Chapter Forty PROFESSIONAL STANDARDS AND ETHICS Carol W. Lewis and Bayard L. Catron Public service is a public trust. If there is anything unique about public service, it derives from this proposition. The idea goes back at least to Thomas Jefferson in this country, and it can be traced to other historical periods and other cultures as well. For example, in a seventeenth-century Chinese manual on local administration (Huang, 1984), the author, himself a local administrator, describes the inauguration of a new magistrate, listing his duties and emphasizing that “he should conduct public business with complete objectivity and with no interference from his personal preferences” (p.146). Buddhism teaches a similar lesson: “If an important minister of state neglects his duties, works for his own profit or accepts bribes, it will cause a rapid decay of public morals” (Bukkyo Dendo Kyokai, 1987, p.468). For a public administrator, upholding the public trust means faithfully executing one’s duties, as determined through the political process, in support of the public interest or the collective good. The first provision in the federal Principles of Ethical Conduct for Government Officers and Employees (Office of Government Ethics, 1992) (first issued by executive order in 1989) is “Public service is a public trust, requiring employees to place loyalty to the Constitution, the laws and ethical principles above private gain” (p.1). Public administrators spend public dollars, and they wield the power of the state in carrying out their role. Because of this, it is often said that they should be held to a higher standard than others. Numerous opinion polls confirm that the public does hold government officials to a higher standard (for example, see Bowman, 1990). They also suggest, however, that in the minds of the public, government officials do not necessarily meet that higher standard. Over many years, Gallup polls have asked respondents to rate various professionals’ honesty and ethical standards (“Survey Data on Ethics,” 1993, p.29). Only 14 percent of respondents rated state officeholders’ standards as high in 1993, compared to 11 percent in the initial poll in 1977. Comparable figures for local officeholders were 19 percent in 1993 and 14 percent in 1977. A majority of respondents ranked both state and local officials’ honesty and ethical standards as average in 1993. Judging from our own experience in conducting a large number of ethics training programs, public administrators agree by about three-to-one margin that they should be held to a higher standard. This does not imply a different standard of morality but rather a more scrupulous adherence to accepted standards. On the whole, administrators and citizens share the same fundamental ethical values and perspectives (see Goodsell, 1994, pp.103-131; Lewis, 1990), although their relative importance does vary. In this chapter, we will discuss a number of values and principles that are particularly important for public service. First, we clarify two basic approaches to government ethics – legal compliance and the “aspirational” approach, which involves an appeal to ethical principles. Next we discuss character ethics and some key virtues and vices. Then we describe ethical decision making, which, we argue, makes use of all these approaches but must ultimately depend on ethical reasoning and judgment. We conclude with some practical suggestions for improving ethical conduct in public agencies. Two Approaches: Compliance and Aspirational Ethics From the founding of the republic, it has been accepted that we need both virtuous public servants who aspire to the highest norms of conduct and also control mechanisms to ensure accountability and the satisfaction of some minimally accepted standard (Thompson, 1985). This dual goal is reflected in the founders’ reliance upon formal government arrangements to supplement personal virtue. In a famous quotation, James Madison (Federalist 51) noted, “If men were angels, no government would be necessary. If angels were to govern men, neither external nor internal controls would be necessary. In forming a government which is to be administered by men over men, the great difficulty lies in this: you must first enable the government to control the governed; and in the next place oblige it to control itself.” The Compliance Approach and the Rule of Law The compliance approach to ethics in government provides controls on the conduct of public officials; thus, it serves as an important check on the substantial power they wield. All federal officials take an oath to uphold the Constitution, and all public officials at every level explicitly or implicitly agree to act in accordance with the law. To act otherwise is widely regarded as an abuse of office (see Lewis, 1991, pp. 38-40). Thus, legal compliance as an ethical obligation draws upon such virtues as truth-telling, promise-keeping, and fidelity. In the two decades since the Watergate scandal, and especially during the past decade, there has been a veritable explosion of so-called ethics laws at every level of government, creating more and more stringent conflict-of-interest, financial disclosure, and other requirements applying to more and more public servants (Congressional Research Service, 1994). Conflict of interest, perhaps the most generic type of public corruption, is typically proscribed by both professional and government codes and statues. According to a survey conducted by the Council of State Governments (1993), many specific forms of conflict of interest are proscribed by a majority of the states. Prohibitions against bribery, using public position for personal benefit, and misuse of confidential government information are among the most frequent. A majority of states limit outside income in some way, and in 1990, limits were added to the federal Principles of Ethical Conduct as well. Postemployment restrictions (limitations on what public officials can do after leaving government work) are also becoming increasingly common. One interesting provision that is appearing increasingly in ethics laws in the admonition to avoid the appearance of impropriety. While this is somewhat amorphous and difficult to codify, it is of great importance in maintaining (or restoring) public confidence and trust in government. More than one-quarter of the one hundred largest U.S. cities and more than dozen states in some way address the appearance of impropriety, according to a survey we conducted in 1994. Attorneys general, ethics commissions, and municipal attorneys were asked whether the appearance of impropriety on the part of elected or appointed officials and other public employees was prohibited, constrained, or in any way addressed by their jurisdictions. We found that such provisions appear in local ordinances, prevailing state statutes, case law, executive orders, regulations, civil service and agency rules, collective bargaining agreements, and other sources. Also, officers of the court are enjoined by Canon II to meet an appearance standard, as are members of many professional associations. A visitor from another planet might reasonably suppose that all this legislative activity has been in response to a virulent epidemic of public corruption, but is not the case. It is not even clear that there has been a general decline in I cal behavior, although this is a common perception reflected in public opinion veys. "The fact that higher proportions of the public are now professing con about a perceived decline in ethical standards hardly constitutes proof (that] ; dards are actually declining" (Ladd, 1993, p. 20). One possible indicator of J lic officials' conduct might be the number of corruption indictments. Department of Justice statistics show federal corruption indictments of stat, ficials increased from lOin 1970 to 71 in 1989, and indictments of local offi rose from 26 to 269 in the same period (Feigenbaum, Pockrass, Chapman, Lenzer, 1991, p. 4). These are large percentage increases, even though the ac numbers of indictments are rather small, but this increase could simply re more rigorous laws and/ or more vigorous investigation and prosecution efj rather than a greater incidence of corruption. Corresponding to the increase in ethics laws has been an increase in pr< sional ethics codes, like the code of the American Society for Public Adminii tion (ASPA), adopted in 1985 and revised in 1994; the Government Fina Officers Association's code; and rule 1.1 of the American Bar Association's M, Rules of Professional Conduct (see Gorlin, 1990, for a collection of professi, codes). The appeal to professionalism draws on selfawareness, honor, and r( tation. There has also been significant increase in ethics coverage in professi< graduate programs in public administration (Catron and Denhardt, 1993). other aspect of professionalism, "self-policing" as a collegial responsibility am members of a profession, is represented by the oversight and enforcement 1 cedures of the International City/County Management Association, which had an ethics code since 1924. The dramatic increase in the compliance approach to promoting ethic government is no doubt partly due to a heightened moralism in the broader ture, a moralism paradoxically linked to the debasement of ethics. In these culiar times, ethics seems to have lost much of its original meaning. Politicians I the "ethics card" to gain advantage over a political opponent, and the "blc game" has replaced meaningful discourse on policy. Commentators wield ethics club to trounce an exposed hypocrite or transgressor, and journalistic pr go to the 'Junkyard dog" for "protecting the public's right to know" (ofter appealing to its most prurient interests). All of this-which in another time wc have been considered improper conduct-contributes to public cynicism ; actually undermines ethics. It is far from clear that increasingly stringent ethics laws make people m ethical, and in fact, they may have a counterintuitive effect. For at least the reasons, external ethics requirements subvert or at least distract from personal responsibility. First, the floor set by law or rule may be accepted as the norm in- stead of the minimum standard; because norms guide or govern conduct, this is a considerable defect. Second, the more rules there are, the less one may be tempted to think about positive ethical behavior and instead focus on compliance--on "how to stay out of trouble," as the title of one government ethics guide puts it (Office of Government Ethics, 1989). And third, the more burdensome and punitive an organization's rules, the more members may work to minimize their adverse impact, thus increasing perverse behaviors and outcomes. The U.S. Department of Defense's 1993 ethics directive runs over 180 pages; the ethics business has be- come almost as cumbersome as the procurement process. The tendency in the compliance approach is to reduce ethics to law. When ethics provisions are put into law, they are transformed from "ought" into "must," and discretion and flexibility are reduced. The issue of the relationship between ethics and the law goes back a long time (Hart, 1961 ). Sophocles' Antzgone is one classical statement of the need to distinguish ethics from law. The Roman states- man Tacitus saw a connection: "The more corrupt the state, the more numerous the laws" (Annalj~ bk. 3, sec. 27). Chief Justice Earl Warren's well-known formulation states that "in civilized life, law floats in a sea of ethics. Each is in- dispensable to civilization. Without law, we should be at the mercy of the least scrupulous. Without ethics, law could not exist" (Cook, 1963, p. 453). The attempt to substitute rules for judgment undermines respect for ethical principles (discussed in the next section) and denies what we believe is the central importance of reason and reflection in ethical decision making (discussed in the second section below). The Aspirational Approach and the Appeal to Principle The approach here is to enunciate high-minded principles, affirm one's commitment to them, and through example and leadership motivate others to adhere to them as well. Nowhere in history is the aspirational approach to ethics illustrated more elegantly and eloquently than in the oath of the Athenian city-state: We will never bring disgrace to this our city by any act of dishonesty or cowardice, nor ever desert our suffering cotnrades in the ranks; We will ever strive for the ideals and sacred things of the city; both alone and with many; We will revere and obey the city's laws and do our best to incite to a like respect and reverence those who are prone to annul or set them at naught; We will unceasingly seek to quicken the sense of public duty; That thus, in all these ways, we will transmit this city not only not less, but greater, better and more beautiful than it was transmitted to us. In our era, the notion of serving the public interest is often used in this aspirational way. For example, the Josephson Institute's "Ethics Pledge for Elected officials" identifies the duty to serve the public interest as placing "democratic principles and public good over all other allegiances and considerations" and respecting "the will of the citizenry." Democratic values as they have evolved in the American republic include impartiality, justice, and due process to sustain a nation of law (Rohr, 1989; Rosenbloom, 1992); liberty, equity, and human dignity; accountability (and hence disclosure); promoting a responsive process that is accessible to the citizens and citizenship rights and obligations, such as informed participation and compassion. Ethical principles and duties reflect behavioral goals and responsibilities and are linked to our vision of a good society and worthy relationships. Ethical principles may be procedural or substantive; they may center on sacrosanct ideas such as those embodied in the Bill of Rights or focus foremost on results and outcomes. The four time-honored fundamental ethical principles listed below are designed to guide behavior by harmonizing duties and values without dictating the specific resolution (which is left to the ethical decision maker's reason and reflection). 1. Reciprocity signals respect for human dignity and rights and avoiding doing harm; the Golden Rule is a familiar example. 2. Reversibility (or empathy) calls for seeing oneself as subject or victim-in other words, trading places or walking in someone else's shoes. 3. Utility (or net good results, however defined) urges concern for the number of people affected by an action and for how deeply they are affected, in both the long and short term. 4. Universality and consistency mean blocking arbitrary, haphazard, or unscrupulous behavior in favor of impartiality, fairness, and predictability. Character Ethics-Some Virtues and Vices Ethical principles are often abstract and remote, and it is sometimes difficult to see how they apply to particular situations. Another, ancient approach to ethics emphasizes the role of character in determining right and wrong in many complex, idiosyncratic situations. Here we merely summarize some virtues and vices that we believe are particularly relevant to public service. Public Service Virtues Four virtues are discussed below-humility, moral imagination, courage, and prudence. Humility. Because administrators are temporary stewards of public authority, a certain humility is a valuable trait for them-increasing their self-restraint-especially when human fallibility is conceded. (On the concept of stewardship in public administration, see Kass, 1990; Morgan and Kass, 1991; and Frederick- son, 1994.) In its 1985 code, the ASPN.s formulation of this virtue obliges members to "serve the public with respect, concern, courtesy, and responsiveness, recognizing that service to the public is beyond service to oneself" (American Society for Public Administration, 1985). Although it is undesirable to compromise important ethical principles, it is also undesirable to insist rigidly and exclusively upon one's own personal principles at great cost to others. Public office should not be a bully pulpit for administrators to promote only their own ethical viewpoints. The virtue of humility implies valuing accommodation, inclusivity, and empathy and seeking reconciliation of contending views. Note, however, that an administrator's ethical concerns do count (or else personal integrity no longer does). Moral Sensitivity and Imagination. Serious conflicts and dilemmas are endemic to ethics problems; one function of the moral imagination is to generate creative resolutions of these impasses. By redefining dilemmas as part of the process of mediating and reconciling disputes, administrators can influence outcomes without taking exclusive ownership of public affairs. The best solutions are not compromises but novel, fully adequate responses to the situation. Instead of being satisfied with doing as little harm as possible, an administrator with moral imagination seeks to satisfy as many ethical values and principles as possible; thus, a creative response to complexity is especially valued. A related function of the moral imagination is empathy, the capacity to experience from a distance the effects of an action or decision on others, including future effects. Moral sensitivity and empathy may be thought of as the conceptual equivalents in philosophy and psychology of the public interest. As Adam Smith (1976) (who thought of himself as a moral philosopher, not the father of capitalism) wrote in his Theory of Moral Sentiments, empathy is the source of our capacity to act ethically. In A Theory of Justice, John Rawls (1971) proposes that the ethical decision maker should don a "veil of ignorance" in order to downplay self-interest and promote empathy. The ability to generalize to a broad or universal and abstract plane is prized in Kailt's "categorical imperative" and occupies the highest level of moral reasoning in Lawrence Kohlberg's formulation ( 1981) of cognitive development. Universal application of moral reasoning was a basic argument of the American suffrage movement, formally inaugurated in Seneca Falls in 1848, at the f1rst Women's Rights Convention held in the United States, by the signing of the Declaration if Sentiments, which states, "He [man J has created a false public sentiment, by giving to the world a different code of morals for men and women, by which moral delinquencies which exclude women from society, are not only tolerated but deemed of little account in man." (For critical feminist perspectives, see Gilligan, 1982; Gilligan, Ward, Taylor, and Bardige, 1988; Hirschmann, 1989; and Okin, 1989.) Moral Courage. Often public officials are not in doubt about the right thing to do but are reluctant to do it because it is not popular, convenient, or comfortable. Sometimes there is a personal cost or risk associated with doing the right thing, and the temptation is very great to rationalize inaction or avoid the situation al- together. But a commitment to doing the right thing is rarely an intolerable bur- den; one's career is at stake less frequently than one's integrity. Capability and risk are relevant to making a judgment in such situations, and they usefully distinguish courage from rashness or heroism beyond the call of duty. Prudence. This is the basic practical virtue, even though today it usually connotes little more than self-interested and expedient action, which might or might not be ethical (Dobel, 1990). A traditional virtue familiar to the founders of the republic, prudence can be traced to the ancient Greeks, for whom it embodied the wisdom to see the right thing', coupled with the will to do it. Moral, democratic public leadership requires ethical compromises, not compromise of ethics (Guy, 1990, p. 19). It values principled judgment, responsively accommodates democratic inclusion over exclusive purity, and proposes principled, creative resolutions when rival claims and true dilemmas threaten to create personal or collective ethical gridlock or damaging exclusion. Public Service Vices Four ethical deficiencies in particular shadow public leaders today. Each has a distinct character and a different sort of remedy. Self-Righteousness. When power is combined with zealotry and self-righteousness (what might be called the Ollie North syndrome), our constitutional democracy is threatened. But the problem has a more intimate face as well: survey after survey consistently finds that people view themselves as more ethical than others in their profession or organization, and they view those in their own group as more ethical than others outside the group. Too often we regard ethical problems as applying mainly to other people. Self-reflection, together with a habit of applying most moral judgments only to oneself, is the best antidote for self-righteousness. Self-Indulgence. Most corruption scandals are due to garden-variety greed for money and/or power. This represents self-indulgence, in which an individual is unable or unwilling to resist temptation. (Abuses are also occasionally the result of ignorance, which may be an explanation but rarely a justification.) The best way to protect against self-indulgence at the personal level is to marshal the virtue of self-restraint. Institutionally, the remedy is to design effective and humane accountability and control mechanisms. Self-Protection. Escaping blame and hiding behind the authority of others (epitomized by the Nuremberg defense of "only following orders") represents an abandonment of personal responsibility and judgment. For moral leaders, fixing the blame should not preempt fixing the problem. Remedies for this def1ciency include moral courage, mentoring, ethics training, and accessible confidential re- sources such as the federal designated agency ethics officer, ethics commissions, and safeguards for whistle blowers and the accused. Self-Deception. Perhaps the most widespread ethical deficiency (and the most insidious one) is self-deception. We often mask real but ignoble motives even from ourselves. The remedy is self-reflection, self-knowledge, and the courage to face the truth about falling. short of one's personal standards (which is preferable to compounding the offense with hypocrisy). Making Ethical Decisions The various approaches we have discussed all have a role to play in promoting the ethical conduct of public officials. Understanding and trying to accommodate the different basic perspectives on ethics is not an argument for situational or relativistic ethics. It is crucial to administrators' functioning as trustees or stewards, however. Administrators exercising public power in a democracy are obligated to be responsive and accountable to the people. We believe that minimum standards, high-minded principles, and a virtuous character are not by themselves adequate to ensure that this obligation is met, given the complexity of the modern political environment and the demands placed on public administrators. Thoughtful reflection and judgment are also crucial and distinctive aspects of ethical conduct. Ethical Reasoning and Judgment Public administrators often face incongruent responsibilities and conflicting claim As unfamiliar situations, organizational and technological impersonality, and professional and public power intensify pressures, public servants can count on el countering true ethical dilemmas, in which a well-intentioned person of strong moral character is troubled by opposing claims and competing ethical values an principles. In such circumstances, prudent and pragmatic decision makers apply ethical reasoning to resolve their dilemma. Ethics in this context refers to making systematic, reasoned judgments about right and wrong and, equally important, taking responsibility for them. The reasoning underlying a resolution, decision, or agreement is important in aiding understanding about ourselves and others; probably even more than the answer we arrive at, our reasoning informs us about who we are, what we value, and how we are likely to resolve future dilemmas. Making decisions in authentic, coherent ethical terms is essential to maintaining one's personal integrity. So is taking responsibility for one's decisions and being held accountable for them. Judgment and responsibility help to distinguish between loyalty and obedience; loyalty is generally considered an ethic, virtue, obedience is not. Moreover, integrity is vitally instrumental to a democracy that relies upon citizens' voluntary compliance and willing participation. The public's confidence and trust in government depend in no small degree on the integrity they attribute to their leaders and institutions. According to our concept of ethics, no ethical resolution is permanent no can it be provided by someone else. Nonetheless, standards and expectations are operative in public service. The mix of "oughts" has been catalogued elsewhere (for example, see Council of State Governments, 1993;Josephson Institute, 199C Mertins and others, 1994; Office of Government Ethics, 1992; Stewart and Sprinthall, 1993). The priorities by which obligations and responsibilities are ranked are more troublesome; this is at the very heart of ethical dilemmas. Ethical imperatives may be framed in terms of not doing harm, easing or reducing injury; accounting for stakes and stakeholders, and taking care of the de pendent and vulnerable. But the many values and principles of public service ma' dictate contradictory actions, creating a moral dilemma. The burden-and beauty-of ethics is that there is no user-friendly menu-driven program to substitute for personal judgment and responsibility. Elements of Ethical Decision Making From the elements discussed above, we can see that ethical decision making exercises the virtues, refrains from the vices, and starts by scanning and assessing the ethical claims at stake. These claims include roles (and the associated appropriate behaviors), affected parties and interests, values and virtues, and principles and duties. Many decision-making models developed for public service (Cooper, 1990; Lewis, 1991) and business (N ash, 1990; Rion, 1990) stress adequate information and feedback so that claims are neither neglected nor misunderstood. A useful decision-making model also allows for gradations and modifications. Decision makers routinely apply different approaches and perspectives, depending upon the seriousness of the case and whether the issue is significant or trivial, novel or common. Various types of responsibility are factored in. According to Cooper (1990), objective responsibilities are externally imposed expectations and involve obligations to elected officials, superiors, and the citizenry. Subjective responsibilities are internally imposed and derive from personal feelings, beliefs, experiences, and values. When objective and subjective responsibilities collide, as they are bound to do, the public administrator confronts an ethical dilemma. The values of accountability, responsiveness, and detecting and correcting error require that considerable effort be expended to resolve it. The "publicity test," an evaluative test regularly applied to ethical choices (Rawls, 1971, p. 133), is particularly useful in promoting the administrator's obligation to avoid the appearance of impropriety and to promote public confidence and trust. The idea behind the publicity test is captured nicely in this advice from Thomas Jefferson in a letter written in 1785 to his nephew and ward: "Whenever you are to do a thing, tho' it can never be known but to yourself ask yourself how you would act were all the world looking at you, and act accordingly" (1975, p. 381 ). Several variations on this theme can provide administrators with a useful check of the ethical adequacy of their contemplated actions. The mirror test for integrity asks, "What kind of person do I admire and want to be?" The publicity test for accountability asks, 'Am I willing to read about this in the newspaper? Tell my family?" The visceral-reaction test for implementation and authenticity asks, 'Am I willing and/ or likely to follow through? How does this feel? Can I live with it?" The next step is ethical action that is both publicly defensible and personally supportable on ethical grounds. Ethical actions are firmly rooted in moral values and principles that express what is right and important in relationships and society. Aristotle defined ethics as a practical field rooted in habitual action of a moral character. Finally, to be adequate, ethics must be learning oriented. Actors must pay careful attention to the results of their actions and adjust their conduct accordingly over time. Summary We have discussed several approaches to ethics in public service-the compliance approach, aspirational ethics and the appeal to principle, character ethics, and the reliance on ethical reasoning. All are relevant and appropriate in specific instances as public administrators seek to fulfill their responsibilities in an increasingly demanding environment. There are also many things public administrators can do to improve ethical conduct within their organizations. Here is a sample from the ethics handbook of the International City / County Management Association (Kellar, 1988): Set the tone for a high standard of conduct by clearly articulating the organization's values. Make ethics a part of employee orientation and training programs. Include ethics concerns in performance evaluations and in regular feedback to employees. Audit management practices in different parts of the organization to help identify existing or potential ethics problems. Develop a code of ethics and keep it alive, not only by enforcing it when violations occur but also by communicating its meaning and updating it as new concerns develop. Make certain that the actions of top officials are consistent with their expectations for employee conduct. The task of ethics-bringing reason and reflection to bear on complex problems and attempting to meet ethical standards and live by ethical principles-is an ongoing process for each individual. On this process rests the public administrator's personal integrity and ultimately the character of the polity. References American Society for Public Administration. Code of Ethics and Implementation Guidelines. Washington, D.C.: American Society for Public Administration, 1985. Bowman, J. "Ethics in Government' A National Survey of Public Administrators." Public Ad- ministration Review, 1990,50,345-353. Bukkyo Dendo Kyokai. The 7liaching of Buddha. (509th ed.) Tokyo. Toppan, 1987. Catron, B. L., and Denhardt, K. "Ethics Education in Public Administration." In T Cooper (ed.), Handbook of Administrative Ethics. New York. Marcel Dekker, 1993. Congressional Research Service. U.S. Library of Congress. "Legislative Ethics in Democratic Countries: Comparative Analysis of Financial Standards." CRS Report 94325A. Washington, D.C.: Congressional Research Service, 1994. Cook, F:J. "The Corrupt Society." TheJ\liltion, 1963,196, 454-496. Cooper, T L. The Responsible Administrator: An Approach to Ethics for the Administrative Role. (3rd ed.) San Francisco: Jossey-Bass, 1990. Council of State Governments. COGEL Blue Book. (9th ed.) Lexington, K)(: 1993. Dobel,J. 1'. Compromise and Political Action. Savage, Md.: Rowan & Littlefield, 1990. Feigenbaum, E. D., Pockrass, S. F:, Chapman, B. A., and Lenzer, S. E;ffective Strategies for the Prosecution of Public Corruption. Final Report. Indianapolis, Ind.: Hudson Institute, 1991. Frederickson, H. G. "Can Public Officials Correctly Be Said to Have Obligations to Future Generations?" Public Administration Review, 1994, 54, 457-464. Gilligan, C. In a Different Voice. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1982. Gilligan, C., Ward,J. V, Taylor,J. M, and Bardige, B. (eds.). Mapping the Moral Domain. Cam- bridge, Mass.: Harvard Graduate School of Education, 1988. Goodsell, C. T The Case for Bureaucracy: A Public Administration Polemic. (3rd ed.) Chatham, NJ.: Chatham House, 1994. Gorlin, R. A. (ed.). Codes of Professional Responsibility. (2nd ed.) Washington, D.C.. Bureau of National Affairs, 1990. Guy; M. E. Ethical Decision Making in Everyday Work Situations. Westport, Conn. : Quorum Books, 1990. Hart, H.L.A. The Concept of Law. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press, Clarendon Press, 1961. Hirschmann, N.J. "Freedom, Recognition, and Obligation: A Feminist Approach to Political Theory." American Political Science Review, 1989, 83, 1227-1244. Huang, L.-H. A Complete Book Concerning HapPiness and Benevolence. A Manual for Local Magistrates in Seventeenth-Century China. (D. Chu, trans. and ed.) Tucson: University of Arizona Press, 1984. Jefferson, T. "Letter to Peter Carr, August 19, 1785." The Portable Jefferson. New York: Viking Penguin,1975. Josephson Institute. "Ethics Pledge for Elected Officials." Marina del Rey, Calif: Josephson Institute for the Advancement of Ethics, Government Ethics Center, 1990. Kass, H. D. "Stewardship as a Fundamental Element in Images of Public Administration." In H. D. Kass and B. L. Catron (eds.), Images and Identities in Public Administration. Newbury Park, Calif.: Sage, 1990. Kellar, E. K. (ed.). Ethical Insight, Ethical Action: Perspectives for the Local Government Managel: Washington, D.C.: International City/County Management Association, 1988. Kohlberg, L. The Philosophy of Moral Development, Moral Stages and the Idea of Justice. Vol. 1. New York: HarperCollins, 1981. Ladd, E. C. "Ethics Problems. ..and Problems in Polling on Ethics." The Public Perspective, 1993,4, 20--21. Lewis, C. W The Ethics Challenge in Public Service. A Problem-Solving Guide. San Francisco. Jossey- Bass, 1991. Lewis, G. B. "In Search of the Machiavellian Milquetoasts: Comparing Attitudes of Bureaucrats and Ordinary People." Public Administration Review, 1990, 50, 220-227. Mertins, H., Jr., and others (eds.). Applying Professional Standards and Ethics in the Nineties. A UYJi book and Study Guide with Cases for Public Administrators. (3rd ed.) Washington, D.C.: American Society for Public Administration, 1994. Morgan, D. F., and Kass, H. D. "Legitimizing Administrative Discretion Through Constitutional Stewardship." In J. S. Bowman (ed.), Ethical Frontiers in Public Management: Seeking j, Strategies for Resolving Ethical Dilemmas. San Francisco: Jossey- Bass, 1991. Nash, L. L. Good Intentions Aside: A Manager's Guide to Resolving Ethical Problems. Boston, Mass.: Harvard Business School Press, 1990. Office of Government Ethics. How to Keep Out of 1Touble: Ethical Conduct for Federal Employees. Washington, D.C.: Office of Government Ethics, 1989. Office of Government Ethics. Standards of Ethical Conduct for Employees of the Executive Branch. Washington, D.C.: Office of Government Ethics, 1992. Okin, S. M. Justice, Gende1; and the Family. New York: Basic Books, 1989. Rawls,J. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971. Rion, M. The Responsible Manager: Practical Strategies for Ethical Decision Making. New York: HarperCollins, 1990. Rohr,J. A. Ethicsfor Bureaucrats: An Essay on Law and Values. (2nd ed.) New York: Marcel Decker, 1989. Rosenbloom, D. R. "The Constitution as a Basis for Public Administrative Ethics." In P. Madsen and J. M. Shafritz (eds.), Essentials of Government Ethics. New York: Viking Penguin, 1992. Smith, A. The Theory of Moral Sentiments. Indianapolis, Ind.: Liberty Classics, 1976. Stewart, D. W., and Sprinthall, N. A. "The Impact of Demographic, Professional, and Or nizational Variables and Domain on the Moral Reasoning of Public Administrators." I H. G. Frederickson (ed.), Ethics and Public Administration. Armonk, N.Y: M.E. Sharpe, 19 "Survey Data on Ethics." The Public Perspective, 1993, 4,29-34. Thompson, D. F. "The Possibility of Administrative Ethics." Public Administration Review, 19 45, 555-561.