The Philosophy of David Hume Introduction David Hume could almost be considered a post-modern philosopher rather than a modern philosopher due to the skepticism that is one of the signs of our current age. Another reason is because it has taken so long for Hume to come into his own, for his skepticism seemed to extreme for his era, which was optimistic about the growth of knowledge and the human capacity to solve scientific and social problems. “About a year before his death, Hume remarked to his publisher: “as to any suitable returns or approbation from the public, for the care, accuracy, labor, disinterestedness, and courage of my compositions, they are yet to come. Though, I own to you, I see many symptoms that they are approaching. But it will happen to me as to many other writers: Though I have reached a considerable age, I shall not live to see any justice done to me” (David Hume, An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, Second Edition, [Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett Publishing Company, 1977, 1993] p. vii. Hereafter referred to as Hume). Hume has had to wait a long time. Even during the 20th century philosophers were slow to warm up to him. Just as we saw with Berkeley, people were quick to not only think they understood him, but then to dismiss him as a skeptic and atheist. Even his friend and one of the most esteemed British philosophers of that time, Frances Hutcheson, told the town council of Edinburgh that he did not think it was a good idea to give Hume a position as a teacher. Hume did have those who recognized his genius, such as Kant who said that reading Hume awoke him from his “dogmatic slumber” and as a result Kant was to write some of the most influential philosophy of all time. As it sometimes happens, people seem to think reading Kant was enough and didn’t bother with Hume. So who was this man and what did his philosophy teach? Hume is often seen as the third of three major British philosophers starting with John Locke and continuing with George Berkeley. And while it is true that he builds on their work and was deeply influenced by them, he does not just continue their work but he makes fundamental changes in it. Hume said about his own philosophy: “My principles … would produce almost a total alteration in philosophy: and you know, revolutions of this kind are not easily brought about” (Hume, p. viii). While perhaps not a modest statement it is nevertheless considered true by many philosophers today. At the very least, Hume is now considered to be one of the two greatest philosophers of the 18th century, along with Kant. Therefore it is important to study Hume not only to understand the history of philosophy, “but for a study of some of the most formidable arguments and positions in philosophy” (Hume, p. viii). So formidable that many people who align themselves with skepticism still think that Hume has not yet been refuted. We don’t know a great deal about Hume’s early life and education, but he was born on April 26th, 1711 in Edinburgh, Scotland and he died in 1776, when he was 65. He spent a few years studying at the University of Edinburgh, but he left before he received a degree. While his family hoped he would study Law, Hume showed much more interest in the ancient classics. He spent three years in France in the 1730’s, during which time he started to write his first works which he subtitled “Being an Attempt to Introduce the Experimental Method of Reasoning into Moral Subjects.” None of his philosophical works would achieve much critical success, let alone popular success during his life. Besides his writing, he worked many different jobs, as a teacher and tutor, as a secretary to a general, and as a librarian. He wrote on many subjects and while his philosophy was not popular his political writings were, especially in France. He also wrote the six-volume History of England. In the last decade of his life he had a famous dispute with the French philosopher Rousseau, which is usually blamed on Rousseau’s illness and paranoia. Hume was raised as a Calvinist but early on he showed signs of moving away from orthodoxy. He never was excommunicated as he expected, but he was continually attacked by the religious leaders of the day and it was their opposition that prevented him from becoming a University Professor. Hume’s Philosophy Hume’s most famous book on philosophy is a small book called An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. He worked on this book all of his adult life, personally editing all ten editions of this book, each time trying to make it clearer and better. He first published his ideas in an early work referred to as the Treatise on Human Nature, but later left off his grand attempt to write about a science of human nature that would be profound as Newton’s laws concerning motion. But both his earliest work and his last edition both have as their main purpose the attempt to destroy what he called “dogmatic rationalism.” “A view that pervades nearly all Hume’s philosophical writings is that both ancient and modern philosophers have ben guilty of optimistic and exaggerated claims for the power of human reason” (Hume, p. xiii). What did he mean by dogmatic reason? Hume seems to have felt that all the attempts to prove the existence of God and to understand and articulate final and absolute truths were doomed to failure. He was very aware of the limitations of the human mind and thus when Kant read him and said that Hume awakened him from his dogmatic slumbers it was the dogma of reason that he was talking about and thus it led to Kant’s important book: Critique of Pure Reason. Hume attacked dogmatic reason in two ways. First he tried “to show that beliefs about particular entities could not be validated because we lack experience and thus ideas or concepts of such entities” (Hume, p. xiv). Notice right here how he connects our ideas with experiences. We get our ideas from our concrete experiences, our sensations and perceptions. This brings him into line with empiricism. Where “the rubber meets the road” is in our concrete lived experience. “Every simple idea has a simple impression, which resembles it; and every simple impression a correspondent idea. All our simple ideas in their first appearance are derived from simple impressions, which are correspondent to them, and which they exactly represent. Complex ideas, on the other hand, need not resemble impressions. We can imagine a winged horse without having ever seen one, but the ingredients of this complex idea are all derived from impressions. The proof that impressions come first is derived from experience; for example, a man born blind has no idea of colors” (Russell, pp 660-661). I think one way of seeing how this works is looking at all of the strange creatures in a movie like Star Wars. No matter how creative the artists are they still have to use ingredients that come from our experience. What is unusual is how they are put together, but not the individual pieces. Hume’s second attack on reason came from his attempt to demonstrate that “even where we possess these ideas or concepts [about ultimate truth], our beliefs about such things are not based on reason or the understanding, but on feeling, imagination or Hume’s catchall term, “custom” (Hume, p. xiv). I think even today we see that many public policies on all sorts of things, but especially moral issues, are not based on careful reasoning, but rather on “custom” or belief systems. That does not mean that they are inherently wrong, but it does mean that what we take for reasonable positions are very often not rational, but emotional, responses to what we feel is right or simply the acceptance of what we have been taught is proper. Hume was aware that if he was too successful at combating dogmatic reason he would lead the way to a profound skepticism that would not only undermine metaphysics, (which was fine with him), but also all practical knowledge and scientific enquiry, which was not fine with him. What was he to do? In An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding Hume implied that the proper remedy for [this] is a moderate or mitigated form of skepticism, a middle path between dogmatism on the one hand and excessive skepticism on the other. A true philosopher must “avoid all distant and high enquires” and limit enquiries to “such subjects as are best adapted to the narrow capacity of human understanding.” He must be skeptical of the pretenses of reason without adopting a “skepticism as is entirely subversive of all speculation, and even action” (Hume, pp. xiv-xv). Unfortunately this tells us what to do but not how to do it! This is one of the main problems of speculative philosophy that people have been struggling with for thousands of years. People have been trying to figure out how Hume thought this “moderate skepticism” could be facilitated ever since he published his ideas. In fact, Hume was dismissed in part because it was not clear once the smoke settled how we could know anything at all! In fact we can’t even hold as true our most mundane everyday beliefs such as the fact that the sun will rise tomorrow. Did I say fact? How do we know the sun will rise? We don’t really. All we know is that it always has come up each morning and so there is no real reason to assume it won’t. Hume’s conclusion stated that we could live our lives in a practical way based on probabilities, but not on exact knowledge. Earlier I mentioned that Berkeley had problems with the use of words. It sometimes seems that when we have a word for something we believe it means something, that is, it signifies something. But Berkeley said that this was not true and Hume would agree. He said this was the problem with reason; it was dependent on words and abstractions. Hume said ideas were tautological, “that is, they are redundant, repetitive, merely verbal truths that provide no new information about the world, only information about the meaning of words” (Palmer, p. 181). This was a stab at the rationalists who believe in a priori truths, that is a truth that can be known independently from observation. This usually refers to math and logic and things such as that and it is often connected with the concept of innate ideas. Plato taught that we could understand the world because the structure of our thought corresponded to the structure of the cosmos. But Hume did not believe this. He thought we could only know truths from observations, which is of course, classic empiricism. We get our abstractions from noticing similarities. So we call one animal a cat because it resembles other cats and not dogs. But this is only a superficial way of organizing matters, because in reality, every cat is unique. The word “cat” as an abstraction allows us to talk about cats as if they are one thing when actually they are all different. And yet one must wonder if this is all there is to it? Suppose we have seen the color red and we have an idea, therefore, of that color. Then we see a pink flower and we have an idea of that color. Wouldn’t it then be possible to imagine a color in between red and pink that we had never actually seen? This seems to be something that other philosophers have pointed out that Hume missed. Perhaps all of our ideas are not exactly related to simple impressions. But in general they are. We first would have to have seen certain colors to be able to imagine any color at all. Hume believed that there were three types of propositions, analytic, synthetic, and nonsense. Hume wrote: “When we run over libraries, persuaded of these principles, what havoc must we make? If we take in our hand any volume - of divinity or school metaphysics, for instance - let us ask, ‘Does it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number [i.e. analytical truths]? No. Does it contain any experimental reasoning concerning matter of fact and existence [i.e. synthetic truths]? No. Commit then to the flames, for it can contain nothing by sophistry and illusion’” (Palmer, p. 183). Analytic knowledge is like having five apples. If someone then explains to you that what you have is three + two = five you have some words, but you don’t have new knowledge. You already had five apples and knew you did. So analytic knowledge does not count for much with Hume, which is saying a lot because the rationalists put so much emphasis on it. What Hume wants is synthetic knowledge, that is, knowledge that corresponds with experience. If you have an idea in your head such as “this rock is heavy” that is because you have had experience of rocks that are heavy. Your idea corresponds to a real impression. But if you have an idea in your head like “angel” or “God,” what does that idea correspond to? According to Hume, it corresponds to nothing. Therefore it is nonsense in the true meaning of the word because it is not related to the senses. In other words, if an idea can be “traced back to sense data it passes the empirical criterion of meaning” (Palmer, p. 184). This is why Hume’s philosophy is considered atheistic - there is no place for God in his thought. But how does this work with other philosophical ideas such as the “world.” Hume was aware that Berkeley had already taken away one of the main beliefs about the world, that it somehow existed out there as a material substance independent of human reasoning. So now he undermines reason even more by denying causality. If you take two billiard balls and say that the first ball hits the second ball, and therefore the second ball moves, most of us would say that this makes sense and is therefore traceable to a physical impression and so it is true. But Hume asked us to think about this again. He asked us what we really saw? Yes, we saw the first ball strike the second ball, and yes, we saw the second ball move. But, did we see the necessary connection between them? No, because that is an inference. “So ‘causality’ proved to have the same status as ‘material substance and ‘God.’ This embarrassment has farreaching consequences. It means that whenever we say that one thing A causes another B, we are really only reporting our expectation that A will be followed by B in the future. This is a psychological fact about us and not a fact about the world. But if we try to show the rational grounding of our expectation, we cannot do so. Even if A was followed by B innumerable times in the past, that does not justify our claim to know that it will do so again in the future” (Palmer, p. 188). With this idea Hume really threw a wrench into the system and it is the reason why scholars can’t really move past him until they try to solve the dilemma that he set up. Essentially this comes down to questioning the laws of nature. It is already radical to question God, but now nature as well? Yes! How can we know that the laws of nature that have worked in the past will continue to work in the future? According to Hume we can’t. Now if this seems like a stunning assertion about the world and how can we understand it, it has more personal impact when we try to understand what we mean when we talk about ourselves having a “self.” Hume would ask us what our idea of “self” corresponds to? What experience of a self do we have? And if you closely analyze what you call your “self” you will see that there is not this “simple, indubitable, absolutely certain, eternal soul that Descartes had claimed it to be” (Palmer, pp. 188-189). Rather, “Hume found, according to his method, that there is no such idea as self. The socalled self proves to be a bundle or collection of different perceptions [such as heat or cold, light or shade, love or hatred, pain or pleasure] which succeed each other with an inconceivable rapidity, and are in perpetual flux and movement” (Palmer, p. 189). In other words, look deeply inside and see if you can find such a thing as a self. According to Hume, you can’t. And what is very interesting to me personally is that from a completely different place Buddhist philosophy says the same thing. A Zen master will say, “Show me your self” and you can’t do it. You can show constantly changing thoughts, perceptions, emotions, sensations, etc. but nothing that might be a self in any traditional understanding of the word. Therefore the Buddhists teach as one of their main truths “Anatman,” meaning no self. And since so much of our misery and suffering comes from worrying about and doing whatever we can to protect the self and provide for it and save it from dying, it apparently comes as a huge relief to realize that the whole thing is not true in the first place! Needless to say Buddhist philosophers have found Hume much more interesting than Western philosophers traditionally have. Reflections on Hume In one stroke Hume managed to wipe out hundreds of philosophers and philosophies that relied on the human ability to know certain things with surety. “David Hume had consistently and vigorously followed the program of empiricism to its logical conclusion. The results were disastrous for the philosophical enterprise. The sphere of rationality was found to be very small indeed, reduced as it was to verbal truths and descriptions of sense data; yet nearly everything that interested people as philosophers or nonphilosophers fell beyond those limits. Hume believed he had shown that human life was incompatible with rationality and that human endeavors always had to be extrarational, hence irrational. (Rationally, I can never know that the loaf of bread that nourished me yesterday will nourish me today, hence I can never be rationally motivated to eat.) But Hume knew perfectly well that the meager fruits of philosophy could not sustain the human being. Even while writing his philosophical manuscript he knew that, once he put down his pen, he too would revert to the normal, illogical beliefs of humanity - namely beliefs in self, world, and causality (if not God). He even suggested, maybe with tongue in cheek, that perhaps we should abandon philosophy and take to tending sheep instead” (Palmer, pp. 189-190). If you are not attached to your thoughts and your mind then there is no real concern. But because most of us do in fact take our thoughts seriously and think we can trust how we think about the world Hume’s philosophy and his deep skepticism were very unnerving. The great Prussian philosopher Kant, for example, was very disturbed by Hume’s work and spent many years working out a response. And, no doubt about it, Hume is disturbing. It can really shake us up to realize deeply how much we take for granted as knowledge is really simply beliefs about how things are without really understanding them. This is rational dogmatism, the belief that we can understand and figure out not only the simplest things, but also the greatest mysteries of the universe. Hume would say that we should not only forget the great mysteries, we should even be cautious about the most simple every day things. “He represents, in a certain sense, a dead end; in his direction, it is impossible to go further. To refute him has been ever since he wrote, a favorite pastime among metaphysicians” Russell, p. 659). Hume’s philosophy not only shows us the dogmatism of reason, it also shows us that a philosophy based purely on empirical observations ends up proving only that we can know nothing. He starts out wanting us to be sensible and careful observers only to show us that we can’t learn anything at all. In the process Hume proves to be personally inconsistent, because after proving our inability to really know anything, he goes on to talk as if he knew all sorts of things. In other words, if Spinoza was special because he was able to live his philosophy, Hume stands out for not being able to live his! But who could? Some would argue that Hume has yet to be successfully refuted. In my mind, Western philosophy has gotten stuck in the mud and it needs to be towed out. But it can’t tow itself out. It needs to call a tow truck, and the tow truck will come from the East. I would suggest that if a refutation were to be successful, it would come from the East rather than the West because the East has been dealing with this much longer. The East would start by going back to the question of the self. It would agree with Hume that no self could be found. But rather than stop there it would ask the further question, what part of us sees this? That is, what part of our minds can understand that we cannot understand? Normally we are so taken by what we see that we forget that we are seeing. The magic is not what we see; it is the seeing itself!