INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF ORGANIZATION THEORY AND BEHAVIOR, 8 (4), 559-576 WINTER 2005 CRITICAL THEORY, INSTITUTIONS, AND HEGEMONY: ROLE OBLIGATION AND THE RECONCILIATION OF SEEMINGLY INCOMPATIBLE GOALS Arthur J. Sementelli* ABSTRACT. Literature on critical and institutional theories are often perceived to be incompatible, despite a shared conceptual grounding. By clearly defining and understanding the concepts of “hegemony” and “role obligations” one might address this misconception of incompatibility, and allow the development of a framework to bridge the concepts of institutions and critical theory. This bridge allows the two streams of literature to meaningfully benefit from each intellectual space. This bridge can ultimately be used to inform both theory and practice in the study of organizations. INTRODUCTION The twenty first century has given rise to sets of circumstances where conceptual turf battle among disciplines has created a sort of environment where compartmentalized ideas of knowledge tend not to provide the best insights into social phenomena, epiphenomena, and what scholars typically understand as lived experiences. Consequently, effective scholars and practitioners must reexamine, reevaluate, and sometimes redefine relationships among seemingly disparate ideas. One such relationship exists between the study of contemporary critical theory and the study of institutions. Sometimes, those who self identify as contemporary critical theorists tend to prefer to examine and deconstruct institutions rather than engage in a more pragmatic approach to critical theory such as that outlined by -------------------------* Arthur J. Sementelli, Ph.D., is an Assistant Professor, School of Public Administration, Florida Atlantic University. His research interests are in integrating economic concepts and critical theory within management and organization studies. Copyright © 2005 by PrAcademics Press SEMENTELLI 560 SEMENTELLI Abel and Sementelli (2004). Arguably, there are benefits to be gained from participating, modifying, and otherwise changing these institutions from within, rather than from what some might argue to be a catastrophic change. Despite the potential benefits of a planned or internal approach to deconstruction, contemporary critical theorists often look upon such an argument with horror or revulsion, as it appears to conflict with the Marxist sensibilities of their training and flies in the face of their understanding of hegemony, control, and power. This purely negative view is arguably both erroneous and unproductive since both classical scholars of critical theory in the tradition of the Frankfurt School such as Adorno (1978) and contemporary scholars of management such as Alvesson and Wilmott, (1992) point towards means and methods by which critical theory can usefully function within institutions. In each case, however, scholars take great care to “hedge” the applicability of their conclusions within the mainstream concerns of traditional and contemporary critical theorists, which often leads at the very least to a tone of despair or futility about the process of emancipation within institutions. Some of the greatest areas of contention between the two bodies of literature come from how they perceive, understand, and cope with notions of hegemony and role obligations. Institutions and the accompanying literature often understand hegemony, for example, as a simple fact, relying on the basic definition where the institution is invested with some sort of authority over a group of individuals. This investment of authority is legitimated by contract, social structure, or some other agreement such as through human nature (Aristotle, 1992), natural law (Aquinas, 1981), dialectical necessity Hegel (Berthold-Bond, 1993), certain categorical principles of rationality (Timmons, 2002), and social contracts adopted by everyone upon leaving a state of nature (Barker, 1960; Rousseau, 1967). In such a context, the practice of hegemony most often flows from the legitimate exercise of power. The ability to wield such power and influence consistently within an organization or institution emerges from socialization, learning, and development of institutional leadership (Selznick, 1957). Some scholars, associated with contemporary critical theory, and particularly those influenced by the works of Gramsci, Freire, and others have a different understanding of hegemony than the one forwarded by many of the classic institutional scholars. Hegemony, from the CRITICAL THEORY, INSTITUTIONS, AND HEGEMONY 561 perspective of these contemporary critical theorists, often implies some force, coercion, and even malicious intent. Furthermore, such a conception is bound by its links at least contextually, if not historically, to the traditions of a ruling class in Europe. Such a linkage raises serious questions about the applicability of such assertions in the United States and other countries that do not have a longstanding tradition of a ruling class, though it often still holds in the context of social scenarios relating to gender, ethnicity, and other groups typically affected by this negative hegemony. Consider that scholarship by people such as Gramsci (1971), Freire (2003), and others was typically the product of an arguably oppressive ruling class or social order. Alternatively, it might have emerged as a reaction to the natural development or evolution of some power relationship (Foucault, 1977; 1980). In such a context, it becomes clear why some contemporary critical theorists tend to view institutions as instruments of oppression requiring deconstruction (Dennard, 1997). However, simply deconstructing institutions as a goal is problematic, since it typically fails to address the questions of what to do after the deconstruction. Furthermore, the process of deconstruction is at once a positive and a negative endeavor. It suggests new options as it critiques what is extant (Abel & Sementelli, 2004). One such possibility for the aftermath of deconstruction might be some social transformation (Sementelli & Abel, 2000, p. 460). Additionally, it might lead to processes of micro emancipation offered by Alvesson and Willmott (1992). Most likely, however, deconstruction will arguably lead to the development of an alternative institution that might check or possibly supplant the existing/offending entity. This thesis that institutions will develop to counter or supplant hegemonic efforts of other institutions is by no means altruistic, idealistic, utopian, or an act of faith. Instead it most closely parallels the well heeled quote by Madison in Federalist 51 “Ambition must be made to counteract ambition” (Padover, 1953, p. 179) whereby the most effective way to foil a hegemonic institution would be to have it compete for scarce societal resources against another institution. The justification for why these institutions can and should compete with each other comes from their associated role obligations (Hardimon, 1994) which helps set the stage for the decisions they make, actions they take, and language games they play (Wittgenstein, 1953). This paper, consequently, will attempt to uncover a place for institutions (be they oppressive or not) in 562 SEMENTELLI contemporary critical theory grounded in their corresponding role obligations and the values associated with their “brand” of hegemony, which arguably leads to competition among institutions. INSTITUTIONS AND SOCIETY There are numerous definitions of what people generally and what scholars in particular consider an institution to be. When the literature speaks of an institution, it may refer to any number of different ideas depending on where, when, and how the speaker was trained. If we consider a sociological or organizational definition, we might understand that “institutions consist of cognitive, normative, and regulative structures and activities that provide stability and meaning to social behavior. Institutions are transported by various carriers ─ cultures, structures, and routines ─ and they operate at multiple levels of jurisdiction” (Scott, 1995, p. 33). If we take a more philosophical stance, institutions are simply “any public system of rules” (Hardimon, 1994, p. 335). Economic definitions of institutions refer to “rule-following behaviour” (Allegret, Courbis & Dulbecco, 2003, p. 73) or some widely accepted method for doing something in a society such as marriage, markets, government, etc. Political scientists, in contrast, typically define institutions within the context of “the state” (Abbot, 1999; Hansen, 1998), and often focus on how voters interact with them rather than focusing more broadly on institutional structures, systems of rules, or even methods. From a sociological context, Hughes (1936) identifies the essential elements of an institution as a set of mores, formal rules or both, which can be fulfilled by people acting collectively in established capacities. Such a definition is broad enough to include, at least loosely all the definitions presented above. This piece similar to Hughes (1936, p.180) will describe institutions as the “order of social phenomena in which the feature establishment and that of collective behavior meet in a particular way: namely, so that the very form taken by the collective behavior is something socially established.” Using such a definition enables one to include the ideas of political governance, rule following behaviors, and implicit needs for structure discussed by political scientists, economists, and sociologists. Additionally, it supports Hardimon’s (1994, p.341) assertion that lives are lived through institutions, making them integral CRITICAL THEORY, INSTITUTIONS, AND HEGEMONY 563 for understanding and coping with the lived experiences discussed by contemporary critical theorists. From the definitions offered above, we can glean some basic information about institutions and their nature. First, they are social structures made up of people, and as Cooley (1956, pp. 313-314) argued, people are a primary cause of and can influence processes within institutions. Second, they are composed of individuals who are shaped, trained, and otherwise socialized by their leaders. Ultimately, as argued by Selznick (1957, p.17) in many institutions, members become invested with sets of values by their leadership core, which creates and modifies roles and behaviors, while creating a space for the examination of role obligations in this study. Third, as institutions evolve over time through interaction with individuals and the changes in their beliefs, culture, and mores, we begin to understand the reflexivity of the process, creating opportunities for the sort of micro emancipation discussed by Alvesson and Willmott (1992), and others. These changes can and will affect the operation of institutions. This responsiveness or sensitivity of institutions in turn enables emacipatory processes while it enables strategies for checking, supplanting, or at least moderating the effects of negative hegemony in an institution. Specifically, scholars can adapt and apply an analog of Madison’s idea of pitting ambition against ambition (Padover, 1953, p. 179). Rather than simply pitting political actors against other political actors, this author argues we might pit institutions against other institutions, which can lead to a number of the positive outcomes sought by contemporary critical theorists, including emancipation, micro emancipation, and in some cases social change a la Schumpeter (1975). However, before one can meaningfully employ institutions as a source of what can be understood as positive hegemony, concurrently with contemporary critical theory which can act as a source of negative hegemony, we must first understand these influences, which arguably grow from role obligations. The manner in which people understand role obligations is central to understanding how one can reconcile institutions and contemporary critical theory. NON-CONTRACTUAL ROLE OBLIGATIONS There are two basic components of role obligations. The first, contractual role obligations are tied most closely to Hegel’s (1952) idea 564 SEMENTELLI of Sittlichkeit. It requires some sort of overt agreement or formal documentation of acceptance of an institutional role. The second, noncontractual role obligations refer to roles that are not a function of agreement. Specifically, they tend to refer to the types of familial, cultural, and social relationships that people are born into or happen into without conscious choice or some informed decision. These role obligations in turn create specific relationships with certain obligations, such as those typical among the cultural elites in Europe, Central, and South America. These role obligations, typically non-contractual in nature, represent the sort of negative hegemony, if not the overt “oppression,” that is often a central argument of contemporary critical theorists such as Freire (2003), Gramsci (1971), and others. Typically, these non-contractual role obligations, as illustrated by Durkheim (1949) are part of some collective framework or normative system. The nature of these normative systems can be understood using both Kant and Pufendorf. For example, Kant’s (Timmons, 2002) notion that some obligations are categorical creates a system of non-contractual role obligations from the perspective that the role is predetermined, or without conscious choice. Pufendorf (1991) presents another way for these normative systems to emerge. Specifically, his idea that these roles are inherent in human nature points toward the sort of habituation that happens in many non-contractual role obligations. Furthermore, Pufendorf’s (1991) conception functions particularly well when explaining the maintenance of a patriarchy or monarchy. The normative system in these non-contractual role obligations is present from birth, and tends to socialize or indoctrinate individuals with a set of values similar to the process discussed by Selznick (1957), but without the conscious choice to enter into the institution and its normative system. This makes the systems that foster these noncontractual role obligations “inherently heteronomous” (Hardimon, 1994, p. 349), which can lead to conflict. This helps to explain how some, for example, can often function habitually in ways that contradict the normative systems that they themselves support and even defend, since the internalized sensibilities of people within a system can exist in conflict with the principles of the system itself. Such an internal conflict can help foster a “lifeworld” that seeks change either within or without an institution, but not necessarily. Socialization into an institution might also carry with it the beliefs that enable one to establish the principle of CRITICAL THEORY, INSTITUTIONS, AND HEGEMONY 565 reflective acceptability (Hardimon, 1994; Rawls, 1999), making the role binding. Consequently, many of the duties assigned by these non-contractual roles are not questioned, which might lead to oppression and other undesirable outcomes. At least, participants in these roles might have doubts or skepticism while performing their duties (Hardimon, 1994, p. 344), but this is not the only option since such skepticism might also lead to the sublimation discussed by Marcuse (1985), and even insurgency or “Jihad” (Barber, 1995). It can craft through this process of primogeniture, the sort of situation railed against by a number of Frankfurt critical theorists including Adorno (1978), Horkheimer (1999), and Marcuse (1964), as well as the more contemporary ones including Gramsci (1971), Freire (2003), and even Foucault (1977; 1979; 1980; 1991). CONTRACTUAL ROLE OBLIGATIONS Contractual role obligations, in contrast, are based on freely entered agreements such as those grounded in “the constitutional rights of the place” (Padover, 1953, p. 179). This role obligation also includes traditional entrances into organizations and institutions such as volunteering for the military in the US, accepting employment at a Federal agency, or accepting employment at a private institution. In this situation, the process of entering into the role is significant since the individual is in effect accepting the package of duties that accompany that role (Hardimon, 1994, p. 354) with a generalized and diffuse understanding of these duties typically without force or coercion. Contractual role obligations, though defined, can also change and mutate over time. These obligations can be interpreted, reinterpreted, and recast as institutions grow and evolve into other roles, duties, and obligations through the process of drift or endogenous evolution (Abel & Sementelli, 2004, p.95). Furthermore, since these roles are linked explicitly to the external world through these agreements (Hegel, 1952, pp. 122-123), the potential exists to reflect, adapt, and challenge other institutional roles. It is at this point where these evolving role obligations require continued informed consent or at least a mechanism of refusal to prevent it from evolving into an instrument of oppression through some type of coercion. 566 SEMENTELLI Consequently, by itself, these role obligations offer no comfort and no repose for contemporary critical theorists, but only the potential to function within their framework, or at least function as a heuristic device to understand the current set of obligations. Moreover, these concepts could be equally as likely to change or evolve into the sort of control and potential for oppression through the authority provided by these institutional positions that concerned Hayek (1994), as they can in situations with “at will” employees. However, even though we now have the potential for hegemony and oppression, we also have means and methods to respond to it as well. Once the nature of hegemony itself has been examined, we can then demonstrate how to reconcile hegemonic relationships within contemporary critical theory. HEGEMONY AND ITS PROBLEMS The idea of hegemony itself is relatively complex. Though hegemony is simply defined as leadership or preponderance (Oxford English Dictionary, 1991), it has become encumbered with value judgments placed on how this leadership or preponderance is achieved over time. Current conceptions often distinguish between hegemony that exists with or without the threat of force. The implication of force is most often associated with contemporary critical theory, while the study of organizations and institutions tend to refer to a more legalistic hegemony that is entered into willingly. In either case, there is typically a dominant group as well as one that typically has less power, or is potentially marginalized for good or for ill. This argument parallels the discussion of the positive and negative aspects of power discussed by Abel and Sementelli (2002). The primary issues with hegemony emerge when we try to mix and match these remarkably different uses, values, and intentions. As discussed earlier, many critical theorists (both classical and contemporary) believe that oppression and social injustice are the inevitable consequences of institutions, arguably seeing only one element of this concept “hegemony.” As a result many scholars of classical and contemporary critical theory tend to argue that immanent encounters are necessary to deconstruct meanings, identities and dualisms that emerge from these socioeconomic elites through the dominant culture (Dennard, 1997, p. 50), while often ignoring the potential effects of positive hegemony on institutions and society. CRITICAL THEORY, INSTITUTIONS, AND HEGEMONY 567 One scholar most frequently associated with studies of hegemony in a society is Antonio Gramsci, who believed that states could not enforce control or class structures without a multifaceted approach, which included some socialization and management of media. This makes Gramsci, exceptional among contemporary critical theorists since he at least alludes to both aspects of the concept of hegemony, though tending to emphasize the negative aspects of it in practice. As a consequence of emphasizing these negative elements, those inspired by Gramsci’s work, including Kiros (1985, p. 102) focus on the “continuous effort in stimulating the human subjects to critically question, examine and intellectually overthrow the effects of ideas that have generated those distorted and false religions, political ideas and philosophies.” Rather than include both the positive and negative aspects of hegemony, this literature stream instead takes the far more limited view, which emphasizes negative hegemony. Gramsci (1971) himself is not immune to this trap. In Selections from the Prison Notebooks, he argues that hegemony can be classified as the “social basis of the proletarian dictatorship and of the Workers State" (p. 443). From such a stance, Gramsci’s hegemony takes on far more malicious tones and becomes reinforced through manipulation and development of a ‘false consciousness.’ Gramsci, similar to Marx, and other scholars of what we might now call Neo Marxism or Neo Socialism, also points toward the issues of domination that arise from economic determinism and moral leadership. These socioeconomic influences, according to Gramsci and other like-minded philosophers, often lead to specific life choices, and can create or reinforce a culture of domination. In summation, the views of Gramsci and his intellectual progeny tend to emphasize one element of the concept of hegemony, and have over time sculpted the term to mean something wholly negative. This in turn, creates a sort of “imaginary truth” for the term (Baudrillard, 1996) that completely ignores the other, more positive elements of hegemony as a concept. To bridge these two faces of hegemony we need to examine them through the lens of role obligations. It is the two categories of role obligations, which can aid us as scholars in our efforts to understand hegemony, and consequently reconcile how institutions can and must mesh within the study of contemporary critical theory. 568 SEMENTELLI ROLE OBLIGATIONS, HEGEMONY, AND CRITICAL THEORY Understanding role obligations becomes a fundamentally useful exercise in the context of both the study of institutions and critical theory. As discussed earlier, Hardimon (1994) discusses two different types of role obligations, contractual and non-contractual. Contractual role obligations are entered into freely and are not encumbered by many of the “domination” issues expressed by Gramsci, and others in the context of institutional membership. Non-contractual role obligations, however, are often very consistent with many of the fears of Gramsci (1971), Freire (2003), and others sometimes leading to domination, alienation, and marginalization. Consequently, one can arrive at the idea that contractual and noncontractual role obligations differ based both on their processes and context. One (contractual role obligations) relies on the unimpeded, unencumbered entry into an institution. Some critical theorists might even argue that such a set of processes and context requires if not alludes to the sort of genuine communication proffered by Habermas (1981). The other (non-contractual role obligations) function within the sort of oppressive or otherwise unjust contexts that emerge from the habituated social conditions that remove the freedom of decision from the process of entry into an institution. Once these contextual differences between contractual and non-contractual obligations are understood, one might then argue that contractual role obligations reflect the sort of hegemony often understood in the mainstream literature on institutions (positive hegemony), while non-contractual role obligations typically reflect the sort of hegemony feared by contemporary critical theorists (negative hegemony). These differences in intent and process can allow us to disassociate the negative connotations from hegemony at least some of the time, in turn reducing if not eliminating the perceived incompatibility between the study of institutions and contemporary critical theory. CHOICES, JUSTICE, AND GOAL DIFFERENCES Philosophers tend to be most interested in contractual role obligations, often within the study of justice or fairness. Rawls (1999) discusses how people enter into institutions and then become “encumbered” with duties. In this sense, one might argue that Rawls is referring to a contractual role obligation, which is supported by the statement that people entering the institution have to do it voluntarily, CRITICAL THEORY, INSTITUTIONS, AND HEGEMONY 569 and use this agreement to advance their interests. This concept of entry as discussed earlier is remarkably different from that of Kant (Timmons, 2002), Pufendorf (1991), and even Rousseau (Barker, 1960; Rousseau, 1967) who explicitly or implicitly advocate for non-contractual role obligations, which in turn can provide a basis for many of the concerns voiced both by classical and contemporary critical theorists. Using the combination of voluntary participation and advancement of self-interest, one might arrive at a conception of a contractual role obligation grounded in the principle of fairness and moral reasoning that is attached to the role, instead of from the role itself outside of any social, ethical, or moral context. These concepts of voluntary participation and fairness are key elements of contractual role obligations. Contractual role obligations enable participants to enter into institutions freely, while retaining their links to the social world given that our lives are lived in practice through institutions (Hardimon, 1994). Non-contractual role obligations, as stated earlier, are problematic (Hardimon, 1994) since they are often nonspecific, the duties tend to be ill defined, or are shaped over time, and often lead to conflicts with moral beliefs. In practice, non-contractual role obligations can provide the sort of social space for the “administrative evil” discussed by Adams and Balfour (1998), where people can engage in acts of evil, harm, or hegemony without being aware they are doing anything wrong. It is under these circumstances, where the sort of hegemony discussed by Freire (2003), Gramsci, (1971), and others can and does exist. Historically, we find these role obligations are often habituated and typically lead to many of the clearest examples of injustice and harm. The study of role obligations, then, appears to offer substantial insights as a mechanism for understanding first, how contemporary critical theory and institutions might be in opposition to each other and second, how they might be complimentary to each other. The context of contractual role obligations, typically understood as being Hegelian (1952) in nature, focuses on how people freely choose to enter into institutions and their associated obligations. The tension between contractual and non-contractual role obligations gives us a somewhat balanced view of society, similar to Madison (Padover, 1953), who simultaneously reflected on the “idea of complete human depravity” while accepting Jefferson’s logic that people might possess “sufficient virtue” to participate meaningfully in institutions. This in turn reveals 570 SEMENTELLI other options besides the oppression and social injustice discussed by many critical theorists. Instead, institutions, like the individuals that exist within them, can become mechanisms that foster emancipation, or at least micro emancipation (Alvesson & Willmott, 1992), by challenging, impeding, or replacing other hegemonic institutions that might otherwise not be interested or amenable to the processes of emancipation or micro emancipation. Such a strategy remains analogous to Madison’s notion of pitting ambition against ambition (Padover, 1953), or in contemporary terms, it places the impetus for deconstruction and change on institutions competing against one another for scarce resources and support. BRIDGING LIFEWORLDS AND PRAXIS One of the most interesting areas of theory and practice that could benefit from this intersection of literature of contemporary critical theory and institutions is the study of communicative spheres (or lifeworlds), and how people, organizations, and institutions interact within them (Habermas, 1989). Organizations and institutions exist in many different “spheres” including public, private, mass, and others (Ku, 2000). Additionally, these organizations and institutions often deal both with of the conceptions of hegemony discussed earlier (Ogbor, 2001) and the associated consequences of them including critique, oppression, deconstruction, and reconstruction. Additionally, using role obligations appears to help clarify and bridge contemporary critical theory and institutional theory similar to what Dryzek (1987) advocated for the public sphere. Unlike Dryzek (1987), who limits himself to the study of the public sector exclusively, one might argue instead that the conception of role obligations allows scholars to use critical theory and literature on institutions within any and all of the spheres discussed by Ku (2000). Linking contemporary critical theory to institutional theory using role obligations also creates a solid foundation to use epistemic critique (Steffy & Grimes, 1986) meaningfully. Furthermore, it can help us to understand and explain how social rationality, where rational procedures tend to emanate from psychological processes and are eventually embraced and adopted within a society (Tillman, 2004 p. 156), might function in each of these spheres either consistently or inconsistently with the goals, objectives, and beliefs of contemporary critical theorists. Additionally, within the context of “community” writ large, the argument CRITICAL THEORY, INSTITUTIONS, AND HEGEMONY 571 forwarded helps to describe and explain how institutions in each sphere can interact, and how communitarianism often plays a role, particularly when there are issues of stratification and power ((Brint, 2001). Within contemporary society, we as scholars have come to understand that people inevitably exist within structures, within organizations, and within institutions. These institutions interact across multiple spheres, have multiple agendas, and exist in multiple geographic areas. Consequently, understanding the positive and negative influences of such institutions on the members of this contemporary society is essential for any cogent treatment of the subject. Separately, scholars such as Freire (2003) attempted to understand the politics of oppression, or the negative elements of hegemony. Simultaneously, other scholars including Selznick (1957) and Scott (1995) at least implicitly if not explicitly examined the positive elements of hegemony within organizations and institutions. This, in turn, raises the question of which to use. As argued throughout this piece, it would be fruitful to the study of both institutions and critical theory to spend some time reflecting upon the concepts of hegemony, role obligations, and how they influence organizations, institutions, and society in the broadest sense. By including this understanding of role obligations and the two sides of hegemony, one might begin to understand and possibly resolve some of the paradoxes regarding institutions acting on behalf of individuals, as a foil to dominating institutions, and as a space for the sort of immanent critique desired by many critical theorists without endorsing violence (Jay, 1973). Furthermore, when institutions become spaces for immanent critique, tools of emancipation, and foils against oppression, they in effect can begin to act against many of the “totalizing influences” (Marcuse, 1964; Horkheimer & Adorno, 1947) leading us to a meaningful critical praxis and possibly as a consequence a less oppressive society. CONCLUDING REMARKS By linking the ideas of contemporary critical theory to the institutional literature through role obligations, we find a mechanism to understand, cope, and potentially address the “crisis of confidence” that critical theorists often have as a goal, without the negative baggage that often accompanies the understanding of such a crisis. Instead of relying on the very destructive, arguably “Marxist” alternatives for coping with 572 SEMENTELLI this crisis, by reflecting on the two sides of hegemony in practice, we might instead, supplant a dominant culture (Dennard, 1997), with another from within a societal sphere. This process of institutional competition, pitting the interests of a potentially oppressive institutions against the interests of other institutions, possibly with different values, goals, and objectives can in turn achieve many of the goals set forth both by Frankfurt and contemporary critical theorists without the negative consequences associated with a total social upheaval. Some critics of such an approach might argue this is nothing more than an affront to the sensibilities of Frankfurt Critical theorists. Arguably, given that what we currently understand as “critical theory” has, in fact continued to evolve and change over time, it must then incorporate new scholars, perspectives, and ideas into its body of knowledge. Additionally, if the study of critical theory is to be a productive endeavor within the study of organizations and institutions, it must reconcile itself within these seemingly disparate goals such as institutional survival and longevity. Critical theory generally, and contemporary critical theory in particular can provide us with a number of useful insights into organizational dysfunction, many process issues, and issues of representation and power, making it a powerful tool to manage both survival and change. By reexamining and re-grounding the concept of hegemony, we as scholars can now have a productive discussion of the positive and negative consequences of it in public, private, and other social spheres. The concept of role obligations also has proved itself a fruitful mechanism to help frame the interpretations often found in the literature of contemporary critical theory. Understanding this notion of hegemony within the context of these role obligations then enables us to understand some if not most of the issues forwarded by contemporary critical theorists regarding institutions and their function. Finally, bridging the institutional literature to the literature on critical theory through the concept of hegemony opens a space for debate about the study of both organizations and institutions, while simultaneously offering access to some powerful tools and methods, such as immanent critique, that might not otherwise be pursued by scholars. CRITICAL THEORY, INSTITUTIONS, AND HEGEMONY 573 REFERENCES Abel, C., & Sementelli, A. (2002). “Power, Emancipation, and the Administrative State.” Administrative Theory and Praxis, 24 (2): 253-278. Abel, C., & Sementelli, A. (2004). Evolutionary Critical Theory and its Role in Public Affairs. Armonk, NY: M.E. Sharpe Publishing Co. Abbott, K. (1999). “International Relations Theory, International Law, and the Regime Governing Atrocities in Internal Conflicts.” The American Journal of International Law, 93 (2): 361-379. Adams, G., & Balfour, D. (1998). Unmasking Administrative Evil. Thousand Oaks, CA Sage Publications. Adorno, T. (1978). Prisms. London: Neville Spearman. Allegret, J., Courbis, B., & Dulbecco, P. (2003). “Financial Liberalization and Stability of the Financial System in Emerging Markets: The Institutional Dimension of Financial Crises.” Review of International Political Economy, 10 (1): 73-92. Alvesson, M. & Willmott, H. (1992). “On the Idea of Emancipation in Management and Organization Studies.” Academy of Management Review, 17 (3): 432-464. Aquinas, T. (1981). Summa Theologica. Notre Dame, IN: Ave Maria Press. Aristotle (1992). The Politics. New York: Penguin Books. Barber, B. (1995). Jihad Vs. McWorld: Terrorisms Challenge to Democracy. New York: Ballantine Books. Barker, E. (1960). Social Contract: Essays by Locke, Hume, and Rousseau. New York: Oxford University Press. Baudrillard, J. (1996). The System of Objects (James Benedict, trans) London: UK Verso. Berthold-Bond, D. (1993). Hegel's Grand Synthesis: A Study of Being, Thought, and History. New York: Harper & Row Publishing. Brint, S. (2001). “Gemeinschaft Revisited: A Critique and Reconstruction of the Community Concept.” Sociological Theory, 19 (1): 1 –23 574 SEMENTELLI Cooley, C. (1956). Social Organization Glencoe, IL: Free Press, Dennard, L. (1997). “The Democratic Potential in the Transition of Postmodernism.”American Behavioral Scientist, 41: 148–162. Dryzek, J. (1987). “Discursive Designs: Critical Theory and Political Institutions.” American Journal of Political Science, 31 (3): 656-679. Durkheim, E. (1949). The Division of Labor in Society Glencoe, IL: The Free Press. Foucault, M. (1977). Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison. New York: Pantheon Foucault, M. (1979). The History of Sexuality: Vol. 1, An Introduction. London: Allen Lane. Foucault, M. (1980). Power/Knowledge. New York: Pantheon. Foucault, M. (1991). “Questions of Method.” In G. Burchell (Ed.), The Foucault Effect (pp. 73-87). London: Harvester Wheatshef. Freire, P. (2003). Pedagogy of the Oppressed 30th (Anniversary ed.). New York: Continuum Publishing. Gramsci, A. (1971). Selections from the Prison Notebooks. London: Lawrence & Wishart. Habermas, J. (1981). The Theory of Communicative Action Vol. 1: Reason and Rationalization of Society. Boston, MA: Beacon Press. Habermas, J. (1989). The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere: An Inquiry into a Category of Bourgeois Society. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press Hansen, J. (1998). “Individuals, Institutions, and Public Preferences over Public Finance.” The American Political Science Review. 92 (3): 513-531. Hardimon, M. (1994). “Role Obligations.” The Journal of Philosophy, 91 (7): 333-363. Hayek, F. (1994). The Road to Serfdom (fiftieth anniversary ed.) Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Hegel, G. (1952). Philosophy of Right (T.M. Knox trans). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. CRITICAL THEORY, INSTITUTIONS, AND HEGEMONY 575 Horkheimer, M., & Adorno, T. (1947). The Dialectics of Enlightenment. London: Verso. Horkheimer, M. (1999). Critical Theory New York: Continuum Press. Hughes, E. (1936). “The Ecological Aspect of Institutions.” American Sociological Review, 1 (2): 180-189. Jay, M. (1973). The Dialectical Imagination. Boston, MA: Little Brown. Kiros, T. (1985) Toward the construction of a theory of political action; Antonio Gramsci: Consciousness, Participation and Hegemony. Lanham: University Press of America. Ku, A. (2000). “Revisiting the Notion of ‘Public’ in Habermas’s TheoryToward a Theory of Politics of Public Credibility.” Sociological Theory, 18 (2): 216-240. Marcuse, H. (1964). One Dimensional Man. Boston, MA: Beacon. Marcuse, H. (1965). “Repressive Tolerance,” in R. Wolf et al (Eds.), A Critique of Pure Tolerance. Boston, MA: Beacon. Marcuse, H. (1985). Eros and Civilization. New York: Vintage. Ogbor, J. (2001). “Critical Theory and The Hegemony of Corporate Culture.” Journal of Organization Change Management, 14 (6): 590608. Oxford English Dictionary (2nd ed.) (1991). Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press. Padover, S. (1953). The Complete Madison: His Basic Writings. New York: Harper & Brothers Publishers. Pufendorf, S. (1991). On the Duty of Man and Citizen according to Natural Law. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Rawls, J. (1999). A Theory of Justice Revised Edition. Cambridge, MA, Belknap/Harvard University Press. Rousseau, J. (1967). The Social Contract and Discourse on the Origin of Inequality. New York: Simon & Schuster. Schumpeter, J. (1975). Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy. New York: Harper & Row Publishers. 576 SEMENTELLI Scott, W. (1995). Institutions and Organizations Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications. Selznick, P. (1957). Leadership in Administration: A Sociological Interpretation. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Sementelli, A., & Abel, C. (2000). “Recasting Critical Theory: Veblen, Deconstruction, and the Theory-Praxis Gap.” Administrative Theory and Praxis, 22 (3): 458-478. Steffy, B., & Grimes, A. (1986). “A Critical Theory of Organizational Science.” The Academy of Management Review, 11 (2): 322-336. Tillman, R. (2004). “Karl Mannheim, Max Weber, and the Problem of Social Rationality in Thorstein Veblen.” Journal of Economic Issues, 38 (1): 155-172. Timmons, M. (Ed.) (2002). Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals: Interpretative Essays. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical Investigations. New York: Macmillan.