Ethics in Epidemiologic Research Dr. Javier Lopez-Zetina Department of Health Science California State University, Long Beach Supporting Materials Significance The practice of public health and epidemiologic research is uniquely challenged by fundamental ethical concerns. With its emphasis on population and community work, public health practitioners are routinely presented with activities that may affect the wellbeing and liberties of individuals. Broadly speaking, the public health mission encompasses two major activities: health surveillance and community intervention for preventing disease and reducing disparities in the impact of impairment and mortality. Epidemiologic research provides the tools to effectively implement the public health mission. In both disciplines, ethical dilemmas constantly arise; and they often challenge current notions of what “ethical” means in the context of a changing world. In the U.S., there is a rich history of efforts, dating back several decades, that provides an ethical framework for public health and medical and epidemiologic research. Driven in part by highly reprehensible abuses in experimental medical research during the mid1900s1, this ethical framework has given rise to a unique component of current epidemiologic/medical research: the Institutional Review Board (IRB). An integral component of federally-funded research with human subjects, the IRB prescribes specific ethical requirements and compliance in research. These ethical requirements have been enacted to ensure that research with human subjects meets current principles of beneficence, justice and respect for persons. Given the importance of these principles in guiding federally-funded research, students trained in ethics should be familiar with these principles and the tensions that arise when applications of these principles and the principles themselves are applied in epidemiologic research. Briefly, the first principle refers to beneficence or the prescriptive principle of acting for the benefit of others 2. The principle of justice obligates researchers to ensure that in their scientific activities, 1 For example, in what it was later known as the Tuskegee experiment; beginning in 1932 and well into the early 1970s, 400 black men affected by syphilis were left with no treatment for four decades. Despite knowledge of effective treatment for syphilis by the researchers involved in the study, government doctors continued with the experiment so they could learn more about the natural history of syphilis. 2 The CSULB IRB policy document defines Beneficence as follows. “Persons are treated in an ethical manner not only by respecting their decisions and protecting them from harm, but also by making efforts to secure their well being. Such treatment falls under the principle of beneficence. The term "beneficence" is often understood to cover acts of kindness or charity that go beyond strict obligation. In this document, beneficence is understood in a stronger sense as an obligation. Two general rules have been formulated as complementary expressions of beneficent actions in this sense: (1) do not harm and (2) maximize possible benefits and minimize possible harms”. 1 benefits outweigh the risks, and that a shared decision-making process accompanies all activities involving human subject participation in the research protocol 3. Finally, the principle of respect for persons states that the dignity and autonomy of individuals should always be respected. Moreover, individuals with diminished autonomy (e.g. children, persons under correctional supervision or medically incapacitated) should be afforded the same level of respect 4. These basic ethical principles have been, in turn, translated into specific applications, for example, obtaining informed consent, assessment and disclosure of risks and benefits, voluntariness, disclosure of conflict of interest, and other applications. Despite this ethical framework, public health practitioners are constantly faced with new challenges arising from the evolving and extended nature of what constitutes “research”. For example, few or no regulations for the protection of human subjects are followed by private companies conducting research with their employees and with their own funds (McDaniel, Solomon et al. 2006). Another gray area posing unique ethical challenges is international research (Miller 1988; Kelley 2002; Hyder, Wali et al. 2004). Domestically, the growing tension between the IRB prescriptive translations of ethical principles and the specific need of community participatory research is generating ethical issues that are as yet, unresolved (Malone, Yerger et al. 2006). Next, but not last or least, examination of genetic variation in large communities and populations has often been met with heated controversy over whether such screening and testing, even under IRB protection, is bound to cast upon entire communities the stigma of being branded “genetically defective” (Sterling, Henderson et al. 2006). Curriculum Development Proposal 3 CSULB IRB policy definition. Justice. “Who ought to receive the benefits of research and bear its burdens? This is a question of justice, in the sense of "fairness in distribution" or "what is deserved." An injustice occurs when some benefit to which a person is entitled is denied without good reason or when some burden is imposed unduly. Another way of conceiving the principle of justice is that equals ought to be treated equally. It is necessary, then, to explain in what respects people should be treated equally. There are several widely accepted formulations of just ways to distribute burdens and benefits. Each formulation mentions some relevant property on the basis of which burdens and benefits should be distributed. These formulations are (1) to each person an equal share, (2) to each person according to individual need, (3) to each person according to individual effort, (4) to each person according to societal contribution, and (5) to each person according to merit”. 4 CSULB IRB policy definition. Respect for Persons. “Respect for persons incorporates at least two ethical convictions; first, that individuals should be treated as autonomous agents, and second, that persons with diminished autonomy are entitled to protection. The principle of respect for persons thus divides into two separate moral requirements: the requirement to acknowledge autonomy and the requirement to protect those with diminished autonomy”. 2 The proposed 3-hour ethics module will be integrated into the course HSC500 Principles of Epidemiology. Dr. Lopez-Zetina has taught this course since 2000 to graduate students of the Master’s of Public Health in the Department of Health Science. Ethical issues in epidemiologic research are covered in various lectures and assignments but there is currently no stand-alone module solely dedicated to examining ethical principles, dilemmas, and controversies. As former member of the CSULB IRB, Dr. Lopez-Zetina is uniquely qualified to provide a comprehensive training on ethics and research compliance. Overall Objective I: The proposed module will provide students with the intellectual and academic tools to recognize currently accepted institutional mechanisms for the protection of human subjects when conducting epidemiologic research. In particular, the prescriptive and oversight role of the local CSULB IRB will be examined. Overall Objective II: The proposed curriculum will provide students with an overview of current ethics controversies and dilemmas impacting implementation of public health, biomedical and epidemiologic research, both domestically and internationally. The module will be comprised of the following sections: 1. Overview of the IRB Principles of Beneficence, Justice and Respect for Persons 2. Overview of specific applications of IRB Principles Informed Consent Confidentiality Disclosure of risks and benefits Disclosure of conflict of interest 3. Current ethical dilemmas and controversies Shared clinical decision-making Genetic screening International ethics and IRB review of international collaboration Participant observation and community-based participatory research Non federally-funded research: ethical framework Each section of this module will be structured as follows: Learning Objectives Presentation of invited speakers (if scheduled) Overview Case Study/Discussion Questions Overview of Collective Answers Suggested Reading Other online resources Work Cited and Suggested Preliminary Module Bibliography (Appended) 3 4 Hyder, A. A., S. A. Wali, et al. (2004). "Ethical review of health research: a perspective from developing country researchers." J Med Ethics 30(1): 6872. Kelley, S. D. (2002). "The forum. A contextualized approach to IRB review for collaborative international research." Ethics Behav 12(4): 371-6. Malone, R. E., V. B. Yerger, et al. (2006). ""It's Like Tuskegee in Reverse": A Case Study of Ethical Tensions in Institutional Review Board Review of Community-Based Participatory Research." Am J Public Health 96(11): 1914-1919. McDaniel, P. A., G. Solomon, et al. (2006). "The ethics of industry experimentation using employees: the case of taste-testing pesticide-treated tobacco." Am J Public Health 96(1): 37-46. Miller, J. (1988). "Towards an international ethic for research with human beings." Irb 10(6): 9-11. Sterling, R., G. E. Henderson, et al. (2006). "Public Willingness to Participate in and Public Opinions About Genetic Variation Research: A Review of the Literature." Am J Public Health 96(11): 1971-1978. 5