inseparable operation’.228) For Gregory, distinctions among the Persons are posited by preserving the ‘individual properties’ (idiotétes) of the ‘three individually existing entities’ (treis hupostaseis), which includes avoiding thinking of them as ‘fusing or dissolving or mingling’, and accepting that the Father is ‘both source and without source’ (kai anarchou, kai archés), and the Son, who is not without source, is ‘the source of all things’ (archés de tōn holōn).229 He says he is using ‘the term’ source here ‘in the sense of causal agent, fount, and eternal light’.230 The idea that the Father is the arché (beginning, origin, principle, source, first cause) or aitia (cause) of the Son and Spirit is attributed to Cappadocian thinking.231 The concept of causation (from aitia) can come from Aristotle’s ideas about the four causes of things,232 and can be used with meanings related to arché, including source or origin.233 Gregory’s Gregory of Nazianzus, ‘Oration 20’, 7, p. 111; Thesaurus Linguae Graecae. For Ayres, the principle of ‘inseparable operations’ is one of three principles of ‘pro-Nicene’ theologies, and requires ‘clear’ statements that the Persons ‘work inseparably’, even if acts are attributed to one Person through ‘appropriation.’ The other two principles are that they offer ‘clear’ expressions of ‘the person and nature distinction’, and of ‘the eternal generation of the Son’ occurring ‘within the unitary and incomprehensible divine being’. Ayres sees a close connection between the principles of inseparable operations, appropriations, and divine simplicity. Ayres, Nicaea and its Legacy, pp. 236, 278-282, 286-288, 296-300. 229 Gregory of Nazianzus, ‘Oration 20’, 7, pp. 111-112; Thesaurus Linguae Graecae. 230 Gregory of Nazianzus, ‘Oration 20’, 7, pp. 111-112. 231 Lampe, pp. 54, 234-235. 232 Aristotle’s four causes are the material, formal, efficient, and final causes. R. J. Hankinson, ‘Philosophy of Science’, in The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle, Jonathan Barnes, ed. (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1995; 11th printing 2006), pp. 109-139 (pp. 120-121). 233 Van Winden says, in discussing ‘the mutual influence’ of arché and aitia and Basil’s use of four archai instead of four aitia, that a study of the concepts of arché and aitia would be welcome. J. C. M. Van Winden, ‘In the Beginning: Some Observations on the Patristic Interpretations of Gen. 1, 227 228 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 39 use of ‘source’ for the Son as ‘source’ of ‘all things’ may represent a mix of Aristotelian ideas and terminology, and words and ideas from John 1. 3. In looking at the economic acts of the Persons in creation, it is relevant that aitia or cause can be used of both the Father and Son in Patristic writings, as can arché, when it is intended to mean ‘First Cause’ or ‘Creator’ of creation.234 Gregory’s use of ‘source’ or ‘archés’ for Father and Son is similar. However, this use of the same word for Father and Son with respect to economic acts of creation can cause confusion. Similar confusion can arise when Athanasius and Basil write of both Father and Son as ‘Creator’ or ‘Maker’, as illustrated above and here. The questions to be discussed here are whether speaking of both Father and Son as source, Creator, or Maker could suggest, inadvertently, that there are two first principles, and whether this language is consistent with scripture (e.g., John 1. 3), Nicene credal language, and the principle of the unity of operations. Athanasius, as seen above, refers to the Son as ‘Creator like the Father’.235 The letter attributed to him uses ‘Artificer and Maker [démiourgos and poiétés]’ to speak of the Son or Word, in response to the 359 Council of Ariminum having called the Son or Word ‘a creature and one of the things that are made’.236 Similarly, Basil, also as noted earlier, uses ‘Maker of the universe’ [‘ton poiétén tōn holōn’] for the Son, in response to Eunomius’s having said that the Son was ‘something made’.237 Thus, ‘Maker’ is used at times for the Son or Word in response to charges made by others, who called him something ‘made’. This might be an appropriate rebuttal, perhaps a good ‘turn’ on words. One can ask, however, whether it is acceptable for the Son to be called ‘Creator’ or ‘Maker’. The Father is known as Creator or Maker, and the 325 and 381 creeds call Him the ‘maker’ of all things, and the Son the one ‘through whom’ all things came into being (or existence).238 If both Father and Son are ‘Creator’ or ‘Maker’, without the use of ‘through whom’ terminology for the Son, this could be construed as setting up two first 1’, in Arche: A Collection of Patristic Studies by J. C. M. Van Winden, J. Den Boeft and D. T. Runia, eds., Supplements to Vigiliae Christianae, 41, ed. by J. den Boeft and others (Leiden: Brill, 1997), pp. 61-77 (pp. 61, 64) (first publ. in Vigiliae Christianae, 17 [1963], pp. 105-121). 234 Lampe, pp. 54, 234-235. 235 Athanasius, ‘Letters to Serapion’, 2.13.4-2.14.1, pp. 123-124. 236 Athanasius, ‘To the Bishops of Africa’, 4; Thesaurus Linguae Graecae. 237 See Basil of Caesarea, Against Eunomius, 2.3-2.4, p. 134; Thesaurus Linguae Graecae, 2040.019, line 27. 238 On the creeds, see J. N. D. Kelly, Early Christian Creeds, pp. 215-216, 297. Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 40 principles or causes of creation, even two Creator Gods. This clearly was not the intention of Athanasius or Basil, but it does suggest inconsistencies in terminology and thinking. By contrast, the use of ‘through whom’ language for the Son in speaking of his role in creation, as in the creeds and John 1. 3, distinguishes his role from the Father’s. This type of language also is reflected in the principle of unity of operations, as it is written of by Basil, in his On the Holy Spirit, and by Gregory of Nyssa. Examples from Basil’s work will be offered below, so Gregory of Nyssa’s words will be given here: But in the case of the Divine nature we do not similarly learn that the Father does anything by Himself in which the Son does not work conjointly, or again that the Son has any special operation apart from the Holy Spirit; but every operation which extends from God to the Creation ... has its origin from the Father, and proceeds through the Son, and is perfected in the Holy Spirit.239 Gregory of Nazianzus’s understanding of ‘source’ as ‘causal agent’ may be sufficient to justify seeing both Father and Son as source or causal agent for creation.240 Gregory can be seen as distinguishing between the Father as source or causal agent of the Son and Spirit within the Godhead, and the Son’s role as source or causal agent of ‘all things’ that are created. Thus, the Father’s role as ultimate source of all is preserved. However, Gregory does not use the ‘through whom’ language of the creeds, John 1. 3, or principle of unity of operations for the Son’s role, but rather is drawing on other ideas and terminology. 2.3 Case study: the immanent and economic Trinity in Basil’s hexaemeral homilies With this major section, attention moves to the third primary question, ‘how are the Persons said to be involved in acts of creation in writings about creation, and what is said about relations within the Godhead and between God and creation?’, again a question related to both the immanent and economic Trinity. Basil’s hexaemeral homilies will be used in an extended case study for these discussions. The dating of these homilies is unknown, but many scholars believe Basil may have delivered them in 377 or 378, after he wrote On the Holy Spirit and not long before his death, which, if true, would mean these Italics added. Gregory of Nyssa, ‘On “Not Three Gods”’, trans. by William Moore and Henry Austin Wilson, in Gregory of Nyssa: Dogmatic Treatises, Etc., NPNF, 2nd series, 5, ed. by P. Schaff and H. Wace (1893; Oak Harbor: Logos Research Systems, 1997 [on CD-ROM]). 240 Gregory of Nazianzus, ‘Oration 20’, 7, p. 112. 239 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 41 homilies would reflect his mature thinking.241 It also would mean that Basil was delivering his homilies only two or three years before Gregory’s orations. However, one clue will be offered here which might suggest that the homilies are earlier than On the Holy Spirit. Basil’s hexaemeral homilies, as the name indicates, are on the first six days of creation according to Gen. 1, and thus are about creation, although they offer only a few insights about Basil’s trinitarian thinking. A few possibilities for why this is so can be offered, but these are reasoned conjectures. On the other hand, it will be shown that his homilies do offer more examples of the Son working in creation than often thought.242 It also will be seen that he offers an example of relations that can develop between people and God, because of what people see in, and can infer from, creation. One reason for Basil’s homilies not reflecting many trinitarian ideas may be that while principles of the doctrine of creation had influenced the development of the doctrine of the Trinity in the second half of the fourth century, the reciprocal influence of trinitarian principles on the doctrine of creation had not occurred. This possibility will be evaluated in the next chapters, in looking at Augustine’s writings about creation and the Trinity. One also could conjecture that there may have been differences between how Basil expressed his ideas in homilies, which were used in pastoral settings, and in dogmatic, theological, or polemical works, like Against Eunomius. Basil did deliver his hexaemeral homilies to people from a variety of educational levels and employment, and he liked to use homilies to encourage people to adopt moral ideas or behavior.243 In his hexaemeral homilies, Basil uses examples from nature to support his moral arguments, and these examples would be ‘familiar’ to people in ‘their daily life’, as Agnes Way points out.244 Nonetheless, Basil’s hexaemeral homilies contain theological, scriptural, and philosophical 241 On the Holy Spirit is dated to the mid-370s. Hildebrand, On the Holy Spirit, pp. 20-21. Ayres and Radde-Gallwitz cite two places where Basil speaks of the roles of the Son (Homily 9.2) or Spirit (Homily 2.6) in creation. Similarly, Gunton says he ‘seems to overlook the role of the Son in creation’, and that he refers to the Spirit’s role twice, including in Homily 2.6. Ayres and Radde-Gallwitz, p. 463; Colin E. Gunton, The Triune Creator: A Historical and Systematic Study, Edinburgh Studies in Constructive Theology (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1998), p. 71. 243 One of Gregory of Nyssa’s defenses against criticisms of Basil’s homilies was that Basil was speaking to people in a church from mixed backgrounds, many of whom would not have understood complicated arguments. Basil of Caesarea, On the Hexaemeron, Homily 3, 1 pp. 37-38; Way, pp. x-xi; Gregory of Nyssa, Traité sur les six jours, 65A-65B. 244 Way, pp. xi, also xii-xiii; see also Ludlow, ‘Power and Dominion’, pp. 141, 145; Rousseau, Basil of Caesarea, pp. 323-324, 327, 331, 334-335. 242 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 42 ideas, even if not many trinitarian ideas, as will be seen, which suggests his audience may have been more sophisticated than supposed.245 Also hard to find in Basil’s hexaemeral homilies are examples of how the principle of the unity of operations works, as applied to acts of creation, and here one can compare this absence with what Basil says in his On the Holy Spirit. In his homilies, Basil does not explicitly show all three Persons working together, nor does he state, as in On the Holy Spirit, a belief in ‘the unity and indivisibility in every work of the Holy Spirit from the Father and the Son’.246 It is possible that the reasons have to do with the scriptures upon which Basil was drawing. The homilies are on an Old Testament book that would reveal only a few trinitarian examples, if read through Christian eyes. In On the Holy Spirit, by contrast, Basil’s examples of the unity of operations are about acts in the life of Jesus of Nazareth, as seen through Basil’s interpretation of New Testament scriptures. It also is possible that Basil’s omission in illustrating the principle of unity of operations in writing of creation in his homilies is a sign that the homilies are earlier than On the Holy Spirit. Here a few examples will be given of how Basil writes of the roles of the Son, Word, or monogenés in creation, and one about the Spirit’s role. The English translation cited here renders ‘monogenés’ as ‘only-begotten’, and Basil uses it as a title, as did Eunomius. Basil speaks of the Son in Homily 9.6, where he argues, based on the plural in ‘ “And God said, ‘Let us make mankind’ ” ’ and ‘ “In our image” ’, from Gen 1. 26, that ‘the Second Person was being indicated mystically, but not yet clearly revealed’.247 He says here (as in Against Eunomius248) that the Son is ‘the image of [the Father’s] substance’. That the Son is the image of God and God is seen when he suggests that the word ‘God’, in ‘ “And God created Man” ’, refers to the Father and Son, but the ‘singular form’ is used to avoid ‘the risk of polytheism’, which, although he does not say this, would have arisen if This perspective is similar to those held by Sandwell and Blowers. Sandwell argues that ‘moral and pastoral matters’ were not Basil’s primary interests in these homilies. She emphasises his theological and philosophical interests, and desire to explain something about the world, nature, and God. Sandwell, pp. 547-548, also 539, 550, 552, 557-558, 564; see also Blowers, pp. 126-129. 246 This statement is from 16, 38. In 16, 39, Basil writes of the Spirit being ‘joined to the very flesh of the Lord [Jesus Christ] as his anointing’ and says the Spirit is ‘inseparably present to him’. Basil is not writing here about creation, but rather about acts done by Jesus of Nazareth. St. Basil the Great, On the Holy Spirit, 16, 38, p. 70; 16, 39, p. 73. 247 The citations here and for the rest of the paragraph, unless noted, are from Basil of Caesarea, On the Hexaemeron, Homily 9, 6, pp. 147-149. 248 This was discussed above. See Basil of Caesarea, Against Eunomius, 1.20, p. 120. 245 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 43 the Father and Son were referred to as ‘two Gods’. Here he shows how the Father and Son worked in acts of creation, as ‘one’ God and ‘substance’, through the unity of operations. Basil also speaks of the role of the second Person when he says, ‘For, He Himself spoke, it is said, and He Himself made.’249 He does not explain this here, but in Homily 3, he says the reason it is said that after God gave a ‘command’ (e.g., ‘ “Let there be a firmament …” ’), that God made something (e.g., ‘God made the firmament’), is that ‘the Spirit’ is calling through the scripture about the involvement of the ‘Only-begotten’ (monogenés) in creation.250 He offers a similar example in Homily 6 and asks: ‘Who spoke and who made? Do you not notice in these words the double Person? Everywhere in history the teachings of theology are mystically interspersed.’251 Here Basil reads Old Testament scripture through at least a christological lens, while he is faithful to the text, which does say that God spoke and God made, opening a door for his discussion. Basil may have borrowed this example of the involvement of the first two Persons in creation from Origen, who gives similar examples in Commentary on John, where Origen discusses the meanings of ‘ “In the beginning was the Word” ’.252 Basil, unlike Origen, gives an explanation, saying that scripture, in showing God ‘commanding and speaking’, indicates ‘silently Him to whom He gives the command and to whom He speaks’, and thus ‘leads us on to the idea of the Only-begotten in a certain orderly way’.253 He says that scripture also shows God speaking and giving commands to suggest that ‘the divine will joined with the first impulse of His intelligence is the Word [Logos] of God’.254 Basil gives the Logos or Only-begotten a name for His role in creation, God’s ‘Co-worker’.255 Basil does not defend himself here, as he does in Homily 9, against a possible charge of speaking of ‘two Gods’ working together, which especially is at issue because of his use of ‘Co-worker’.256 Basil also does not address the implication of subordination of the one 249 Basil of Caesarea, On the Hexaemeron, Homily 9, 6, p. 147. Basil of Caesarea, On the Hexaemeron, Homily 3, 4, pp. 43-44; Thesaurus Linguae Graecae. 251 Basil of Caesarea, On the Hexaemeron, Homily 6, 2, p. 85. 252 Origen, Commentary on John, trans. and ed. by Joseph W. Trigg, in Origen, by Joseph W. Trigg, ECF, ed. by Carol Harrison (London and New York: Routledge, 1998; transferred to digital printing, 2005), pp. 104-149 (Book 1, 109-110, p. 123). 253 Basil of Caesarea, On the Hexaemeron, Homily 3, 2, pp. 38-39. 254 Basil of Caesarea, On the Hexaemeron, Homily 3, 2, p. 38. Thesaurus Linguae Graecae. 255 Basil of Caesarea, On the Hexaemeron, Homily 3, 2, pp. 38-39. 256 Gregory of Nazianzus says his opponents used the names Creator, Co-Worker, and Minister, which were reflective of differences in rank and ‘the qualities of the realities’ of the Persons. These 250 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 44 who is responding to the commands to the one giving them, although this concern might be mitigated by how he shows the two Persons sharing ‘their plans’ through thought. On the other hand, he does not address how the Word or Only-Begotten, who is ‘joined with’ God’s intelligence or will, and shares God’s thoughts, is distinct from God or not a part of God. This concern was raised in discussing Philo’s ideas about the Logos, but is a greater concern for trinitarian thinking, which needs to establish the unity and the distinction of the Persons, including in their economic acts. Basil seems to be interested in demonstrating that scripture does reveal the role of the Word or Only-begotten in creation,257 rather than in discussing some of the trinitarian issues that might be raised. In Homily 2, Basil argues against Platonist ideas, probably from the Timaeus, which suggest that God was a ‘Craftsman’ (ho technités258) who took over ‘matter’ and then ‘formed it by His own intelligence, reduced it to order, and thus through it gave visible things existence’.259 It is clear here that there are not two first principles, God and matter, because otherwise matter would be ‘considered worthy of the same superior ranking as the wise and all powerful and all-good Craftsman and Creator (démiourgō kai ktsité) of all things’, terminology reminiscent of Philo’s.260 Yet in what seems to be an obvious place to write of the role of the Word, Basil says God, ‘having cast about in His mind and resolved to bring into being things that did not exist, at one and the same time devised what sort of a world it should be and created the appropriate matter together with form’.261 His objective seems to have been to be clear that ‘matter and substance’ had not co-existed with God in the beginning, with God providing only the ‘plan and form’ for what was created, which would have suggested ‘the great God is not the author of the formation of all beings’.262 A role for the Holy Spirit in creation is discussed in Homily 2, where Basil gives an interpretation of Gen. 1. 2 borrowed from a ‘Syrian’.263 Basil says the use of the Syrian language, which was closer to the Hebrew, allowed the ‘Syrian’ to translate ‘ “was stirring above” ’ (which translates epephereto) as ‘ “warmed with fostering care” ’, like ‘a bird may have been Eunomians. Gregory of Nazianzus, ‘The Fifth Theological Oration’, 5, p. 120. 257 See Basil of Caesarea, On the Hexaemeron, Homily 3, 2, pp. 38-39. 258 From the Thesaurus Linguae Graecae. 259 Basil of Caesarea, On the Hexaemeron, Homily 2, 2, pp. 22-23; Way, p. 23 FN 2. 260 Basil of Caesarea, On the Hexaemeron, Homily 2, 2, pp. 22-23; Thesaurus Linguae Graecae. 261 Basil of Caesarea, On the Hexaemeron, Homily 2, 2, p. 23. 262 Basil of Caesarea, On the Hexaemeron, Homily 2, 2, pp. 23-24. 263 Basil of Caesarea, On the Hexaemeron, Homily 2, 6, pp. 30-31. Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 45 brooding on eggs’, an activity the Spirit undertook to prepare ‘the nature of the water for the generation of living beings’.264 This interpretation appears in Greek, perhaps Syrian, and Latin texts, as will be seen, and goes beyond Nicene theologies, which makes this example interesting and somewhat unusual. The identity of the ‘Syrian’ is not known, but is said not to be Ephrem, an older contemporary of Basil’s to whom a commentary on Genesis is attributed.265 Basil’s source often is said to be Diodore of Tarsus, who was drawing on Eusebius of Emesa’s writings on Gen. 1. 2.266 However, it has been argued, conversely, that Diodore could not have been Basil’s source.267 The ‘Syrian’ ideas Basil cites may stem from Eusebius’s writings on Gen. 1. 2, but it is not known how Basil learned of his ideas, and Eusebius’s writings are said not to be trinitarian.268 On the other hand, the ideas Basil cites do appear in a commentary on Genesis that is (wrongly) attributed to Ephrem the Syrian, even though Ephrem is known to have believed that Gen. 1. 2 is referring to the ‘wind’ (not the Holy Spirit), which is not a trinitarian interpretation.269 Even so, the ideas in this commentary 264 Basil of Caesarea, On the Hexaemeron, Homily 2, 6, pp. 30-31; Thesaurus Linguae Graecae. Mathews, Jr. says it is now ‘certain’ the Syrian could not have been Ephrem. See Brock on the Syrian commentary attributed to Ephrem or his followers. Edward G. Mathews, Jr., translation, introduction, and notes, The Armenian Commentary on Genesis Attributed to Ephrem the Syrian, Corpus Scriptorum Christianorum Orientalium, 573 (Louvain: Éditions Peeters, 1998), p. 6 FN 35; Sebastian P. Brock, ‘Ephrem and the Syriac Tradition’, in CHECL, pp. 362-372 (pp. 363, 365); see also Ayres, Nicaea and its Legacy, pp. 229-230; Young and Teal, pp. 174-178. 266 Mathews, Jr. says Basil was drawing on Eusebius, with Diodore as intermediary. Brock thinks ideas often attributed to Ephrem in Basil’s work are likely from Eusebius. Winn, drawing on François Petit’s work, says Diodore drew on Ephrem’s biblical commentaries and often offered ‘identical’ opinions on passages (p. 11). Mathews, Jr., p. 6 FN 35; Sebastian Brock, The Luminous Eye: The Spiritual World Vision of Saint Ephrem, Cistercian Studies, 124 (Kalamazoo, MI: Cistercian Publications, 1992), p. 145, including FN 2, and pp. 179-180, FN 2; Robert E. Winn, Eusebius of Emesa: Church and Theology in the Mid-Fourth Century (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2011), pp. 11, 37-41. 267 Haar Romeny says L. Van Rompay has shown that Diodore could not have been Basil’s source for the Syrian’s ideas, even though Basil knew Diodore. R. B. ter Haar Romeny, A Syrian in Greek Dress: The Use of Greek, Hebrew, and Syriac Biblical Texts in Eusebius of Emesa’s Commentary on Genesis, Traditio Exegetica Graeca, 6 (Leuven, Belgium: Peeters, 1997), pp. 179-180, 27-28. 268 See Haar Romeny’s citation of texts, including Basil’s, that relate to Eusebius’s interpretation of Gen. 1. 2, and his discussion of lines of transmission. Hanson, however, says that Eusebius did not believe in the divinity of the Spirit, and regarded the Spirit as inferior to the Son, who was inferior to the Father. Haar Romeny, pp. 174-183, 27-28; Hanson, The Search, pp. 395-398. 269 Elowsky and Louth quote passages with words similar to the words Basil cites, attributing them to a commentary by Ephrem on Genesis, and citing as the source a 1737 edition of Ephrem’s works by J. A. Assemani. The passage, as quoted by Elowsky, is: ‘The Holy Spirit warmed the waters with a kind of vital warmth, even bringing them to a boil through intense heat in order to make 265 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 46 (wrongly) attributed to Ephrem and those held by Eusebius of Emesa are similar, which suggests further study of lines of transmission is warranted.270 It is possible for there still to have been a connection between Basil and Syrian theology, because Eusebius came from a Syrian region and knew Syriac, although he wrote in Greek.271 Basil draws on the ‘Syrian’s’ interpretation to offer ‘sufficient proof’ that the Spirit did have a role in creation, and Basil is clear that the spirit in Gen. 1. 2 is ‘the Holy Spirit which forms an essential part of the divine and blessed Trinity.’272 Given that this is the primary example of the Spirit’s role in creation in Basil’s homilies, it would be interesting to know whether this trinitarian interpretation of creation, and not just the turn of phrase about ‘warming with fostering care’, was adapted from the ‘Syrian’ source, or whether Basil already held similar ideas, and was drawing on this source for support. Similar interpretations of the role of the Holy Spirit in Gen. 1. 2 were known in Latin writings. Ambrose, who drew on Basil’s homilies in his hexaemeral homilies, cites similar phrases to Basil’s from a ‘Syrian text’, to support the belief that ‘the Holy Spirit, too, is them fertile. The action of a hen is similar. She sits on her eggs, making them fertile through the warmth of incubation.’ Mathews, Jr. says the 1737 edition is ‘unreliable’, and is an edited version of a ninth century Catena on Genesis by Severus, purported to contain passages from Ephrem and Jacob of Edessa. It is clear from comparing the passages quoted by Elowsky and Louth to passages from the commentary on Genesis attributed to Ephrem published by Dembski, Downs, and Frederick (taken from vol. 91 of the FOTC series), that two different commentaries are cited. The latter, which is understood to be by Ephrem or his followers, is explicit that Gen. 1. 2 is not referring to the Holy Spirit, but to ‘the wind’ (an element) of God, and that the Holy Spirit could not have a role in creation. Joel C. Elowsky, ed., We Believe in the Holy Spirit, Ancient Christian Doctrine, 4, ed. by Thomas C. Oden (Downers Grove, IL: IVP Academic, 2009), p. 39; Louth, Genesis 1-11, pp. 6, xxxvii; William A. Dembski, Wayne J. Downs, and Justin B. A. Frederick, eds., The Patristic Understanding of Creation: An Anthology of Writings from the Church Fathers on Creation and Design (Riesel, TX: Erasmus Press, 2008), p. 228, also p. 225 and the ‘Permissions Acknowledgements’ page in the front matter; Mathews, Jr., pp. xxxvi, 5-7; Brock, The Luminous Eye, p. 145, including FN 2, and pp. 179-180, FN 2; Haar Romeny, pp. 181-182. 270 As to ideas that seem to be established as Ephrem’s, more work may be needed. Ayres’s idea that Ephrem may have been writing in support of Nicene theology may be true, based on Ephrem’s other works, which Ayres cites, but Ephrem’s ideas about the Spirit not having a role in creation, according to Gen. 1. 2, do not suggest Nicene influences. Ayres does say that work needs to be done on studying Ephrem’s trinitarian theology. Young and Teal say his theology ‘in some respects bears comparison with that of the Cappadocians’, although he expressed his theology in poetry. Brock says it is because Ephrem wrote in Syrian and did his ‘most important work’ in poetry, including expressing his ‘theological vision through the medium of poetry’, that Ephrem is both neglected and important today. Ayres, Nicaea and its Legacy, pp. 229-235; Young and Teal, p. 175; Brock, The Luminous Eye, p. 13, also 23; see also Ludlow, The Early Church, pp. 140-143. 271 Haar Romeny, pp. 180-181, 5, 9; Hanson, The Search, p. 387. 272 Basil of Caesarea, On the Hexaemeron, Homily 2, 6, pp. 30-31. Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 47 called Creator’.273 As a result of this interpretation, Ambrose argues that Gen. 1. 2 offers evidence that ‘the operation of the Holy Trinity clearly shines forth in the constitution of the world’ [italics added].274 This wording suggests that he held an understanding of the principle of the unity of operations and applied it here, even though Basil had not done so. Jerome, in a work published in the early 390s, also knew of Hebrew translations of Gen. 1. 2, which, instead of using ‘moved’ in ‘the Spirit of God moved over the waters’, rendered the idea as ‘ “was brooding over” or “was keeping warm”, in the likeness of a bird giving life to its eggs with warmth.’275 Jerome is trinitarian in his thinking, and he understands Gen. 1. 2 to apply to the Spirit, the ‘Life-giver of all things’, which may reflect the influence of the 381 creed and John 1. 3.276 Jerome goes beyond the creed in arguing for the divinity of the Spirit based on the Spirit’s role in creation: ‘If, then, He is the Life-giver, He is therefore also the Author [of life]; and if the Author, then He is also God…’277 Jerome knew Ambrose’s work, so Basil could have been one of his sources, or he could have used one of the sources discussed for Basil or Origen’s works, although Jerome studied Hebrew himself.278 Jerome also, like Ambrose, passed the Hebrew ideas on in his writings on Genesis, during a period when Augustine also was writing. Moving to consideration of what Basil says about relations between God as Creator and Trinity and creation, there are not many explicit examples in his homilies. It may be that expecting examples is anachronistic, because of assumptions about Cappadocian trinitarian thinking that emphasise ideas about communion or community. With this said, Basil encourages his listeners to respond to God because of what they see in creation. He asks them to ‘recognize grandeur in the tiniest things’, such as the variety of plant life, and, as a result, to ‘continue always in your admiration, and increase, I Ambrose, ‘The Six Days of Creation’, in Saint Ambrose: Hexameron, Paradise, and Cain and Abel, trans. and with an introduction by John J. Savage, FOTC, 42 (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1961), 3-283 (Book 1, ch. 8, 29, pp. 32-33). 274 Ambrose, The Six Days of Creation’, Book I, ch. 8, 29, p. 32. 275 The dating is from Hayward. Jerome, Saint Jerome’s Hebrew Questions on Genesis, trans. by and with an introduction and commentary by C. T. R. Hayward, Oxford Early Christian Studies, ed. by Henry Chadwick and Andrew Louth (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995; repr. 2001), 1: 2, p. 30; C. T. R. Hayward, translation, introduction, and commentary, Saint Jerome’s Hebrew Questions on Genesis, Oxford Early Christian Studies, ed. by Henry Chadwick and Andrew Louth (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995; repr. 2001), pp. 23-27. 276 Jerome, Saint Jerome’s Hebrew Questions on Genesis, 1: 2, p. 30. 277 Jerome, Saint Jerome’s Hebrew Questions on Genesis, 1: 2, p. 30. 278 See Hayward, pp. 103-104. 273 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 48 pray you, your love for the Creator’.279 He says they can conceive ‘an idea of the Creator of the universe’ and infer ‘the invisible Creator’ from the beauty or wonders of creation, while, by observing the city and life around them, they can understand the ‘first origin of man and death’ and ‘the source of evil’.280 By observing these things, Basil says ‘we shall learn to know ourselves, we shall know God, we shall Worship the Creator, we shall serve the Lord, we shall extol the Father, … we shall not cease adoring the Author of our present and future life…’. 281 This is an example of how making inferences from creation leads people to love their Creator (God the Father) and adore the Son, ‘the Author’ of our present and future life.282 This is not, however, an example of mutually loving relations between God, understood as Creator and Trinity, and human beings or creation. In summarising a few points from this case study, one can say that Basil does illustrate the roles of the Son and Spirit in creation, but does not explicitly convey the trinitarian idea that the Persons work together through unity of operations. The Spirit’s role in Gen 1. 2 of preparing ‘the nature of the water for the generation of living beings’ might be seen as completing or perfecting the work of creation undertaken by God and the Word or Son, but he does not say this. By contrast, in On the Holy Spirit, he does apply the principle of the unity of operations, in the example cited above and an example of how it works in an act of creation. He writes, speaking of the creation of the ‘heavenly powers’: ‘In their creation, consider for me the initial cause of their existence (the Father), the Maker (the Son), the Perfecter (the Spirit).’283 Here he says the Spirit perfects the work of Father and Son, and this example is similar to Gregory of Nyssa’s application of this principle, cited earlier. Although Basil does not illustrate the principle of unity of operations in his homilies, he does discuss how the Son and Father can be seen to work together in economic acts of creation, in ways that illustrate how they may be related within the immanent Trinity. This can be seen in the ways in which he writes of God speaking and God making, which must have taken place within the Godhead in some way, and which resulted in acts of the initial creation of the world. Also of special interest is that Basil passed on an unusual, and to some extent maternal, understanding of the Spirit’s role in creation, one that was known in 279 Basil of Caesarea, On the Hexaemeron, Homily 5, 9, p. 81. Basil of Caesarea, On the Hexaemeron, Homily 6, 1, p. 84. 281 Basil of Caesarea, On the Hexaemeron, Homily 6, 1, p. 84. 282 On the ‘Author’ being the Son, see Way, p. 84 FN 1. 283 St. Basil the Great, On the Holy Spirit, 16, 38, pp. 70-71. 280 Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 49 multiple traditions and may have been known to Augustine. The examples offered above can be said, on balance, to reveal more about relations between Father and Son, although not so much the Spirit, within the Godhead, than they do about relations between God as Creator and Trinity and God’s creation. Even so, Basil’s example of relations between God and people, which is about how people can examine nature and come to ‘Worship the Creator’ and adore ‘the Author of our present and future life’, will be relevant in looking at Augustine’s writings on creation. Conclusions As discussed in the introductory chapter, the Cappadocians are criticised, along with Augustine, by Colin Gunton and Catherine Mowry LaCugna, for creating a ‘breach’ in trinitarian doctrine between ideas about the immanent Trinity, and economic ideas related to the doctrines of salvation or redemption, and, for Gunton, also creation.284 It is because of these criticisms that this chapter was designed to enable examination of ideas about the immanent and economic Trinity. This chapter continued to develop the main hypothesis of this thesis: ideas, principles, and terminology associated with the doctrine of creation influenced the development of trinitarian doctrine. Given the lens of looking at the Trinity in light of creation, and related restrictions on the writings examined, one cannot assess the claim that the Cappadocians contributed to a breach between ideas about the immanent Trinity and the economy of salvation. One might assess whether they contributed to a breach either between ideas about the immanent Trinity and economic acts of creation, or between principles of trinitarian doctrine and principles of the doctrine of creatio ex nihilo. One conclusion to be drawn is that consistency existed, in the second half of the fourth century, between trinitarian principles, particularly of consubstantiality and relations of origin within the Godhead, and already-accepted principles of the doctrine of creatio ex nihilo. A related conclusion is that critiques of Cappadocian ideas about the immanent Trinity should be reconsidered in view of influences of ideas about creation on these principles. A third conclusion is that continuity exists in Basil’s hexaemeral homilies 284 See the introductory chapter for a discussion of these criticisms. Catherine Mowry LaCugna, God for Us: The Trinity and Christian Life (New York: HarperCollins, 1991; HarperSanFrancisco, 1993), pp. 9, 24-30, 143; Gunton, The Promise, p. xii. Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 50 between what he thinks Gen. 1 suggests about the roles of the Son or monogenés with God (the Father) in creation, within the Godhead and in acts of creation. Just a few points will be summarised here, which were made in support of some of these conclusions. Athanasius, in writing on the 325 creed and in Letters to Serapion, posited differences between being begotten and being made, between coming ‘from’ the Father ‘by nature’ as a ‘genuine’ Son and coming from ‘nothing’, and between being a Father and a Maker. He also argued, based on the principle of divine simplicity, that the Spirit is not a creature, and implied that the Spirit is of the same essence as the Son and Father, because, otherwise, God would be comprised of parts. Athanasius argued, again based on the principle of divine simplicity, that the Trinity could not be ‘composed of Creator and creature’, and is ‘entirely given to creating and making’. Here he makes a clear statement about God understood as Creator and Trinity. As seen in Basil’s Against Eunomius, Eunomius’s First Apology, and Gregory of Nazianzus’s orations, there were agreements on the differences between being unbegotten or uncaused, as God (the Father) is, and having come into being. However, for Eunomius, the Son and Spirit were creatures, while for the Cappadocians, they had the Father as their cause, beginning, or source within the Godhead. Other disagreements were over whether the Father, Son, and Spirit could be of the same nature. For Eunomius, they could not, because their names, such as Unbegotten and Only-Begotten, designated their natures, in addition to whether or how they came into being. For Basil, unbegotten and begotten, and Father and Son, say something about ‘distinctive features’ in the substance, but the Father and Son are of the same nature. Gregory argued that the Father, Son, and Spirit are consubstantial, with distinctions posited about whether they are not begotten, begotten, or proceeding, or without or with beginning or source. These arguments and ideas are about substance and relations of origin, and unity and distinctions, within the Godhead, but they are related to ideas about what it means to come into being, or not. There may have been developments in trinitarian doctrine, as opposed to breaches or discontinuities, in the second half of the fourth century, and these examples will be offered. First, if Michel Barnes is mainly correct, despite some of the evidence offered above, the Cappadocians, at least at times, saw the idea that the Son has the Father as cause as representing a distinction between Father and Son, rather than arguing that the Father-Son Jane Ellingwood Post-Upgrade Draft, July 2013 51 relationship establishes that they are of the same nature. If this is true, it is a change in ideas related to the immanent Trinity, from an idea about unity to an idea about distinction, although, as can be seen in Athanasius’s writings, arguments about the Father and Son being of the same nature stemmed from beliefs about human parents and offspring. With that said, given that Athanasius may not have influenced the Cappadocians, one cannot propose that that Cappadocians were changing Athanasius’s ideas. Second, if some of the arguments and conjectures offered about how monogenés was interpreted, misinterpreted, or given new meanings are correct, one could say that giving this word the meaning ‘only-begotten’, as Eunomius, Basil, and Gregory of Nyssa may have done, represents a change in terminology that occurred in trinitarian debates. If this change took place, and the word was not originally intended to mean only-begotten, this is a development in thinking on relations and modes of origin within the immanent Trinity, which also was influential in debates over nature. However, this potential development is complex, because, as argued in this and the previous chapter, monogenés may have been intended to say something unique about Jesus Christ, the Son, not related to how he came into being. This is an area where further research is called for, to add to the arguments that were presented above. The task of reinterpreting or changing the translation of monogenés could affect interpretations of fourth century texts and the 381 creed, which is known as the Nicene Creed today. Third, in keeping with the ongoing interest in assessing how God is understood as Maker and Father, it was argued that the titles ‘Maker’ and ‘Creator’ were applied to the Son, in addition to the Father, by Athanasius and Basil. This, too, is a development, and in this instance, these titles, used for the Son as well as the Father, do relate to their economic acts of creation, and to their names with respect to creation.