Wittgenstein's Language Games Wittgenstein, in speaking about religion and religious belief does so from the perspective of the language-game analysis. This picture of language asserts that the meaning of words and phrases are determined by the context, or game, in which it plays a role. For Wittgenstein, there are infinitely many language-games corresponding to innumerable situations in life. The language-game itself is regulated by depth grammar. Depth grammar is what makes the language-game possible, by setting the boundaries of what can and cannot be said. Words or activities within a language-game take on meaning that is exclusive to that particular language-game. Hence, what is meant by 'belief or 'truth' is different in the religious language-game t h a n t h e s c i e n c e l a n g u a g e g a m e Wittgenstein argues in his‘ Lectures and Conversations ’that the depth grammar that regulates the religious language-game is different than the depth grammar that regulates science. He also postulates that as long as the primary goal of a particular language-game is different from another, they are immune to criticism from each other. Science, which is concerned with determining how the world is ordered, has a distinctly different goal in mind than the religious languagegame which is concerned with questions of an existential nature. The religious languagegame has merit and is immune from science because it asks important questions that science is unable to touch. It serves a human need that is unable to be fulfilled anywhere else. What then is the nature of the religious language-game, what sort of activity takes place in this game? As with all language-games the meaning of the words within the religious language-game is determined by the language-game itself. The word 'belief' is important both in the religious language-game and the science language-game. Where those who have attempted to prove or disprove God's existence rationally have failed, is assuming that the word 'belief' is identical in both language-games. This is clearly not the case. Belief in science is something completely different than belief in religion. When someone says "I believe that the world is not flat" something different is being said than "I believe in God, the Father Almighty. Creator of Heaven and Earth," Under the guise of the referential theory of language, which Wittgenstein asserted in his earlier work the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, the meaning of the word 'belief' would be meaningful only if it referred to an object or fact in the world. This theory does not allow for the same word to have different meanings depending on the context. Wittgenstein's language-game analysis avoids this problem and offers an alternative that truly mirrors the way in which language operates in the world. It follows from this that words in different language-games could have different meanings. Therefore, the word 'belief' can be demonstrated to have a different meaning in the scientific language-game than the religious language-game. If it can be shown that these are different versions of 'belief' and that the rational justifications for God's existence or 1 Wittgenstein's Language Games non-existence rest upon a scientific meaning of 'belief' then it can be shown that these proofs play no role and are irrelevant to the religious language -game. What then does 'belief' mean in the respective language-games? To say that one believes something in science is to argue a claim on the basis of evidence or proof. A belief that the sun is the centre of the solar system is a scientific claim. There is corresponding empirical data that justify this claim. An individual is able to cite reasons for this belief and postulate theories in accordance with it. For religion, belief is not something based on evidence or proof at all. To say that "I believe in God" is not a claim based on empirical data or reasons. It is something that is arrived at when one goes through the process of answering the key existential questions. 'Belief' in the religions language-game is not reasonable as 'belief' in the scientific language-game is, nor does it pretend to be. Religions belief is not based on rationality, but how one sees the world. Here Wittgenstein makes a key differentiation between himself and Kierkegaard. It was Kierkegaard's claim that holding a religious belief was irrational. Wittgenstein develops the position that a belief in the religious languagegame is not rational or irrational. Rationality does not play a role in the religious language-game. Speaking about how science and religion differ on this point of rationality, Wittgenstein notes that; “You could also say that where we are reasonable, they are not reasonable - meaning they don't use reason here.” (Lectures p. 59) If this point is granted, then at any juncture if science uses reason as grounds for an objection to it, it must conform to the depth grammar of that particular language-game for if it does not it cannot be spoken of meaningfully. What results from this conclusion is that the proof for the existence and non-existence of God plays no role in the religious language-game. St. Anselm's ontological proof plays no role in the religious language-game. Intuitively this is not entirely surprising. When one is asked the question; “Do you believe in God, and if so why?" and the ontological proof is given as a reply, the inquirer remains unsatisfied. Instead, what they are likely searching for is an explanation of how that individual sees the world. A suitable answer may be that "The world makes more sense with God than without." This reply does not rest upon evidence or proof, but is rather the result of an individual searching for an answer to the existential questions about the ‘riddles of life,’ and how one develops a religious point of view to address these questions. Conversely, the counter evidence provided against God’s existence is subject to the same kind of scrutiny. Objections, like the problem of evil, that rest upon empirical evidence or reason can no longer 2 Wittgenstein's Language Games be considered within the religious language -game. However viable they may be in terms of reasonability, it is irrelevant to the religious languagegame. Clearly, Wittgenstein has placed science and religion into separate spheres, unable to criticize one another. A key distinction must be made here as to what Wittgenstein means by the religious language-game. One who has developed a religious point of view need not partake in organised religion. Following Wittgenstein's thought, the religious language-game is not an inclusive subset of organized religion or Christianity. This is not what Wittgenstein is connotating when he speaks of a religious language-game. It may very well be the case that certain individuals adopt organised religion within the religious language-game. Christianity or other organized religions may serve as a vehicle for answering the questions of life. However an individual may be playing the religious language-game and not take part in any organised religion. If an individual, outside of organised religion addresses the existential questions necessary in developing a religious point of view, then they indeed are playing the religious language-game. Similar1y, one need not believe in God to take part in the religious language-game. If one, after developing a religious point of view, sees the world making more sense without God than with God, then they are playing the religious languagegame. Again, all that is required is for one to seek answers to the "riddles of life." Conversely, it is also possible for those within organised religion to not be playing the religious language-game. People who attend church services or functions, or even believe in God may be outside the religious language-game. If for example, a person were to blindly accept God in his life without ever inquiring about God's nature or his own existence, this person is not playing the religious language-game. If the existential questions are not asked and the religious point of view is not developed, then, consistent with Wittgenstein, it can be said that the person is not playing the religious language-game. It is in this way that an interesting paradox of a person being ‘religious’ but not playing the religious language-game emerges. Another more important example of someone who is ‘religious’ or a theist not playing the religious language-game are those who attempt to prove God’s existence rationally. Anselm and Aquinas, despite their strong faith in God’s existence introduced proofs for God's existence that have nothing at all to do with the religious point of view. As demonstrated in this paper, these proofs are given from the 3 Wittgenstein's Language Games perspective of the scientific language-game. These proofs are not religious, and therefore fall under the scrutiny of science. Criticism is possible within a language-game, and therefore these proofs based upon scientific reasoning are subject to the same rules as other scientific theories. As such, principles such as Occam’s Razor easily refute the claims made by these proofs. Therefore, just as both science and religion dismiss superstition, both the religions language-game and the scientific language-game reject the rational proofs for God's existence. Which leads into the rational reasons for disproving God's existence. The same mistake that the theist makes by asserting God's existence on the basis of rational proofs is also made by the atheist who bases reasoning as an objection to God's existence. Atheism is no more scientific than theism. From a rational view point it has been shown that belief in a Divine Being is irrational. Kierkegaard was not mistaken about this. What he and the others are mistaken of, according to Wittgenstein, is applying rationality to the religious language-game. Religious and non-religious belief has nothing at all to do with rationality and those who claim atheism based upon science are no more justified than those who base belief on rational proofs. In conclusion, Wittgenstein’s language-game analysis, as it applies to religious belief, allows one to solve an age old problem. The logical contradiction that exists between an all-perfect God and the problem of evil has now been solved. Belief in God is no longer subject to proof or evidence or empirical justification. The religious point of view is how one answers the existential questions, or how one sees the world. The result may be individualistic and perhaps enter into relativity, but it does give religion immunity from the assaults of science. Like the rest of Wittgenstein’s language-game analysis, this theory of religion is consistent with our human needs. Clearly, today’s society relies largely upon the theories and principles of science. Wittgenstein is not denying science, as much as he is preserving the rightful place of religion as an important part of life. Essential to being human is coming to terms with the existential questions and developing a religious point of view. Science can tell us about the world, but we need the religious point of view to tell us about our existence. As Wittgenstein illustrated in the Tractatus, paragraph 6.52; "We feel that even when all possible scientific questions have been answered, the problems of life remain completely untouched." Language Games by B M Sandin - 1999 4