1 THREE QUESTIONS ABOUT TREATISE I iv 2 Treatise I iv 2, “Of scepticism with regard to the senses,” is a notoriously difficult section of Hume’s masterpiece.1 In this paper, I examine three puzzling questions that arise from this section: (1) Why does Hume think that the “continu’d existence” of sensible objects and their “existence distinct from the mind” stand or fall together?2 (2) Why does Hume claim that sensible objects obviously have an intermittent or discontinuous existence? (3) Why does Hume think that the “coherence” of our impressions (as opposed to their “constancy”) goes only a little way toward explaining the belief in body? 1. “Continu’d” and “distinct” existence Hume says that our belief in the existence of body can be broken down into two beliefs, namely that (CE) sensible objects continue to exist while they are not being perceived, and (DE) sensible objects exist distinct from (independently of) being perceived. He immediately adds that if CE is true, then DE is true, and that if DE is true, then CE is true.3 But while the first of these claims is true, the second one may seem to be quite 1 All page references to the Treatise will be marked as “T” and are to David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, Second Edition, eds. L. A. Selby-Bigge and P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1978). 2 Hume uses the term “objects of the senses” rather than the term, “sensible objects.” For brevity’s sake and for ease of pronunciation, I shall use the latter term throughout this paper. 3 “These two questions concerning the continu’d and distinct existence of body are intimately joined together. For if the objects of our senses continue to exist, when they are not perceiv’d, their existence is of course independent of and distinct from perception; and vice-versa, if their existence be independent of the perception and distinct from it, they must continue to exist, even tho’ they be not perceiv’d” (T 188). 2 obviously wrong: why should the “distinct” existence of objects imply their continued existence? Why couldn’t there be momentary objects, which happen to exist only when being perceived, but nevertheless do not depend on being perceived for their existence? Baldly stated, the answer I propose is that if sensible objects existed only when being perceived, then there would be a constant conjunction between their existence and their being perceived. So, sensible objects would be causally dependent on being perceived, in Hume’s sense of causal dependence, and they would accordingly fail to enjoy a “distinct” existence. So given Hume’s views about causality, DE does imply CE, just as he says. But this bald statement is open to the following objection. If sensible objects exist only when being perceived, this means that if a sensible object exists at time t, then it is perceived at t; it means that a sensible object’s existence is a sufficient condition for its being perceived. But clearly this doesn’t show that its being perceived causes it to exist. Of course, if an object’s existence is a sufficient condition for its being perceived, then its being perceived is a necessary condition of its existence. But that doesn’t show that the object’s being perceived causes it to exist: a match’s igniting may be a necessary condition of its being struck, but its igniting is not a cause of its being struck. The trouble is that on Hume’s definition of causality, as it is often construed, perceiving a momentary object cannot be said to cause its existence, anymore than a match’s igniting causes it to be struck. To see this, consider a schematic formulation of the first definition of ‘cause’ that Hume gives in the Enquiry: E1 causes E2 = df (1) E1 is followed by E2 (2) All events similar to E1 are followed by events similar to E24 4 David Hume, An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, Third Edition, eds. L. A. Selby-Bigge and P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1975), p. 76. Subsequent references to this work will be indicated as “E”. 3 In order to allow for cases where cause and effect are simultaneous, I shall replace “followed by” with “is accompanied by,” and for the sake of simplicity, I shall replace the notion of similarity with that of sameness in kind (as Hume himself sometimes does).5 This yields the following definition: D1: E1 causes E2 = df (1) E1 is accompanied by E2 (2) all events of kind K1 are accompanied by events of kind K2 (3) E1 is of kind K1 and E2 is of kind K2 It is plain that on D1, a cause is a sufficient condition for its effect. So, letting E1 stand for a momentary object’s existing and E2 stand for its being perceived, the definition provides no basis for saying that its being perceived causes it to exist, or that its existence depends causally on its being perceived. The reply to this objection is that in the Treatise Hume implies, and in the Enquiry he says, that a cause is not only a sufficient condition for its effect, but also that it is, in the circumstances at hand, a necessary condition. In the Treatise he says not only that “the same cause always produce the same effect,” but also that “the same effect never arises but from the same cause … [so that] where several different objects produce the same effect, it must be by means of the same quality which we discover to be common amongst them” (T 173-174). Leaving to one side the questionable claim that alternative possible causes of a given effect must always have some common feature, this implies that a given effect can occur, in the circumstances at hand (viz. in the absence of alternative possible causes of the same effect), only if its actual cause occurs. In the 5 Of course in the Treatise Hume claims that temporal priority of the cause is always required. But Hume also admits there that his argument for this claim may be unsatisfactory (T 76), and he does not repeat the claim in the Enquiry. Furthermore, there are counterexamples to the claim. So I shall it discount here. Two places where Hume puts his definition in terms of sameness in kind rather than similarity are in the Abstract of the Treatise, T 649 (“balls of the same kind”) and at E 74 (“But when one particular species of event always …”). See also T 87 and T 93. 4 Enquiry, Hume famously remarks that one “object” causes another when “if the first object had not been, the second never had existed” (E 76). Allowing, as we must, for the possibility of alternative causes, this again means that in the circumstances at hand, the cause is a necessary condition of its effect. This point can be incorporated into D1 by expanding clause (2) as follows: (2A) all events of kind K1 are accompanied by events of kind K2 and all events of kind K2 are, in the circumstances at hand, accompanied by events of kind K1. Thus, for example, to say that striking a match causes it to ignite is to say that all such strikings are accompanied by ignition, and that in the circumstances at hand (there is no superheated air present, no other lit match is brought into contact with the one that ignites, and so forth), all such ignitions are accompanied by strikings.6 Now for purely logical reasons, many philosophers would say that (a) All cases of an object’s being perceived are accompanied by cases of its existing. But for momentary objects, we must also say that (b) All cases of an object’s existing are, in the circumstances at hand (i.e. given the oddly perishable nature of such objects), accompanied by cases of its being perceived. But this fits the model for saying that momentary objects are caused to exist by being perceived, in which case Hume is justified in saying that an object with a “distinct” or “independent” existence cannot be a momentary object--that DE implies CE. 6 I offer a more detailed discussion of how to incorporate into D1 the requirement that a cause be, in the circumstances at hand, a necessary condition of its effect in my Hume’s Epistemology and Metaphysics: An Introduction (London and New York: Routledge, 1998), pp, 125-130. The formulation offered there replaces the phrase “in the circumstances at hand” with a schematic reference to the alternative causes and/or background conditions that are not present when E1 is the cause of E2. 5 It might be objected that if (a) is true for purely logical reasons, then the relation involved cannot be a causal one. But this objection is not decisive, for consider a parallel case: (a1) All cases of murder are accompanied by cases of a person’s dying. (b1) All cases of a person’s dying are, in the circumstances at hand, accompanied by cases of murder. Suppose that, on the model of our expanded D1, we add that (c) Oswald’s shooting Kennedy was accompanied by Kennedy’s dying. (d) Oswald’s shooting Kennedy was a case of murder and Kennedy’s dying was a case of a person’s dying. The fact that (a1) is logically true does not prevent its being the case that, given the expanded version of D1, (a1), (b1), (c) and (d) jointly imply that Oswald’s shooting Kennedy caused Kennedy’s death. The contingent nature of (b1) seems sufficient to preserve the causal connection between Oswald’s action and Kennedy’s dying. Likewise, (a)’s being logically true would not go against saying that perceiving a momentary object causes it to exist, because the contingent nature of (b) seems to preserve the causal connection between an object’s being perceived and its existing. 2. The intermittent existence of sensible objects Throughout Treatise I iv 2, Hume asserts that sensible objects have an intermittent or interrupted existence. His most basic reason for this assertion is that our perceptions are obviously discontinuous, “broken,” or “interrupted.”7 Consider for example the 7 Occasionally, he supports the assertion with the following Modus Tollens argument (T 210-211, T 214): (1) If sensible objects continue to exist while not being perceived, then they exist independently of being perceived. (2) Sensible objects do not exist independently of being perceived. __________________________________________________________ ... Therefore, sensible objects do not continue to exist while not being perceived. 6 perceptions you have when looking at the furniture in your study. Those perceptions are plainly discontinuous: they cease to exist each time you glance away from the furniture or shut your eyes, and for much longer periods of time when you leave your study or are sound asleep. This obvious point, Hume thinks, incontrovertibly proves the falsity of the belief in the “continu’d” existence of sensible objects. To grasp Hume’s thinking, it is crucial to understand that when he says that our perceptions are interrupted or discontinuous, he is not saying merely that our perceivings, or acts of perception, or perceptual episodes, are discontinuous, which is of course true. Rather, he is also claiming that the objects of our perceptions--the things that we perceive--are discontinuous. For Hume does not distinguish between perceptual episodes and the objects perceived in them; his use of the term “perceptions” to stand indifferently for both perceptual episodes and their objects is not just linguistic carelessness, but embodies a genuine non-recognition of the distinction between them. The only form in which Hume recognizes a distinction between perception and its objects is that of the philosophical theory of the “double existence of perceptions and objects” advocated by Descartes, Locke and others--a theory that Hume rejects. Except within the context of this theory, Hume sees no place for the distinction between perception and its objects. Hume’s rejection of this distinction calls for an explanation, if only because the distinction is so elementary. Even ordinary, unsophisticated common sense would distinguish between perceiving something, or the perception of something, and what is perceived, e.g. between seeing an apple, and the apple which is seen. Why then does Hume reject this elementary distinction? To support this argument’s second premise, Hume cites the “experiments, which convince us, that our perceptions are not possest of any independent existence,” such as pressing one eye with a finger and seeing everything double (T 210). The obvious interruptedness or discontinuity of our perceptions, however, is Hume’s fundamental reason for holding that the objects of sense have a discontinuous existence. 7 One possible answer lies in Hume’s acceptance of the view that we perceive only our own impressions.8 For impressions have exactly the same temporal characteristics, including notably the same duration, as perceptions, taken as perceptual episodes or acts of perceiving. So the thesis that we perceive only impressions implies that the objects of perception last no longer than the perceptions themselves. But in that case, the distinction between perceptions and objects collapses, at least for an empiricist like Hume. For from Hume’s empiricist point of view, the only thing that could have differentiated between perceptions and their objects is a temporal difference between them, because any “act” of perception distinct from the object perceived would not be something of which we could have any impression: it would be, so to speak, diaphanous or “transparent,” so that Hume’s empiricism would banish it as a meaningless notion. Thus, it may seem that Hume’s acceptance of the philosophical view that we perceive only our own impressions is what explains his otherwise puzzling denial of the elementary distinction between perceptions and objects, which in turn explains his view that sensible objects have an intermittent existence. This explanation, however, puts the cart before the horse. For as I have said, Hume regards the discontinuity of our perceptions, together with the collapse of any distinction between perceptions and its objects, as an incontrovertible proof that the objects of perception are discontinuous. But of course our sense impressions are discontinuous; so an explanation of why Hume holds that sensible objects are discontinuous that appeals to his view that we perceive only impressions renders his claim that perceptions are discontinuous and his rejection of the perception/object distinction completely otiose, as a proof of the discontinuity of sensible objects: one need not offer any argument at all to prove that sensible objects are discontinuous, if one assumes from the start that those objects are only impressions. Hence, in order for 8 This answer is the one I proposed in my Hume’s Epistemology and Metaphysics: An Introduction, pp. 167-168. For the reason I am about to give, I no longer think that this answer is satisfactory. 8 Hume’s claim that perceptions are discontinuous, together with his rejection of the perception/object distinction, to serve as a (non-otiose) argument for his claim that sensible objects are discontinuous, neither premise of that argument can rest on the view that we perceive only impressions. So we need a reason for the rejection of the perception/object distinction that does not rest on that view. I think that such a reason can be given, by pressing the point that there is no impression of any introspectible “act of perceiving” that could distinguish it from its object. For what then does distinguish perceptions from objects? It still seems that the only thing that could do so would be their temporal characteristics: objects can, so to speak, outlast the perceptions of them, and so must be distinct from those perceptions. The central importance of this point is recognized by Kant in his Analogies of Experience, where he explicitly distinguishes between the time-relations of perceptual episodes and the time-relations of their objects, saying that while perceptual episodes are always successive, their objects may be co-existent; for example that while the perceptions of the front of a house may occur before perceptions of the back, the front and back of the house that the observer successively sees co-exist. Hume recognizes the point in his own way, since he says that one of the chief components in our belief in body is precisely that bodies continue to exist unperceived. But unlike Kant, Hume does not argue that assigning a different set of time-relations to objects of perception from those of the perceptions themselves is a condition of the very possibility of experience, and is therefore epistemologically warranted. Rather, Hume sees the time-relations of perceptual episodes--what Kant calls the order of apprehension and his commentators usually call the subjective time-order--as the only one that is necessary for experience: what Kant considers to be the objective time-order enters into Hume’s thought only as the fictional product of the imagination working in accordance with merely contingent principles. So, these time-relations cannot, for Hume, be appealed to as an epistemically warranted way of distinguishing between perceptions and objects: objects do not knowably have different 9 time-relations than perceptions. Within the range of what can be known, there are only the time-relations of the perceptions themselves, and since there is accordingly no other set of time-relations to appeal to, and yet no way to distinguish between perceptions and objects other than their time-relations, the distinction between perceptions and objects collapses. 3. The role of “coherence” Hume finds two features of our impressions that explain why we believe in the continued existence of sensible objects despite their intermittent existence: constancy and coherence. But he thinks that coherence alone is “too weak to support so vast an edifice, as is [belief in] the continu’d existence of all external bodies” (T I iv 2, 198-199), and he places much more weight on his complicated “system” about the way constancy leads to the belief in object-continuity (T 199-210). Why does Hume think that coherence alone goes so little way toward explaining this belief? Here is one of Hume’s characterizations of coherence: Bodies often change their positions and qualities, and after a little absence or interruption may become hardly knowable. But here ‘tis observable, that even in these changes they preserve a coherence, and have a regular dependence on each other; which is the foundation of a kind of reasoning from causation, and produces the opinion of their continu’d existence. When I return to my chamber after an hour’s absence, I find not my fire in the same situation, in which I left it: But then I am accustom’d in other instances to see a like alteration produc’d in a like time, whether I am present or absent, near or remote. This coherence, therefore, in their changes is one of the characteristics of external objects, as well as their constancy (T I iv 2, 195). In this passage, Hume’s intention is to describe the kind of uniformity in our impressions that he calls “coherence.” But as commentators have pointed out, he fails to confine himself to impressions, and carelessly attributes coherence to “bodies” and “external objects” themselves.9 See Barry Stroud, Hume (London, Boston and Henley: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1977), p. 100 and Jonathan Bennett, Locke, Berkeley, Hume: Central Themes (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1971), p. 323. 9 10 Mindful of this point, let us try to characterize coherence without assuming the existence of physical things. We may define coherence this way: to say that a set of impressions I exhibits coherence is to say that I is composed of a discontinuous set of impressions whose members occur in the same temporal relations as the resembling members of continuous but altering sets of impressions that closely resemble each other (that exhibit what Hume calls “constancy”). Here is an example, based on Hume’s illustration. Suppose I have often had the experience that I would call continuously viewing a slowly diminishing fire in my fireplace. Then, when I have an experience that I would call discontinuously viewing such a fire--i.e. of seeing the fire, then leaving the area for a certain period of time, then returning and seeing the fire again--the relations between the elements of that experience are the same as the relations between the “matching” elements of the continuous experiences: for example, the impressions of a fire had at the end are impressions of a smaller fire than the impressions of a fire had at the beginning, not of a larger one or an equally large one. Such coherence among our impressions, Hume thinks, contributes to the belief in the continued existence of bodies; in this instance, to the belief that when I have impressions of a large fire in my fireplace, followed by no impressions of fire, followed by impressions of a small fire in my fireplace, a slowly-diminishing fire exists unperceived in between. Hume initially says, as we saw, that this belief is then based on a “kind of reasoning from causation.” But a little later he writes that: But tho’ this conclusion from the coherence of appearances may seem to be of the same nature with our reasonings concerning causes and effects; as being deriv’d from custom, and regulated by past experience; we shall find upon examination, that they are at the bottom considerably different from each other, and that this inference arises from the understanding, and from custom in an indirect and oblique manner. For ‘twill readily be allow’d, that since nothing is ever really present to the mind, besides its own perceptions, ‘tis not only impossible, that any habit shou’d ever be acquir’d otherwise than by the regular succession of these perceptions, but also that any habit shou’d ever exceed that degree of regularity. Any degree, therefore, of regularity in our perceptions, can never be a foundation for us to infer a greater degree of regularity in some objects, 11 which are not perceiv’d; since this supposes a contradiction, viz. a habit acquir’d by what was never present to the mind. But ‘tis evident, that whenever we infer the continu’d existence of the objects of sense from their coherence, and the frequency of their union, ‘tis in order to bestow on the objects a greater regularity than what is observ’d in our mere perceptions. We remark a connexion between two kinds of objects in their past appearance to the senses, but are not able to observe this connexion to be perfectly constant, since the turning about of our head, or the shutting of our eyes is able to break it. What then do we suppose in this case, but that these objects still continue their usual connexion, notwithstanding their apparent interruption, and that the irregular appearances are join’d by something, of which we are insensible? But as all reasoning concerning matters of fact arises only from custom, and custom can only be the effect of repeated perceptions, the extending of custom and reasoning beyond the perceptions can never be the direct and natural effect of the constant repetition and connexion, but must arise from the co-operation of some other principles.” (T 197-198) To understand Hume’s reasoning here, contrast two types of cases: Type-I cases: I watch a slowly diminishing fire in my fireplace. I neither shut my eyes nor turn my head away from the fire, but watch the fire continuously until it burns itself out. Type-II cases: I watch a slowly diminishing fire in my fireplace. However, at one or more times while the fire is burning, I shut my eyes, turn my head away from the fire, or leave the room. Assuming that I have experienced several type-I cases, my visual impressions in a type-II case exhibit coherence: discontinuous impressions of a fire occur in the same temporal relations as the resembling members of the impressions I obtained in the type-I cases. Suppose that on the basis of this coherence, I infer that in a type-II case, I am observing a fire that continues to burn while my eyes are shut, my head is turned away, or I am absent from the room. Our question is this: why does Hume think I am then making an inference that does not conform to the kind of custom-based causal reasoning which he holds to be the sole basis of any knowledge of matters of fact not based on present perception or on memory? 12 To see why, let us first imagine that a constant-conjunction-establishing series of type-I cases occurs in my experience--i.e. that I have the experience of continuously watching a diminishing fire often enough to establish a constant conjunction between visual impressions like those I have at the first moment (= time-interval) of watching the fire and visual impressions like those I have at the second moment, and between visual impressions like those I have at the second moment and visual impressions like those I have at the third moment, and so on. Notice, then, that in a new case where I have impressions like those I have repeatedly had at the first moment of watching the fire, I can infer, according to Hume’s theory of causal-inductive inference, that I will next have impressions like those I have repeatedly had at the second moment; likewise, in a new case where I have impressions like those I have repeatedly had at the second moment of watching the fire, I can infer that I will next have impressions like those I have repeatedly had at the third moment; and so forth. Now imagine that a type II case occurs in my experience: I watch a fire in my fireplace for the first moment; then shut my eyes, turn my head away, or leave the room for the second moment; then watch the fire again for the third moment; then shut my eyes, turn my head away, or leave the room for the fourth moment; and so on. Then the coherence of my impressions causes me to infer that even during the second moment and the fourth moment, something just like the visual impressions I had during the second and fourth moments of the type-I cases existed, albeit unperceived by me. But clearly enough, this inference is not licensed by the custom-based reasoning from constant conjunction that Hume discusses. For there is a difference between the type-I cases I remember and the type-II case I have just experienced: in the former, each visual impression of a fire was immediately followed in time by another visual impression of a fire; in the latter, each visual impression of a fire is immediately followed in time by other kinds of impressions. For the inference performed in case II to be a custom-based causal inference, there would have to be a constant conjunction between the visual impressions obtained at 13 the first moment of the type-I cases and those obtained at the second moment of the typeII cases, and between the visual impressions obtained at the second moment of the type-I cases and those obtained at the third moment of the type-II cases, and so on. But there is no such constant conjunction; for in all type-II cases my visual impressions of a fire at one moment are followed at the next moment by visual impressions of something else, and so by a “gap” in the impressions of a fire. Therefore, when I infer the existence, in a type-II case, of something just like the visual impressions I have following each visual impression of a fire in type-I cases, I am attributing a greater degree of regularity or uniformity to the world than I ever perceive. And this illustrates why coherence alone is “too weak to support so vast an edifice, as is [belief in] the continu’d existence of all external bodies.” It might be objected that the reasoning I have attributed to Hume is mistaken, because if a constant-conjunction establishing set of type-I cases has already occurred in my experience, then in any new case where I experience the impressions I had at moment M of such cases, I can infer the existence of what I perceived at moment M + 1. So if, say, five minutes into type-I cases I had impressions of a large fire and a minute later of a smaller fire, then in any other similar case where I have impressions of a large fire I can infer that a minute later a smaller fire will exist, whether I perceive it or not. But this objection fails, because the situation just described is not a case of coherence at all. For in this situation no type-II case has occurred as yet; such a case will only have occurred after I have had the impressions of a large fire, followed by no impressions of a fire, followed by impressions of a smaller fire. But once such a case has occurred, it ipso facto constitutes an exception or counterexample to the experienced regularity found in the type-I cases alone. Thus again, to suppose that something like what I experienced at moment M + 1 of the type-I cases exists at moment M + 1 of the type-II cases is to attribute a greater degree of regularity to the world than I perceive. It is true that type-II cases will also include certain impressions, associated with turning my 14 head away, shutting my eyes, or leaving the room, that mark them off from type-I cases. But this does not salvage the objection. For the occurrence of these other impressions does not re-establish a constant conjunction between impressions like those had at moment M and those had at moment M + 1 of the type-I cases. Georges Dicker SUNY Brockport gdicker@brockport.edu