Contemporaries who thought that Berkeley was “half right” Leibniz: right: the only ultimately real thing is minds (monads) and their “perceptions” right: there is no such thing as absolute space or time wrong: matter does not exist (matter is the way spirits appear to one another, and so is founded on the constitution of spirits, though it is not independently real) wrong: God imposes ideas on us in accord with established laws (there is instead a pre-established harmony) wrong: the only ideas are images (there are also abstract ideas) wrong: extension is only finitely divisible (it is the paradoxes associated with the infinite divisibility of extension that prove that it must be phenomenal) Contemporaries who thought that Berkeley was “half right,” cont.d Johnson: right: there is no material world; sensible things are just collections of ideas right: we have an intellectual grasp of our minds wrong: we have no abstract notions Contemporaries who thought that Berkeley was “half right,” cont.d Hume: right: there are no abstract ideas right: there is no knowledge of bodies existing in an external world right: space and time are not infinitely divisible wrong: an idea cannot exist apart from being perceived by some mind (each simple idea is different from everything else in existence, and hence distinguishable and separable from everything else) wrong: minds are perceiving, active things distinct from their ideas, which are perceived and inert Contemporaries who thought that Berkeley was “half right,” cont.d Reid: right: we do not immediately perceive distance outwards or objective magnitude wrong: we do not immediately perceive orientation, situation, or number right: nothing can be like an idea (mental state) but another idea (mental state) wrong: to conceive an object is to perceive a mental image of that object Hume’s Arguments to Confirm Berkeley’s Account of Abstract Ideas (“one of the greatest and most valuable discoveries that has been made of late years in the republic of letters”) A preliminary observation: We do not consider objects to be of different kinds or sorts on account of every small alteration in quantity (e.g., size, shape) or quality (e.g., colour) Consequently, the idea of a kind must be either: an idea that “abstracts” from every particular degree of quantity and quality and represents an object that has none of these particular degrees (e.g., a line of no particular length or colour) a “general” idea that includes every possible different degree of quantity and quality (e.g., an idea of all the different possible lines) Hume’s Arguments to Confirm Berkeley’s Account of Abstract Ideas, cont.’d Hume’s first argument against abstract ideas: different=distinguishable=separable But the precise length of a line is not different or distinguishable from the line itself. or the precise shade of a colour different or distinguishable from the colour. So these things cannot be separated from the line. So abstract ideas of lines are impossible. (By similar argument, all ideas that involve abstracting from precise degrees are impossible.) Note that the “difference principle” is most plausible when ideas are considered to be images. Hume’s Arguments to Confirm Berkeley’s Account of Abstract Ideas, cont.’d Hume’s third argument against abstract ideas: If we could form an idea of an object with no precise degree of quality or quantity, then such objects could exist. (because anything that we can form a distinct idea of must be possible) But no such objects can exist. (As everyone agrees.) So we can form no ideas of objects with no precise degree of quality or quantity. “to form the idea of an object, and to form an idea simply is the same thing; the reference of the idea to an object being an extrinsic denomination, of which in itself it bears no mark or character.” So we can form no ideas that have no precise degree of quality or quantity. So we can form no abstract ideas. Hume’s Account of General Ideas A general idea is a particular idea associated with a general term. Hearing general term = (forming a particular idea) + (experiencing a “custom”) The “custom” does not produce infinitely many more ideas or even any more ideas. It instead consists in a disposition to form any of the many (but not infinitely many) ideas that have been associated with that term in the past. The Disjunction Problem Suppose I form an idea of a particular triangle. What makes it a general idea of a triangle as opposed to a shape or a colour? Hume’s Reply The custom (disposition) aroused by the general term is what makes the particular idea general. Hume’s First Argument for “Scepticism with Regard to the Senses” A “natural instinct or prepossession” induces us all to believe that our perceptions are themselves external objects, that continue to exist unperceived. But philosophical reflection shows us that this cannot be so. (Chief among the reflections Hume mentioned is one having to do with the visual perception of magnitude — how can we think that the perception is the object when the perception constantly changes?) So philosophers maintain that our perceptions are instead caused by the objects and (sometimes) (more or less) resemble them. But this claim is without any foundation in reason because we know for a fact that many of our perceptions (e.g., dreams) have no such cause because causal inference can only be based on past experience of a constant conjunction between types of antecedent and consequent events, but in this case we have never experienced the antecedents (the external objects) The claim is furthermore without any foundation in common sense or natural instinct Hume’s Second Argument for “Scepticism with Regard to the Senses” All are agreed that the sensible qualities are merely perceptions that have no existence apart from being perceived. So if there are external bodies, they must have only the primary qualities (which are modes of extension and solidity). But extension cannot exist apart from its parts, which are ultimately points. And these points would be nothing were they not coloured or solid Similarly, solidity is either just a sensible quality (a feeling of pressure) or the disposition to resist penetration, which presupposes motion of extended shapes & hence colour and solidity (once again) So there can be no external bodies (at least none that have any qualities we can conceive of). (The only way to avoid this conclusion is to accept abstract ideas of extension, which have already been shown to be impossible.) Johnson’s Berkeleyanism Minds are thinking active beings, known by means of a “notion” obtained from self-consciousness Sensible objects are collections of simple ideas obtained from the senses and imposed on us independently of our wills by some greater spirit. These objects are not pictures of externally existing things, but just are the real things (At least, the only real things we are concerned with) Because supposing otherwise leads to scepticism They are nonetheless only copies of archetypes in the divine mind. (We do not see the ideas in the mind of God) Johnson’s Berkeleyanism, cont.’d Pure intellect is a power of conceiving abstracted [!] or spiritual objects, relations, and acts of mind. Spiritual objects (soul, God, agent) are collections of simple intellectual notions, just as sensible objects are collections of simple ideas of sense. Moral relations (justice, charity) are perceived by the eyes of the mind (the intellect) in the same way spatial relations are perceived by the senses. The intellect is as passive in the reception of intellectual truths regarding the spiritual & moral world as the senses are regarding the natural world. And these truths are likewise dependent on God. Johnson’s Berkeleyanism, cont.’d We get our notions of ourselves by comparing our other ideas & notions with one another. This comparison also gives us the abstract notion of being in general. In forming this and other abstract notions, we rely on certain “first intellectual principles” that flow from the divine mind. (It is not immediately obvious how this is consistent with Johnson’s Lockeian view that the mind is originally a blank slate that only begins to acquire ideas and notions as a consequence of experience) Reid’s Account of Berkeley’s Place in the History of Ideas Berkeley (and Hume) were the ones who first showed us that the theory of ideas … (the theory that the immediate objects of perception are mental images) … has certain untoward consequences: scepticism concerning the existence of an external world scepticism concerning the existence of other minds scepticism concerning the existence of my own mind Reid’s modus tollens When a belief leads, by means of a valid argument, to absurd conclusions, you ought to suspect that there is something wrong with the belief. The theory of ideas leads us to absurd conclusions. What justification do we really have for supposing that the immediate objects of perception are mental images? Berkeley’s Reply: Dialogues I Reid’s Account of Mental Operations A sensation is a state of feeling pain is paradigm It exists only in the mind and only when it is perceived. When I touch a hard object I experience a sensation pain or a sensation of pressure But I also conceive that the object consists of parts that resist relative motion. I do not feel this. It is not a sensation. It is something I believe about the cause of my sensation. The occurrence of this belief is not otherwise to be explained than by saying that I am simply innately so constituted as to form that belief on that occasion. Reid’s Use of the Likeness Principle A mind is an unextended an indivisible substance. Neither extension, nor any image of anything involving extension, can exist in an unextended indivisible substance. (Nothing like what is extended can be like anything that is mental.) The most that can exist in a mind is therefore an unextended act of conceiving an object that is entirely distinct from this act in being extended. Reid’s Account of Mental Operations, cont.’d Similarly, when I see an object I experience a sensation of colour. But I also conceive that the cause of this sensation exists at a position in ambient space (a position pointed to by a line that originates from the affected part of the retina and passes through the center of the eye) Sensation and the conception that sometimes accompany it are very different. sensation does not refer to an object conception does While a conception cannot exist apart from being conceived by some mind, the object of the conception can. Reid’s Critique of Berkeley Berkeley failed to recognize the distinction between sensation and perception (conception + belief). He instead accepted the existence of a sole, hybrid entity, existing in the mind like a sensation but possessing extension & solidity like a conceived object. But he had no argument to justify this supposition and it is contrary to what is revealed by careful introspection on mental operations. Can I conceive an extended object without conceiving it as coloured or defined by tactile sensations?