PUBLIC REASON AND DELIBERATION CHAPTER 4 RECIPROCITY AND ACCOUNTABILITY: CONTEMPORARY THEORIES OF PUBLIC JUSTIFICATION Justification Public reason and deliberation are often discussed under the general category of theories of public justification. This chapter offers a brief survey of ideas of public justification and discusses some of the central disputes among defenders of public justification. An interest in justification is becoming a defining feature of contemporary liberalism.1 This does not mean that liberals are in some sense more engaged in the process of justification than they used to be or than other types of political philosophers. For what is political philosophy but the activity of justification? If we understand justification generally to mean the process whereby we seek to ground or defend claims, principles, conclusions (and actions), then all political philosophy to the extent that it engages in arguments, offers reasons and seeks to defend claims is engaged in justification. To say that justification stands at the center of contemporary liberal theory is to say something more than that liberal theorists are in the business of justifying liberal principles. It is to say that liberal theory is self-consciously asking ‘what does it mean to justify liberal principles?’ Even more particularly, liberals are asking ‘how ought we to think about the justification of coercive law and public institutions under conditions of pluralism?’ As we say in the last chapter, John Rawls and Jürgen Habermas inaugurated the move towards a justification-centered model of liberalism when they (independent of each other) introduced ‘all those affected’ as the addressees of justification. “Public justification is not simply valid reasoning, but argument addressed to others” says Rawls.2 John Simmons argues that this represents a major shift in the way political philosophy understands justification: “Justification is now justification to a particular set of persons, not justification ‘simpliciter’” (Simmons: 759).3 What this shift points to, according to Simmons, is a fusion of two concepts held separate within traditional liberal political philosophy. Justification and legitimacy fold into each other in contemporary liberalism especially its Kantian version. This is to be contrasted to the more traditional view, seen for example in Locke, where justification is an essentially philosophical or epistemic enterprise seeking to get it right while legitimacy is a political concept seeking to secure allegiance. Locke justified the state through the device of a contract which was in turn supported by natural law theory. Legitimacy by contrast was established through the consent of the governed. Today we see contract and consent being replaced by an over-arching idea of ‘justification to the other’.4 The move away from justification simpliciter towards inter-subjective ideas of justification is due in part to the accommodation of and respect for the deep pluralism that characterizes most liberal societies. It is not that all liberals have abandoned ideas of natural law or objective good (although many have and so the post-metaphysical nature 1 of much of liberal theory also contributes to the move away from justification simpliciter), it is that there is a general acknowledgment that getting the argument right does not confer any moral authority to impose that conclusion on people who do not agree with the argument. In a philosophy seminar it might be enough to say to those who fail to see the truth in your argument, ‘well you’re just wrong – too bad for you.’ But when justifying the basic structure of the social and political order to fellow citizens, ‘you’re just wrong’ fails to treat others as equals in all sorts of ways that I discuss below. Thus the move from objective justification to inter-subjective justification is the result of subjecting liberal philosophy to liberal constraints. What is being justified, to whom, and by whom? All liberals believe that power and coercion require justification of some kind. A large subset of liberals argue that power and coercion require public justification which involves seeking, constructing and offering reasons that are acceptable to citizens. ‘Consent of the governed’ is replaced by ‘justified to all those affected’ as the touchstone of legitimacy. The term public justification is now a term of art to signal membership in this subset of liberal theory.5 The public of public justification refers first to the fact that it is justification of public things, i.e., laws, constitutions, basic social structure; second, to the fact that the addressee of the justification is a public at large characterized by pluralism (this might be ideally conceived, or as an empirical entity, or something in between); and finally, public refers to the idea that justification is presented in public or by citizens acting publicly. Not all philosophers stress this last dimension of public. Much depends on whether the conception of public justification contains a strong obligation to engage in the public practice of justification or not. Furthermore, the obligation to engage in the practice of public justification can be thought to fall on citizens generally or on public officials especially or perhaps even exclusively. Within public justification it is possible to make further distinctions regarding the ‘what’ of justification. The spectrum runs from the justification of general positions or opinions about public matters through the justification of individual laws and specific policy recommendations to the justification of constitutional essentials and basic structure. Philosophers are often not clear about which end of this spectrum they are focusing on and this can cause some confusion. Some constraints on public justification, for example, are more plausible as constraints on public officials defending constitutional essentials or enacting legislation than on ordinary citizens defending their political positions in public debate. We will return to this issue below. Public reason and deliberation are deeply implicated in any idea of public justification. They offer two slightly different angles from which to view public justification. Public reason (understood generically and not as a specifically Rawlsian concept) refers to the content of the reasons given within public justification. Here the questions focus on the types reasons appropriate to public justification. The adjectives most often used to describe public reasons are intelligible, accessible, acceptable, or sharable. All these terms attempt to capture some special quality of a public reason that sets it apart from a private reason. Deliberation usually refers to the process of reasongiving. Here the focus is often on the procedural constraints and inter-subjective dynamics of public justification. The sorts of procedural characteristics that become important are reciprocity, publicity, and inclusiveness. 2 Scholarly interest in public reason has produced a voluminous literature largely focused on theories of liberal tolerance under conditions of pluralism.6 The two leading trends in this debate are, first, a progressive expansion of the idea of public reason beyond Rawls’s initial and highly influential articulation, and second, a focus (to the exclusion of many other important questions) on the special problems posed by religious reasons. I discuss both these trends below. Scholarly interest in deliberation has produced a voluminous literature largely focused on democratic theory.7 Theories of deliberative democracy take the idea of public justification and place it at the center of theories of democratic decision-making. Thus all theories of deliberative democracy contain some conception of public justification but not all views of public justification entail a deliberative view of democracy or any specific view of democracy for that matter.8 In this chapter I will not discuss democratic decision-making but concentrate on the underlying conception of public justification that both theories of public reason as well as theories of deliberative democracy rely on. Although John Rawls is a central figure in the development of ideas of public justification he is only one among a number of influences playing themselves out in this debate .9 Jürgen Habermas has also been influential (Forst "The Basic Right to Justification: Towards a Constructivist Conception of Human Rights; Benhabib) but one can also identify a pragmatist strain that draws on Dewey and Pierce (Mysak; Talisse), a view inspired by Hobbes (Gauthier), a republican idea of public justification (Pettit), a post-colonial view (Ivison), a deliberative democracy strain (Cohen "Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy; Gutmann and Thompson) and many others.10 Thus, one of the features of the debate about public justification is that it has burst the bounds of “political liberalism” and engages many strains within liberal democratic theory. Public justification is the dominant focus of liberal theory. That focus includes many different readings and claims about how we should be justifying coercive laws to citizens. Why Justification? Despite disagreement about how to conceptualize the public justification requirement there appears to be some agreement on why we should focus on justification to others as the central conceptual tool in thinking through liberalism. Public justification is often thought to embody and give concrete expression to liberal ideas of respect for the freedom and equality of persons (Forst "The Rule of Reasons: Three Models of Deliberative Democracy": 374; Gutmann and Thompson: 79; Cohen "Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy": 416; Eberle Religious Conviction in Liberal Politics: 84-108). While respect stands at the center of all ideas of public justification, some views stress respect for the equal freedom of individuals while others the rational capacity of individuals. Gerald Gaus places freedom at the center: “if we are to respect others as free and equal. Laws must be justified to them.”(Gaus and Vallier: 55). Charles Larmore stresses that justification respects the rational capacity of persons: “(T)he distinctive feature of persons is that they are beings capable of thinking and acting on the basis of reasons. If we try to bring about conformity to a political principle simply by threat, we will be treating people solely as means, as objects of coercion” (Larmore The Morals of Modernity: 137). 3 What is the value added we get with justification that we do not get with the older idea of consent? Why is consent now seen as inadequate? The first thing to say is that justification to all those affected bears a strong family resemblance to consent. Justification shifts the focus from consent simpliciter to the reasons for consent and this in turn has a number of implications. First, as Jeremy Waldron tells us, the move from voluntaristic to rationalist accounts of political legitimacy “corresponds to the distinction between actual and hypothetical consent” (Waldron: 51).11 Actual consent is a notoriously difficult criterion to meet (Estlund: 9). Furthermore, it is subject to all sorts of possible pathologies and distortions connected to human psychology, desires and manipulation. Thus the focus on reasons for consent rather than on the simple act of consent introduces the possibility of imagining what people would consent to as well as tying legitimacy to epistemic ideas of consent for good reasons. Justification rather than consent introduces the possibility of a fully hypothetical model of legitimacy, however, this is not to say that all or even most liberal theorists of public justification opt for a fully hypothetical model of justification. Many theories of public justification introduce some form of hybrid in which there is, on the one hand, an hypothetical argument that might go something like this: ‘P is a policy for which there are reasons that all could accept’. On the other hand, there is the insistence that some form of actual process of public justification in which these reasons are aired, discussed and put before the public take place. Even Kant, who very explicitly states that no actual consent or ratification of laws is needed to establish that a law could be agreed to by a whole people (Kant : 8:297), nevertheless insists that public debate and indeed a process of public justification is necessary to achieve this outcome (Kant: 8:304). But for Kant a public process of justification is endorsed as a means of getting the reasons right and not as furnishing evidence of consent. There is another dimension to justification that is absent in the idea of consent simpliciter that is important to varying degrees within the literature. This has to do with enlightenment ideals of transparency and autonomy. Waldron puts it nicely when he notes that public justification is connected to the demand for the intelligibility of the social order, “its workings and principles should be well-known and available for public apprehension and scrutiny. People should know and understand the reasons for the basic distribution of wealth, power, authority, and freedom. Society should not be shrouded in mystery, and its workings should not have to depend on mythology, mystification, or a ‘noble lie’”(Waldron: 58). Here public justification is not understood as a rationalized idea of consent so much as a process of accountability and disclosure that is a necessary condition for citizens to exercise their autonomous judgment. Indeed, far from embodying consent, this idea of public justification gives citizens the rational grounds to criticize power or withhold consent. These two ways of looking at public justification, on the one hand as a rationalized idea of consent and on the other as a public process of accountability, run through the literature and are often not clearly distinguished although it is a crucial distinction for sorting through and comparing theories. From responsiveness to restraint Approaches to public justification can focus more on process or on outcome. Process centered theories tend to look at public justification through the lens of democratic citizenship (justification as something citizens owe each other) while outcome 4 oriented approaches focus more directly on the question of legitimacy (justification as a means of getting it right).12 Most theorists of public justification value justification for both reasons but emphasis can be important to the type of theory one endorses in the end. An emphasis on outcome, for example, is often connected with an essentially epistemic view of justification while an emphasis on democratic citizenship sees public justification more as a politico-moral mechanism to navigate pluralism. I will begin with views that emphasize citizenship obligations. What do citizens owe each other? Views run along a continuum from a weak idea of accountability to a strong idea of a “duty of restraint” (Macedo "A Republic of Reasons: Public Reason and the Constitution of the Public Sphere": 9). A principle of accountability holds that citizens and officials must be willing to publically defend and justify their claims and policy preferences. Here the idea is simply that we ought to be able and willing to give an account to each other. “Fairness and respect require an honest effort, on the part of citizens advocating a policy, to justify it to other reasonable citizens who may be approaching the issue from different points of view” (Stout: 65). This has also been called an “ethos of responsiveness”(Thaler). This very minimal idea does not require that citizens necessarily offer accessible, acceptable or sharable reasons only that they offer reasons. Stony silence, lies, “it’s a secret”, “go away”, or “none of your business”, for example, are not appropriate responses to the question, “what is the reason for this legislation?” Citizens show a minimum level of respect for each other by honestly and sincerely responding to each other’s claims, demands and policy endorsements. Furthermore, a principle of accountability or responsiveness establishes an obligation on the part of power holders to give an account of power that can be assessed, criticize and challenged if need be.13 But can anything count as a justification if we offer it as such? Can I offer the phrase “because today is Tuesday” as a justification of my preference for policy A? Most people would add an intelligibility requirement.14 On the surface this seems like commonsense but already we are moving into controversial waters. What is to be considered intelligible and what not can itself be problematic at the margins. An atheist might claim that religious arguments are essentially nonsense and so analogous to “because today is Tuesday”(Green: 659). Or even more problematic, indigenous peoples might offer reasons that fall completely outside modern scientific understandings of the world. Would it be appropriate to simply exclude them or their point of view from our conceptions of public justification? Because of these problems, there are some theorists who resist any substantive description of what citizens owe each other in public justification even such minimal ones as intelligibility. The group of theorist who have the most process based and also minimal conception of public justification I place under the loose heading - borrowed from Duncan Ivison – of post-colonial liberalism (Tully; Ivison). What they often have in common is a rejection of the idea that we could conceive of public justification (even in its hypothetical forms) minus power (Thaler). This rejection in turn is often based on thinking about the place of aboriginal, indigenous and colonized people within a process of public justification. Even such a minimal criterion as intelligibility can be seen as a concept whose boundaries have been set by those with the power to set the terms of the discourse. Because discourses are riddled with power, outcomes never have strong claims to legitimacy and the concept of justification itself (for example, what is to be 5 considered intelligible) is also up for debate. What emerges then is an open ended process of public accountability punctuated by temporary modus vivendi solutions to disagreements (Tully: 147; Ivison: 111). Although post-colonial thinkers would resist a substantive or hard and fast intelligibility requirement, many liberals working within this paradigm would think that intelligibility is actually a very weak requirement.15 Rawls, for example, does not think that an intelligibility restriction is very helpful. He wonders if any sort of public justification or respect is invoked by the fact that “Servitus could understand why Calvin wanted to burn him at the Stake”(Rawls "The Idea of Public Reason Revisited": 138). The thought here is that a liberal-democratic order requires more of citizens than that they respond to each other and that they respond in intelligible ways. Many public justification philosophers insist that reciprocity not simply responsiveness is the standard that citizens should try to meet in public justification. Of course post-colonial thinkers like Tully would claim that open-ended responsiveness contains form of reciprocity. Rather than stipulating in advance the rules of reciprocity, as does Rawls, open-ended responsiveness entertains the possibility that on the one hand, there might be forms of reciprocity that we have never thought of, and on the other, that stipulating the rules of reciprocity in advance might actually be a denial of reciprocity to those outside of the tradition. But the counter argument is that the post-colonial view fails as a model of public justification because nothing ever gets justified. Reciprocity as it is invoked by Rawls and others is intended the restrict reasons - not open the door to any and all reasons - in order to specify what is to count as a justified and so legitimate outcome. Reciprocity and reasonableness Rawls describes the criterion of reciprocity this way: “Our exercise of political power is proper only when we sincerely believe that the reasons we would offer for our political actions…are sufficient, and we also reasonably think that other citizens might also reasonably accept those reasons”(Rawls "The Idea of Public Reason Revisited": 137). Similarly, Gutmann and Thompson note that reciprocity requires that citizens “appeal to reasons or principles that can be shared by fellow citizens…moral reasoning is in this way mutually acceptable” (Gutmann and Thompson: 55) So reciprocity introduces a duty of restraint in public justification. Not everything or anything that we might believe to be true or care about has a place within public justification. The idea here is that any time any of us propose and defend a policy, law, or constitutional order we are proposing and defending a form of coercion. Coercion is made legitimate through seeking a common form of reasoning through which all citizens or all those affected can sign on to the proposal (Nagel: 33). Because we cannot as an empirical matter canvas every single person and also because actual responses of empirical persons can be unreasonable (the traditional problems with consent), we ought to seek to fold others people’s possible consent (or at least their interests, concerns and perspectives) into our very reasoning: only appeal to reasons that you think might be acceptable to fellow citizens understood as reasonable. So we do not have to imagine that our reasons must be acceptable to every possible objection no matter how crazy or unreasonable. But how exactly should we go about sorting reasons into the possibly acceptable and probably unacceptable? And how should we specify reasonable beyond ‘not obviously crazy’? Up until this point there is quite a lot of agreement in the literature that public 6 justification requires the adoption of a form of reasoning that takes other citizens understood as free, equal and reasonable into account. So for example, arguing that “some are worth less than others or that the interests of one group are to count for less than those of others” (Cohen "Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy":415) is out from the start. But the real problems arise when philosophers begin to specify guidelines for restricting reasons to ones that are sharable or that other citizens can sign on to. Early articulations of these guidelines all leant towards some ideal of neutrality (Rawls Political Liberalism; Nagel; Larmore "The Moral Basis of Political Liberalism"). Rawls set the terms of debate. For Rawls, public justification should appeal to public reasons only. Public reasons are political not metaphysical.16 By this he means that we should try as much as possible to refrain from appealing to parts of our personal belief system that involve controversial or simply unshared ideas of truth, the good life, ultimate values and so on. Instead we should seek reasons that are freestanding from our comprehensive views to the extent that we could imagine people who do not share our particular comprehensive view possible endorsing them. There was immediate debate about whether it was possible or desirable to exclude comprehensive not to mention controversial ideas about truth and morality from public debate about important matters. Especially vocal were defenders of religion in the public sphere. Rawls’s original articulation clearly excluded religious reasons from the class of potential public reasons. Indeed, for many liberals until quite recently, public justification was thought to be synonymous with secular reasoning. The first and still most powerful objection to the exclusion of religious reasons was that excluding them effectively excluded religious believers from public justification as it was not always possible, desirable or ethical for religiously minded citizens to check their beliefs at the door when they entered the public sphere (Weithman; Wolterstorff). Rawls revised his original conception of public reason, introducing what he called the wide view of public reason (Rawls "The Idea of Public Reason Revisited"). Reasons drawn from comprehensive views in general and religious views in particular could be introduced into public justification (because to exclude them would be unfair to the holders of such beliefs) but only under the proviso that properly public reasons (i. e., political and in principle sharable) could be produced sometime down the line. The introduction of the proviso has done little to quiet critics of the Rawlsian view. The debate has moved beyond Rawls in significant ways. I will mention only two. The first is that, primarily in response to questions posed by religious thinkers, there is a growing tendency to separate public justification understood as a way in which citizen and elected officials talk to each other about public issues and public justification as a criterion of legitimacy. Today, few liberals insist that religion should be excluded from public debate or that those who appeal to religious arguments must be ready to produce ‘bone fide’ public reasons when called upon. Indeed, since the first objections against public reason on behalf of religion were put forward, there has been a tremendous shift in thinking about religion and its relationship to liberalism all across the spectrum. More than just a concern for public justification has fueled this shift of course. But the result has been a rethinking of some of the assumptions about secularism and the place of religion in the public sphere. But this openness to religion in the public sphere often goes hand in hand with a conception of legitimacy in which religion reasons are problematic. Most liberal theorists of public 7 justification (including religiously oriented ones) would still insist that religious reasons can never be sufficient reasons for coercive law even though we should let citizens and sometimes elected representative argue and publicly defend their political positions in religious terms. A great deal of contemporary debate about religion and public justification is devoted to trying to reconcile these two sides of public justification.17 The second trend coming out of a response to Rawls is a move away from neutrality, sharability, and the exclusion of comprehensive world views as guidelines for achieving reciprocity. A few thinkers have stood by this Rawlsian ideal, however. Stephen Macedo is the torch bearer, one might say, for the unreconstructed Rawlsian position. He insists that acceptable should be understood as sharable in a strong sense. For Macedo public justification contains “the hope that members of large political communities can converge on shared principles and a shared rationale, a public framework of thought for reflecting upon and justifying common principles to one another” (Macedo "A Republic of Reasons: Public Reason and the Constitution of the Public Sphere": 9). Public justification understood as the search for shared public reasons should act as force to counter the centrifugal tendencies of pluralism. Thus for Macedo, public justification represents an aspiration to find common ground and not the claim that we have some clear consensus right now to work from. While Macedo does not insist on a blanket exclusion of religion, he is deeply suspicious of religion in the public sphere (Macedo "In Defense of Liberal Public Reason: Are Slavery and Abortion Hard Cases?"). More common is the view that public justification ought to channel and give expression to pluralism rather than seeking to counter balance pluralism. Macedo calls the former position diversitarian and in this group he places theorists who endorse public justification but are skeptical about the possibility of reasons all could accept. It turns out the group is very diverse, large and I would argue getting larger.18 Chief among diversitarians is Gerald Gaus. Gaus approaches public justification from an epistemic perspective19 and asks ‘when is an individual justified in believing x?’ The answer is that an individual is justified (or has conclusive reasons) in believing x when x fits with all sorts of other things that she believes. Public justification is then understood as the aggregate of conclusive reasons for all those affected. “L is a justified coercive law only if each and every member of the public P has a conclusive reason(s) R to accept L as a requirement” (Gaus and Vallier: 53). The most surprising feature of this view is that a law may be justified without any public exchange of reasons or actual public justification. On the epistemic view, there have to be such reasons, but individuals do not necessarily have to consciously embrace or endorse such reasons. Individuals may be mistaken or inconsistent about what reasons are conclusive for them given the other things they believe. Thus framing justified laws is a philosophical/epistemological problem not a political problem. On this view there is a convergence on an outcome but not on the reasons: reasons are acceptable to each and every citizen but they are not shared. 20 While both Macedo and Gaus have staked out important and prominent positions within the public justification literature, they are both outliers to some extent. Macedo’s stress on consensus seems unrealistic and unfriendly to diversity; Gaus’s epistemic model seems overly formal and oddly private lacking as it does any corresponding idea of the public practice of justification. Today, most contributors to this debate fall somewhere between these two alternatives. On the one hand ‘reasons all can accept’ is usually understood as convergent reasons and not shared reasons and furthermore those 8 convergent reasons may very well reflect people’s deepest unsharable commitments. On the other hand, a shared commitment to reasonableness and reciprocity should govern a collective process justification. Reasonableness and reciprocity are often given loose context dependent definitions. Deliberative models of public justification Rainer First/Gutmann and Thompson/et al ******************************************* Eberle, Christopher J. "Religion and Liberal Democracy." Blackwell Guide to Social and Political Philosophy. Ed. Robert L. Simon. Malden Mass: Blackwell, 2002. 292318. O'Neill, Onora. "The Public Use of Reason." Political Theory 14.4 (1986): 523-51. Simmons, A. John. "Justification and Legitimacy." Ethics 109 (1999): 739-71. Benhabib, Seyla. The Claims of Culture. Equality and Diversity in the Global Era. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992. Print. Bohman, James. "Survey Article: The Coming of Age of Deliberative Democracy." The Journal of Political Philosophy 6 4 (1998): 400-25. Print. Bohman, James, and Henry Richardson. "Liberalism, Deliberative Democracy And "Reasons All Can Accept"." Journal of Political Philosophy 17 3 (2009): 253-74. Print. Button, Mark E. Contract, Culture, and Citizenship: Transformative Liberalism from Hobbes to Rawls. University Park, Penn: The Pennsylvania State Press, 2008. Print. Chambers, Simone. "Deliberative Democratic Theory." Annual Review of Political Science 6 (2003): 307-26. Print. Cohen, Joshua. "Deliberative Democracy." Deliberation, Participation and Democracy: Can the People Govern? Ed. Rosenberg, Shawn W. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2007. 219-36. Print. ---. "Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy." Democracy and Difference: Changing Boundaries of the Political. Ed. Benhabib, Seyla: Princeton University Press, 1996. 407-37. Print. D'Agostino, Fred. Free Public Reason: Making It up as We Go. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996. Print. ---. "Public Justification". 2007. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Eberle, Christopher J. "Religion and Liberal Democracy." Blackwell Guide to Social and Political Philosophy. Ed. Simon, Robert L. Malden Mass: Blackwell, 2002. 292318. Print. ---. Religious Conviction in Liberal Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002. Print. Estlund, David. Democratic Authority: A Philosophical Framework. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008. Print. Forst, Rainer. "The Basic Right to Justification: Towards a Constructivist Conception of Human Rights." Constellations 6 1 (1999): 35-60. Print. ---. "The Rule of Reasons: Three Models of Deliberative Democracy." Ratio Juris 14 4 (2001): 345-78. Print. 9 Freeman, Samuel. ""Public Reason and Political Justification"." Justice and the Social Contract: Essays on Rawlsian Political Philosophy. Ed. Freeman, Samuel. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007. Print. Gaus, Gerald. Contemporary Theories of Liberalism. Thousand Oaks: Sage, 2003. Print. Gaus, Gerald, and Kevin Vallier. "The Roles of Religious Conviction in a Publicly Justified Polity." Philosophy and Social Criticism 35 1-2 (2009): 51-76. Print. Gauthier, David. "Public Reason." Social Philosophy and Policy 12 1 (1995): 19-42. Print. George (ed.), Robert, and Wolfe (ed.) Christopher. Natural Law and Public Reason. Washington D.C.: George University Press, 2000. Print. Green, Abner. "Uncommon Ground: A Review of Political Liberalism by John Rawls and Life's Dominion by Ronald Dworkin." George Washington Law Review 62 (1994): 646-. Print. Gutmann, Amy, and Dennis Thompson. Democracy and Disagreement: Why Moral Conflict Cannot Be Avoided in Politics, and What Should Be Done About It. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1996. Print. Habermas, Jurgen. Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1996. Print. Ivison, Duncan. Postcolonial Liberalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002. Print. Kant, Immanuel. Practical Philosophy. The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant. Ed. Gregor, Mary J. Cambridge UK: Cambridge University Press, 1996. Print. Laden, Anthony Simon. "The House That Jack Built: Thirty Years of Reading Rawls." Ethics 113 (2003): 367-90. Print. ---. "The Justice of Justification." Habermas and Rawls: Disputing the Political. Eds. Freyenhagen, Fabian and James Gordon Finlayson. London: Routledge, 2010. Print. ---. Reasonable Radical: Deliberative Liberalism and the Politics of Identity. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2001. Print. Larmore, Charles. "The Moral Basis of Political Liberalism." The Journal of Philosophy 91 12 (1999): 599-625. Print. ---. The Morals of Modernity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996. Print. Macedo, Stephen. "In Defense of Liberal Public Reason: Are Slavery and Abortion Hard Cases?" Natural Law and Public Reason. Ed. Wolfe, Robert P. George and Christopher. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 2000. Print. ---. "Liberalism and Public Justification." Liberal Virtues, Citizenship Virtues, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism. Ed. Macedo, Stephen. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990. 39-77. Print. ---. "A Republic of Reasons: Public Reason and the Constitution of the Public Sphere." American Political Science Association Annual Meeting. Ed. Print. Mysak, Cheryl. "A Culture of Justification: The Pragmatist's Epistemic Argument for Democracy." Episteme 10 (2008): 94-105. Print. Nagel, Thomas. Equality Adn Partiality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991. Print. Pettit, Philip. Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999. Print. 10 Postema, Gerard J. "Public Practical Reason: An Archeology." Social Philosophy and Policy 12 (1995): 43-86. Print. ---. "Public Practical Reason: Political Practice." Theory and Practice. Ed. Shapiro, Ian and Judith Wagner DeCew. Vol. XXXVII. Nomos. New York: New York University Press, 1995. 345-85. Print. Rawls, John. "The Idea of Public Reason Revisited." The Law of Peoples. Ed. Rawls, John. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1999. 129-80. Print. ---. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press, 1993. Print. Scanlon, T. M. What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University press, 1998. Print. Stout, Jeffrey. Democracy and Tradition. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2004. Print. Talisse, Robert B. Democracy and Moral Conflict. Cambridge: Cambrisge University Press, 2009. Print. Thaler, Mathias. "From Public Reason to Reasonable Accommodation: Negotiating the Place of Religion in the Public Sphere." Diacrítica. Revista do Centro de Estudos Humanísticos da Universidade de Minho 23 2 (2009): 249-70. Print. Tully, James. Public Philosophy in a New Key. Volume I: Democracy and Civic Freedom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008. Print. Vallier, Kevin. "Against Justificatory Liberalism's Accessibility Requirement." Journal of Moral Philosophy (2010). Print. Waldron, Jeremy. "Theoretical Foundations of Liberalism." Liberal Rights. Ed. Walden, Jeremy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993. 35-63. Print. Weithman (ed.), Paul J. Reasonable Pluralism. New York: Garland, 1999. Print. Weithman, paul. Religion and the Obligations of Citizenship. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002. Print. Wolterstorff, Nicholas. "The Role of Religion in Decision and Discussion of Political Issues." Religion in the Public Sphere: The Place of Religious Convictions in Political Debate. Eds. Audi, Robert and Robert Woltersdorff. London: Rowman & Littlefield, 1997. 67-120. Print. Here are examples of similar assessments. “The idea of public justification is the key idea in contemporary liberal-democratic political theory” Fred D'Agostino, Public Justification, 2007. “Justificatory Liberalism is perhaps the dominant brand of political liberal political theory today” Kevin Vallier, "Against Justificatory Liberalism's Accessibility Requirement," Journal of Moral Philosophy (2010).: 1.“The moral core of this (liberal) order is a commitment to public justification.” Stephen Macedo, "Liberalism and Public Justification," Liberal Virtues, Citizenship Virtues, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism, ed. Stephen Macedo (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990).: 40-41. “(P)ublic deliberation and justification - has become increasingly prominent in contemporary political philosophy…It is frequently said to lie at the heart of liberalism.” Gerard J. Postema, "Public Practical Reason: Political Practice," Theory and Practice, ed. Ian and Judith Wagner DeCew Shapiro, vol. XXXVII, Nomos (New York: New York University Press, 1995).:345. “Liberalism rests on a certain view about the justification of social arrangements.” Jeremy Waldron, "Theoretical Foundations of Liberalism," Liberal Rights, ed. Jeremy Walden (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993).: 36. “Contemporary Liberals, as I understand them, have a special commitment to public justification.” Duncan Ivison, Postcolonial Liberalism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002).:14. “Today liberal political theory is increasingly dominated by the question of justification.” Mark E Button, Contract, Culture, and 1 11 Citizenship: Transformative Liberalism from Hobbes to Rawls (University Park, Penn: The Pennsylvania State Press, 2008).: 37. “The norm of public justification…has been a focal point of recent liberal political theory generally” Christopher J. Eberle, "Religion and Liberal Democracy," Blackwell Guide to Social and Political Philosophy, ed. Robert L. Simon (Malden Mass: Blackwell, 2002).: 294 2 John Rawls, "The Idea of Public Reason Revisited," The Law of Peoples, ed. John Rawls (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1999).: 155. This view of justification was already present in A Theory of Justice. See especially p. 581. Jurgen Habermas, Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1996). 3 For similar distinctions see Anthony Laden (philosophical justification vs. political justification) and Christopher Eberle (rational justification vs. public justification). Anthony Simon Laden, "The Justice of Justification," Habermas and Rawls: Disputing the Political, eds. Fabian Freyenhagen and James Gordon Finlayson (London: Routledge, 2010). Christopher J. Eberle, Religious Conviction in Liberal Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002).: 63-66 4 For a reading of the whole liberal tradition through the lens of justification, see Gerald Gaus, Contemporary Theories of Liberalism (Thousand Oaks: Sage, 2003). 5 Justification has also become central to liberal moral philosophy which seeks to offer a general account of right action as well as legitimate law. See especially T. M. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University press, 1998). In this essay I focus primarily on the justification of coercive law and not right action. 6 It is hard to know where to start. For some general overviews see: Gerard J. Postema, "Public Practical Reason: An Archeology," Social Philosophy and Policy 12 (1995). Paul J. Weithman (ed.), Reasonable Pluralism (New York: Garland, 1999). Fred D'Agostino, Free Public Reason: Making It up as We Go (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996). 7 Again it is hard to know where to start. For some general overviews see Joshua Cohen, "Deliberative Democracy," Deliberation, Participation and Democracy: Can the People Govern?, ed. Shawn W. Rosenberg (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2007), Simone Chambers, "Deliberative Democratic Theory," Annual Review of Political Science 6 (2003). James Bohman, "Survey Article: The Coming of Age of Deliberative Democracy," The Journal of Political Philosophy 6.4 (1998). 8 Jeremy Waldron, for example, places public justification at the center of his conception of liberalism but endorses a majoritarian view of democracy that stands opposed to many aspects of deliberative democracy. And Gaus endorses a very strong idea of public justification but believes that citizen deliberation is not the best way to actually achieve justification. 9 Examples of theorist who could be said to work within a Rawlsian framework are Stephan Macedo, Anthony Laden and Samuel Freeman. See especially Stephen Macedo, "In Defense of Liberal Public Reason: Are Slavery and Abortion Hard Cases?," Natural Law and Public Reason, ed. Robert P. George and Christopher Wolfe (Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 2000). Anthony Simon Laden, Reasonable Radical: Deliberative Liberalism and the Politics of Identity (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2001), Samuel Freeman, ""Public Reason and Political Justification"," Justice and the Social Contract: Essays on Rawlsian Political Philosophy, ed. Samuel Freeman (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007). 10 There is a Natural Law conception of public reason and public justification but as it does not fall within the liberal conception, I leave it out of the list. See especially Robert George (ed.) and Wolfe (ed.) Christopher, Natural Law and Public Reason (Washington D.C.: George University Press, 2000). 11 Hypothetical consent is also sometimes called normative consent. See David Estlund, Democratic Authority: A Philosophical Framework (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008).: 10 12 In addition to legitimacy and citizenship, Bohman and Richardson note that justification is also valued as a model of authority and of course philosophical justification on its own. See James Bohman and Henry Richardson, "Liberalism, Deliberative Democracy And "Reasons All Can Accept"," Journal of Political Philosophy 17.3 (2009). 13 It is tempting to call this a principle of publicity because at its core is the simple requirement of making reasons and justifications public. The term ‘publicity principle,’ however is over used and over burdened and so I do not appeal to it in this context. 14 This is as far, for example, as Jeremy Waldron goes. See Waldron, "Theoretical Foundations of Liberalism.": 44. Although he places public justification at the very core of a liberal order he does not think that the process itself is likely to result in a convergence on mutually acceptable reasons. 12 15 I do not wish to imply that post-colonial liberals think that nonsense has a place within public justification. They do think that justifications need to make sense. They simply resist defining in advance what that might mean -leaving it open to participants to struggle with that question. The thought here is there might be non-western ways to justify claims that should not be ruled out from the beginning. 16 Rawls’s discussion of public reason is rich and complex and I can only touch on it very superficially here. For an in depth discussion see Anthony Simon Laden, "The House That Jack Built: Thirty Years of Reading Rawls," Ethics 113 (2003), Freeman, ""Public Reason and Political Justification"." Also see the special issue of the Fordham Law Review (April 2004, 72:5) and a special issue of Philosophy & Social Criticism (September 2004, 30: 5-6) devoted to Rawls and public reason. 17 For a good discussion of these issue see the special issue of Philosophy & Social Criticism (September 2009, 35:1-2) on religion and the public sphere 18 Macedo includes Jeremy Waldron, Christopher Eberle, Jeffrey Stout and Gerald Gaus. I would add most theorist of deliberative democracy with the exception of Habermas. 19 Two other philosophers who take an explicitly epistemic view are David Estlund and Robert Talisse. Estlund, Democratic Authority: A Philosophical Framework, Robert B. Talisse, Democracy and Moral Conflict (Cambridge: Cambrisge University Press, 2009). 20 Drawing on social choice theory, Gaus and Vallier add that broad public deliberation is counterproductive to public justification because most citizens do not, as an empirical fact, have the epistemic capacity to weigh and assess other people’s claims. Gerald Gaus and Kevin Vallier, "The Roles of Religious Conviction in a Publicly Justified Polity," Philosophy and Social Criticism 35.1-2 (2009).: 6569 13