Citizenship and the marginalities of migrants David Owen What is owed to migrants by receiving states, and what do migrants owe to these states? This question occupies an increasingly central place in debates within political theory. However, addressing this question requires at least two fundamental methodological choices.1 The first concerns how much, if any, of the normative structure of the current political order one chooses to treat as background conditions for the purposes of the enquiry. The second concerns the normative orientation adopted, that is, for example, whether one chooses to work within the terms of a specific theory of justice or of freedom or, alternatively, adopts a more catholic approach. These choices are related in that the degree to which one builds features of the existing normative architecture of politics into one’s account has implications for how much appeal one can make to, for example, widely held democratic norms (norms which, typically, can be supported on a variety of different theoretical grounds and, hence, the adoption of which need not require one to commit oneself to a specific theory). It is important to be explicit about these choices for two reasons. The first is that they specify what the argument is – and is not – committed to doing. The second is that it helps to clarify the advantages and limitations of the approach adopted. For these reasons, I will introduce the argument of this essay by situating it in relation to these choices before laying out its structure. The approach adopted in this essay holds in place the normative presumption that states have a general entitlement to regulate their own border regimes in ways compatible with respect for basic human rights, where this includes their entitlement to limit their own authority to regulate their border regimes (for example, the establishment of a right of free movement for citizens of EU member states within the territory of the EU), and concomitantly, to construct normatively consequential distinctions within the general class of migrants. It does so in order to investigate the legitimate forms of state practice towards migrants within such terms. The advantage to this approach is that it starts from a set of presuppositions that are widely held by states and that it can provide reasonably determinate guidance with respect to the duties that democratic states owe to migrants and that migrants owe to democratic states under such conditions.2 It should be noted, however, that this choice does not come without consequences. Thus, it brackets questions such as whether states should be entitled unilaterally to regulate their own borders and, of perhaps more immediate salience, whether states should be entitled to offer distinct conditions of entry and residence to migrants. These are important questions. Indeed, it will become apparent that such questions cannot be fully bracketed in our enquiry. This does not mean, however, that it is pointless or mistaken to try to get as far as we can without entering the more controversial and contested waters that such questions inhabit. Rather, it will make explicit the points at which the presuppositions that serve as the background for this approach are thrust into the foreground and, hence, become the necessary focus of normative attention. In adopting this stance towards the normative structure of our current political order, this approach also adopts a relatively catholic approach to the normative issues under investigation drawing on widely held understandings of national citizenship and of democratic norms. The orientation adopted in this essay deploys the concept of civic marginalisation as an analytic lens through which to address the conditions of legitimacy of the conduct of democratic states towards migrants under the basic presumptions of the legitimate exercise of state agency that are being taken as background givens for the purposes of this argument. By ‘the civic marginalisation of migrants’, I refer to the phenomenon of being (or becoming) marginal relative to the abstract norm of equal membership in the democratic state as that norm is concretely instantiated in the figure of the national citizen. The rationale for adopting the lens of civic marginalisation is, firstly, that it allows us to situate state-differentiated types of migrant in relation to the norm of national citizenship in a way that clarifies the normative differences at stake in such differentiations and, second, that it enables us to attend to the legitimacy and significance of state practice in differentiating between migrants in terms of their access to citizenship. The focus of the former is on duties to, and rights and duties of, migrants; the focus of the latter is on the availability and terms of routes to national citizenship for migrants. It is, I will argue, important to take these two aspects of the civic marginalisation of migrants together because they are related in ways that are normatively consequential with respect to the duties of the state. The state may have special duties to migrants who are not owed a route to national citizenship in virtue of the vulnerability to which they are exposed by this presumptively justifiable condition of civic marginalisation. Given this approach to the topic, the argument will be structured in the following way. I will begin by addressing the availability and terms of routes to national citizenship for immigrants, before turning to the topic of the duties to, and rights and duties of, immigrants, and, finally, concluding with critical reflections on the advantages and limitations of the approach exemplified in this argument. I. Routes to National Citizenship Permanent Residents Those migrants who are lawful habitual residents and enjoy (or are in the process of acquiring) the status of permanent residents are widely held by democratic theorists of a variety of theoretical persuasions to count as ‘citizens in the making’ in David Miller’s apposite phrase (Miller, 2008a: 195). After a specified temporal threshold of residency is passed, it is argued, variously, that citizenship should be automatically bestowed on them (Carens, 2005; Rubio-Marin, 2000), that they should enjoy an automatic entitlement to citizenship if they choose to apply (Baubock, 2009) or that they should possess an automatic entitlement to apply for citizenship which may be granted subject to satisfying a test (of some kind) that bears on their identification with, or disposition and capacities for identifying with, the political community (Miller, 2008b; for an overview, see Seglow, 2008).1 The most austere argument for this conclusion can be drawn from Dahl’s ‘principle of full inclusion’: ‘The demos must include all adult members of the association except transients and persons proved to be mentally defective’ (Dahl, 1989: 129), where ‘adult members of the association’ refers to ‘all adults subject to the binding collective decisions of the association’ (Dahl, 1989: 120). In the context of a democratic polity characterised in significant part by authority over a territorial jurisdiction, Dahl’s account implies that any competent adult who is habitually resident within the territory of the polity and, hence, subject to the laws and policies of its government is entitled to full inclusion within the demos. Such an argument can be taken to underwrite Walzer’s claim that the denial of full political rights to legally-admitted habitual residents amounts to citizen tyranny (Walzer, 1983: 55).3 This 1 In this essay, I will adopt the presumption that the sole route to full political rights is through acquiring national citizenship. Elsewhere (Owen 2011) I have argued that it is plausible to draw a distinction between political membership and national citizenship but that suggestion is both controversial and, not unrelatedly, at variance with widespread state practice in which the symbolic and substantive link between (resident) citizens and political rights is generally (albeit not universally) taken for granted. Since I am trying to remain reasonably close to existing practices in this essay, I will consequently bracket this proposal for the purposes of this argument. argument is supplemented in Caren’s and Rubio-Marin’s social membership principle by the additional point that, as a general rule, habitual residents become members of society in the sense of forming important ties and attachments within this society, and hence coming to identify a significant range of their interests with their membership of this society such that this membership serves a central locus for their lives and, consequently, it would be unjust to deny them membership of the political community as the body through which society reflectively acts on and governs itself. Whereas Dahl’s argument bears on national citizenship in respect of subjection to a regime of rule, this supplementation bears on national citizenship as membership of a political community and provides reasons to be confident that, in general, such membership will be of noninstrumental value to persons who have practically committed themselves to living their lives within this society. Baubock’s stakeholder principle which proposes that those ‘persons and only those persons have a claim to citizenship in a particular political community who (a) depend on that community for long-term protection of their basic rights’ and/or ‘(b) are or have been subjected to that community’s political authorities for a significant period over the course of their lives’ (Baubock, 2009: 479) similarly supplements Dahl’s austere argument by directly adducing the identity-forming dimension of inhabiting a polity in a way that addresses national citizenship as membership of a political community.4 These liberal egalitarian positions contrast in some respects with the liberal nationalist stance which focuses on the integration of permanent residents into a national community and asserts the defensibility of ‘the policy … of making access to citizenship conditional on passing a test, that requires, for example, a working knowledge of the national language, and some familiarity with the history and institutions of the country in question’ (Miller, 2008b: 385)5 on the grounds that citizens are required to undergo such education and the incentives that migrants have to acquire this education may be variable and insufficient to secure their provision. In one respect the grounds that Miller adduces would appear only to justify the requirement that immigrants undergo compulsory language training and civic education, a position which liberal egalitarians can also endorse (alongside exemptions from such classes for those who show, perhaps through a test, that they do not require them), but I take it that the unstated (and contestable) premise is that a test is required to ensure that people attending such classes genuinely engage with them. The underlying motivation of the liberal nationalist position is not hard to understand since it is plausibly the case that the stable reproduction of a democratic state oriented to a politics of the common good requires that many, even most, citizens regard membership of the political community as non-instrumentally valuable. However, both the social membership and stakeholder principles provide reasons for thinking that persons who satisfy Dahl’s all-subjected requirement are likely to stand, or come to stand, in non-instrumental relationship to the political community. The social membership principle points to the normative salience of the fact that permanent residents will typically form significant ties to other members of society and an attachment to this society in general as the locus of their lives. The stakeholder principle directs its attention to the identity-constituting dimension of being subject to the polity and, thereby, to the notion of a shared fate. In this respect, both acknowledge the significance of this aspect of national citizenship. The crux of the disagreement is, thus, whether it is justifiable to discriminate within the class of permanent residents on an individualised basis through recourse to citizenship tests. While it is plausible that liberal egalitarians may accept accelerated access to national citizenship for those who can pass a citizenship test, what they reject is that you can make access to the legal status of citizenship fully conditional on passing a test. On this liberal egalitarian view, you can legitimately expect that permanent residents will learn the relevant vernacular language and acquire the salient practical knowledge needed to participate in civic life, and you can require them to attend publically funded classes that attempt to provide them with these skills, but to make access to citizenship dependent on satisfying a test is to commit a basic injustice against those denied citizenship on this basis. It condemns them to the abject political state of perpetual subjection to ‘citizen tyranny’ on the basis of the fact that they fail to meet a stipulated threshold of linguistic competence and political knowledge, where what this entails practically is that the higher costs of effective civic engagement for them (i.e., dependency on translation by, and the practical political knowledge of, others) are taken to justify denying them a right to civic engagement. But the fact that the costs of exercising a right and fulfilling a duty may be higher, even significantly higher, for Alf compared to Ben does not provide good grounds for denying the right to Alf. This is especially so if we adopt an integration regime that cultivates the capacities for, and disposition to, civic participation through widening opportunities for participation and increasing incentives to do so in ways that lower the costs for Alf.6 Such an integration regime can provide the basic reassurance that the liberal nationalist seeks without requiring that individual law-abiding migrants who have become permanent residents are denied citizenship. Thus, I conclude that habitual residents should be automatically entitled to citizenship after a specified period of residence.7 Short-term/temporary contract workers and students Workers who are admitted on temporary contracts or students who are admitted to educational programmes which do not approach the norm for inclusion stand in contrast to habitual residents with (or in the process of acquiring) the status of permanent resident in that migrants with time-limited visas are not prima facie entitled to a route to citizenship any more than tourists are. Short-term and habitual modes of residency are different relationships which construct distinct webs of rights and obligations between the state and migrant. This does not mean that temporary migrants cannot be permitted the option of converting their status to that of permanent residents but it does, I think, rule out their access to citizenship in the absence of taking up this option and meeting the relevant requirements. It does so because the period of residence required for access to national citizenship is best conceptualised as the period required to establish what Dahl would refer to as ‘non-transient’ status and, consequently, although the state may choose to adopt a shorter period than the EU average of 5 years (such as, for example, the choice of 1 year by New Zealand) for access to political membership, this simply determines the relative contrast between the categories of transient/short-term and nontransient/habitual residents. What counts as ‘short-term’ or ‘temporary’ is determined relative to the political rules on access to citizenship for habitually resident non-citizens in a given state. This does not mean that we cannot specify reasonable upper and lower limits to current state practices which should support international norms governing these practices (I would generally argue that a norm of 5 years, plus or minus 3 years represents a defensible specification of such reasonable limits), but it does entail that we cannot specify what counts as ‘short-term’ as a determinate period of time in abstract from the political context being addressed. What of conditions in which a short-term worker gains a further short-term contract in the same country of residence (even if following a brief period of absence from the state) such that the period of (more or less continuous) residence passes the threshold for the inclusion of habitual residents? Should we count the period of residence as starting again with the contract renewal, or as continuous across contracts? This question arises because, in contrast to the habitually resident non-citizen, the short-term worker is admitted as someone engaged on a project with a specified end and, then, re-admitted on another project with a specified end. In general, I think that this does make a difference in that when the state admits ‘voluntary’ migrants for an open-ended period, the relationship between state and migrant is conceived as potentially permanent, whereas in the case of the short-term worker or student, each of their serial stays has a contractually agreed and specified purpose with an endpoint. The temporary migrant lives in society with the presumption that they will be required to leave; the habitual migrant with (or acquiring) permanent residency status lives in society with the presumption that they will not be required to leave. These distinct conditions of social life will almost inevitably affect the depth and extent of the ties to society (rather than individuals) that these differently situated migrants enjoy. In this respect, I think that the stress of the social membership argument on a standard period of time (Carens, 2005; Carens, 2008) has a tendency to suppress the point that, from the standpoint of social ties (rather than that of subjection to law), time is being used as a proxy for integration.2 The problem is that the adoption of a standard period of time as a proxy for integration across different classes of lawful migrant relies on the presupposition that the migrant’s relation to the society in which they reside is independent of the temporal horizon in terms of which migrant’s experience, and reflect, on their presence in society. I don’t see what speaks in favour of this presupposition. This is admittedly a matter for sociological investigation but if it is 2 There are, of course, a range of other objections that can be made to using time as a proxy for integration since a habitually resident migrant may not integrate into society (Seglow 2008) but the issue here is the framing of a general rule and, given the general tendency of people to integrate (often in circumstances that are far from ideal), it seems reasonable to adopt a rule in which time serves this purpose (with qualifiers such as not committing serious criminal offences). The alternative is to adopt an integration test of some kind but the design problems raised by such a test are significant. the case that there is a real difference in what might be termed the ‘time-integration coefficient’ between those with temporary and permanent residency statuses, what implications follow? The first is that treating the periods of residency as continuous, that is, as if the short-term and habitual migrant were relevantly identical, is not required by justice. However, second, it is also unjust to treat each consecutive period as a distinct and separate period as if the short-term migrant who is admitted for a given number of consecutive periods were equivalent to the same number of short-term migrants, each of whom is admitted for a single period. The hypothetical presumption that the temporality of integration is different for temporary and permanent residents does not imply that the temporary resident does not integrate into society, only that one cannot reasonably expect that their integration over a given period of time to have the same depth and scope as the typical permanent resident over the same period. In this context, just treatment of the temporary migrant requires that we adopt the view that a (more or less) serial short-term migrant not merely be permitted to switch to permanent resident status but, after a specified period of time, entitled to do so with their existing years of residence counting at a discounted rate (where the discount is a function of the ratio of the two time-integration coefficients). Consequently, the temporary worker who remains (more or less) continuously present for the appropriate time-period is entitled to acquire a route to citizenship. Stateless persons A stateless person is any person who is not legally counted as a national by any state through its nationality legislation or constitution (there are currently estimated to be about 12 million people8 in this condition though estimation is unsurprisingly difficult in respect of this class of persons). Stateless persons who are present on the territory of a state are recognized as occupying an acutely vulnerable condition since they have no right to diplomatic protection or right to return or right to pass on a nationality in respect of a state of nationality. This puts them in the position of being almost wholly dependent of the protection and good will of the state in which they are resident. It is, in part for this reason, that international law recognises the right to a nationality as a basic human right (UNDHR Art.15.1, see also 1930 Hague Convention on Nationality, and 1954 and 1961 UN Statelessness Conventions) and, thereby, establishes a duty of states to facilitate the naturalization of stateless persons. From a liberal egalitarian standpoint, the condition of statelessness grounds a general duty on states to naturalise stateless person’s resident on their territory. Thus, stateless residents are entitled to a route to national citizenship. The real issue here is whether, given their vulnerability and the manifold disadvantages of lacking any national citizenship (for example, lacking a passport), there are compelling reasons to provide accelerated access to national citizenship compared to the time-period required of the permanent resident. Consider three possible policies: (i) conferring citizenship in the state of residence without a time-threshold and supporting these ‘immediate’ citizens through a post-naturalisation integration regime, (ii) lowering the time-threshold for naturalisation combined with more intensive support for integration and special protections (including a ‘surrogate’ passport) while they are below this timethreshold and (iii) maintaining the same time-threshold as applies to permanent residents, providing continuous support for integration across this period (including relevant identity documentation) but also establishing an special institution within the state (for example, an Ombudsman for Stateless Persons) which actively protects and represents their interests. Although I think that (ii) is the most sensible practical policy in terms of respecting the claims of stateless persons and of the democratic community, it is the case that, independent of normatively relevant empirical evidence, any of these options would meet the basic normative requirements. What is ruled out by justice is maintaining stateless persons in a condition which denies them access to citizenship in the state of residence for any time-period longer than applies to permanent residents. Refugees and ‘forced’ migrants This category of lawful residents encompasses asylum seekers who are authorised to remain with the state of refuge, whether or not they are recognised as meeting the national interpretation of the 1951 Convention criteria governing the attribution of ‘Convention refugee’ status. In contrast to other types of resident non-citizens, the state is under a general obligation to admit prima facie plausible asylum seekers who present themselves at the borders of the state in order to determine whether they qualify for refugee status. If they do so qualify, the principle of non-refoulement entails that the state cannot return them to their state of persecution and, in general, established state practice has been to grant them lawful residence within, and a form of ‘surrogate membership’ of, the state. If they do not so qualify, the state may choose to deport them or to grant them a distinct status than that of Convention refugee which, nevertheless, permits them to reside lawfully in the state. In both cases, it should be noted, the right to remain is not a right to permanent residence but rather a right to reside for whatever period is required to secure protection from persecution or, in the case of non-Convention refugees, the danger that underwrites the right to remain. The question that arises is whether, after a certain period, refugees can legitimately claim a general entitlement to citizenship. Consider, first, that the residence of the refugee on the territory of the state does not represent a voluntary choice on the part of the state, but the discharging of an obligation in international law. This has one significant consequence in terms of civic marginalisation, namely, that the duty of non-refoulement that states rightly incur in respect of refugees provides less legitimate scope for returning a migrant to their home state than is the case for ‘voluntary’ migrants that the state has chosen to admit. Second, in contrast to habitually resident non-citizens, refugees are de facto unable to exercise their right to diplomatic protection and their right of return. In this respect, refugees are relevantly analogous to stateless persons, a relation which prima facie supports similar conclusions concerning the provision of a (potentially accelerated) route to citizenship. In the cases of both stateless persons and refugees, the state of residence stands in loco civitatis and must reflect this standing in its treatment of their claims. Third, the refugee’s relation to the society in which they now reside is characterised by an indeterminate timehorizon, neither open-ended like the habitual resident nor with a specified endpoint like the short-term worker, in that they may be subject to (and indeed desire to) return if the relevant conditions entitling them to refugee status cease to pertain at some future point in time. This is an extremely difficult position to occupy because it means that the refugee is situated in a condition of social and civic limbo, unable to commit to building a new life because they may be returned to the old, unable to commit to the old life because they may never be able to take it up once more. This consideration strongly supports the view that the state of residence has a duty to provide a determinate path to national citizenship for refugees whose status persists beyond some specified timethreshold. Taken together, these features of the refugee require that a route to national citizenship is available and suggest that an accelerated path to citizenship would be a reasonable option to adopt, even if the state’s duty of care might be met in ways that don’t require this. Irregular Migrants Irregular migrants are persons who currently reside on the territory of the state while lacking authorisation to do so. Are such migrants entitled to a route to citizenship? Consider here the distinction that we have drawn between habitual and short-term residents which I have argued can ground differences in their access to citizenship. Bearing this distinction in mind, we can consider an acute point made by David Miller: How should the contrast apply in the case of irregular migrants? The answer is that we simply do not know … The very fact that somebody is an unauthorized migrant means that we cannot draw the usual distinctions between a person who is admitted on a short-term visa to work for a certain period and a person who is legally accepted as a long-term immigrant in the expectation that he or she will in due course set out on ‘‘the path to citizenship’’ … (2008a: 196) Miller develops two further points from this reflection. First, the rights, other than human rights, of irregular migrants will depend on how actively and successful the state tracks them down. Second, ‘horizontal equity’ between irregular and temporary migrants must be respected (2008a: 196-7). There is a relatively straightforward way of accommodating Miller’s concerns, namely, to argue that there is no requirement on states to provide a route to citizenship for irregular migrants until they have satisfied a period of residence equivalent to the norm for lawfully resident non-citizens and, then, to discount their prior residence either entirely or, at least, at a rate of discount higher than that which applies to the short-term worker who also meets this time-threshold. Notice that such a view is compatible with the state choosing to provide regular amnesties within shorter time-periods for irregular migrants that allow them to regularise their status on terms broadly equivalent (although not identical) to those of short-term workers. Although such a view would meet Miller’s immediate concerns, grounding it requires that there are reasons to adopt such a policy rather than simply holding that irregular migrants should have no route to citizenship. To provide such an argument involves attending to two points. The first simply draws attention to the fact that the presence of irregular migrants and, more specifically, long-term residents who are irregular migrants is both unavoidable and a problem for democratic states as forms of polity committed to the view that those who are subject to the law should have a say in the nature of the law to which they are subject. Consequently, the state has a choice between either allowing conditions under which irregular migrants can regularise their status and, thereby, acquire a route to citizenship or compromising what is arguably its deepest normative commitment. The second point notes that even if the irregular migrant’s presence is not authorised, the fact that long-term irregular migrants choose to centre their lives in this society retains normative significance in that it is typically the case that such irregular migrants become embedded members of society who also contribute to it. It might be objected to this second point that its force is negated because the continuing presence of the long-term irregular migrant represents the perpetuation of the violation of the right of the state to determine whether this person is entitled to reside on its territory. But we should note that it ‘is widely believed that some rights are capable of ‘fading’ in their moral importance by virtue of the passage of time and by the sheer persistence of what was originally wrongful infringement.’ (Waldron, 1992: 15) The pertinent question is, consequently, whether the right to determine whether the long-term irregular migrant is entitled to remain in the state is one such right. There are two reasons to suggest that it is, and so should be subject to a ‘statute of limitations’. The first is that the harm to the individual of being deported after long-term residence and having acquired the attendant social attachments is significantly greater than any harm done to society in allowing this individual to remain. This argument is, however, open to the objection that although this may be true for each case taken singly, it leaves aside the general harm of irregular migration to the state as a legal and political order. The more important reason is the second, namely that the legitimate expectations of other ‘regular’ members of society whose life-plans centrally involve the presence of the long-term irregular migrant will also be frustrated by the act of deporting this migrant. This reason, in my view, justifies the establishment of a cut-off point beyond which the irregular migrant can regularise their status and, hence, acquire a route to citizenship. II Having addressed the issue of routes to citizenship, we are now in a position to turn to the question of the rights and duties that compose the relevant relationships between states and types of migrant in the light of their relationship to citizenship. I start again with the figure of the habitually resident non-citizen. Permanent and ‘not-yet-permanent’ Residents Carens (2005) has argued that permanent residents should be broadly entitled to all the rights – and, I would add, duties - that citizens enjoy with the exception of the right to vote in national elections and stand for public office.9 The argument has two steps. The first asserts the basic principle that differential treatment of those subject to the legal authority of the state requires justification (2005: 33). The second step then argues that differential treatment is not justified in the case of permanent residents on the basis of their social membership: ‘Living in a society on an ongoing basis makes one a member of that society.’ (2005: 33) From a rather different position and on somewhat different grounds, David Miller concurs, arguing that the justification for granting rights of citizenship ‘to certain categories of immigrants who do not yet hold formal citizenship status is that they are citizens in the making, so to speak.’ (2008a: 195). However, notice that both of these arguments effectively lump together resident non-citizens who have been granted the status of ‘permanent resident’ and habitually resident migrants who have not acquired that status. I want to suggest that we can differentiate between these classes of habitual migrant, not least on the basis that applying for permanent residency makes explicit one’s commitment to long-term residence in the society. If permanent residents should enjoy broadly the same rights and duties as citizens, what differences are justified in treating the class of habitual but ‘not yet permanent’ residents?10 This matters since this class of resident non-citizens as presumptively ‘permanent residents in the making’ are not in the same position as short-term contract workers or students whose projects are tied to specific endpoints. What rights, then, should this class of ‘not-yetpermanent’ resident non-citizens enjoy? Notice that the same reasoning that supports treating permanent residents as ‘citizens in the making’ supports seeing this class of resident non-citizens as ‘permanent residents in the making’ and, hence, as broadly equipping them with the legal rights – civil, social and economic – that enable them to integrate into society and the legal duties that are required of permanent residents such as paying tax and contributing to work-based welfare and pension programmes as well as the legal duties that are required of anyone present on the state (for example, tourists) such as abiding by the law. There are, however, two significant differences between this class of resident non-citizens and permanent residents. First, ‘not-yet-permanent’ residents who choose to leave the state before becoming permanent residents should be able to be compensated for the contributions that they have made to state-based pension schemes but from which they will not be able to benefit. By contrast, permanent residents who choose to leave the state should be treated in the same way as citizens who live abroad with respect to state-based pension schemes and, similarly, enjoy a right to return to the state of ‘permanent residence’ for a period at least equivalent to that required to attain permanent residency. In other words, the presumption that a permanent resident is a ‘citizen in the making’ is not straightforwardly defeated by the fact that this resident leaves the state, rather it is sustained unless and until they have not returned with the relevant time-period. Second, ‘not-yet-permanent’ residents have no entitlement to some rights of political participation (such as the right to hold office in the organisation of national political parties) to which permanent residents are entitled as ‘citizens in the making’. This limitation on the political rights of ‘not-yet-permanent’ residents places an additional burden of responsibility on the state to ensure that resident non-citizens who have not achieved the status of ‘permanent resident’ are not subject to abuse or exploitation. Thus, while ‘not-yet-permanent’ migrants should enjoy most of the rights and duties characteristic of permanent residents, there are some respects in which their rights can legitimately be differentiated from those of permanent residents and such differentiation affects the duties of the state towards them. Stateless persons, refugees and ‘forced’ migrants permitted to remain Stateless persons fall into the same class as permanent residents, while refugees and forced migrants are best placed in the same class as ‘not-yet permanent’ residents. This distinction is based on the fact that refugees and forced migrants may legitimately be required to return to their home state if the conditions that generate their status cease to apply within a given time-period. The key normative difference between stateless persons, refugees and ‘forced’ migrants compared to other lawful residents is that these migrants don’t enjoy an effective right to diplomatic protection by, or right to return to, another state and hence, the state of residence stands in loco civitatis. As such, the state has special duties to ensure their protection from abuse or exploitation. Notice that since refugees and ‘forced’ migrants may legitimately be required to return to their states if the relevant conditions have changed within the salient time-period, the state of refuge has a special duty to ensure that this class of migrant should have access to resources that support them through the difficulties that attend the condition of ‘social and civic limbo’ in which they find themselves. Short-term/temporary contract workers and students In relation to short-term contract workers, Carens has argued that ‘temporary workers should receive most of the economic and social rights that citizens and residents enjoy’ (2008a: 430). In stark contrast David Miller has suggested that while the human rights of temporary workers must be protected, ‘beyond that, [the position of temporary migrants] is better understood in contractual terms: what rights they get should depend on what agreements they have made (or are in place) before they enter.’ (2008a: 196) Neither of these positions seems altogether satisfactory. On the one hand, Carens’ argument seems to remove any normative distinction between short-term contract workers and ‘not-yetpermanent’ residents, and in so doing underestimates, as Miller does not, that an important range of civic obligations cannot reasonably be imposed on short-term contract workers. On the other hand, Miller’s position underestimates the potential for exploitation in contracts to which parties in highly asymmetric power relations mutually consent. A more reasonable stance acknowledges that short-term contract workers need not be required to pay income tax or into work-related pension schemes but, equally, that the state has a duty to regulate the contracts that can be agreed to ensure that fair remuneration, health and welfare protections, and the like are included with its terms. The point here is that since, with a few exceptions, the use of short-term contract workers is not a routinely required feature of the economy of the state and its consequences for the wider population may be ambivalent, the costs should lie largely on the employers (unless some clear public interest is involved). These remarks do not, however, bear on a central issue raised by Carens, namely, whether a short-term contract worker should have the right to change employer or, indeed, the sector of the economy in which their initial job is situated. In respect of the first issue, Carens’ argument is that the restriction is not justified on the grounds that it enables exploitation; at best, acknowledgment of the employer’s investment in recruitment ‘would only justify a limited period during which the migrant could legitimately be tied to a particular employer’ and even here there should be an escape clause for abusive behaviour (2008a: 431), where, I’d add, the employer should be liable for penalties that fund the search for new employment opportunities of a commensurately desirable kind to the original offer or, in the absence of such opportunities, compensate the migrant for the varied costs of their relocation. The state in regulating contracts can make accommodation for this practice. What of the case of the migrant being able to move to a different sector of employment? Carens’ argument for this right is that its absence ‘forces foreign temporary workers to perform tasks for wages that are lower than they could command if they were free to compete on the entire labour market.’ (2008a: 432) But is this the relevant counterfactual? An alternative formulation would hold that offering entry for a restricted sector is expanding the labour market options available to the migrant by adding one to the options available in the state of origin and typically one that enables the worker to perform tasks for wages that are higher than they could command on the entire labour market of the home state. The problem here concerns identifying the relevant counter- factual without appealing to broader considerations of global justice and the legitimacy of state practice. Given this methodological commitment, it seems more plausible to argue that the state has a regulatory duty of care towards those migrants that it admits on such restricted terms to ensure that they are paid a fair wage for the work that they perform. While it is true that what such a fair wage would amount to cannot be given any determinacy independent of broader considerations of justice, this position does allow for a coherent normative stance within the terms of the methodological commitments I have adopted even as it raises and points to the limitations of these commitments. Irregular Migrants The difficulty posed by the case of irregular migrants concerns, first, the rights to which they should be entitled, despite not being authorised to be resident in the territory of the state, and, second, the effects of their lack of authorisation to residence on their effective enjoyment of these rights. To address these issues, we can begin by re-iterating that irregular migrants are entitled to human rights. The problem that arises in relation to the enjoyment of such rights on the part of irregular migrants, which has been treated in depth by Bosniak (2006), is that their possession of these rights is effectively quashed by the fear that exercising them will draw their migration status to the attention of state authorities. As Carens notes: ‘This creates a serious normative problem for democratic states. It makes no moral sense to provide people with purely formal legal rights under conditions that make it impossible for them to exercise those rights effectively.’ (2008b: 167) One response to this situation is Carens’ suggestion to adopt a firewall policy which draws a line between enforcing immigration law and protecting basic human rights: ‘We ought to establish as a firm legal principle that no information gathered by those responsible for protecting and realizing basic human rights can be used for immigration enforcement purposes.’ (2008b: 167) The point of a firewall is to protect the rights to which irregular migrants are entitled and to protect them insofar as they act civically in reporting breaches, or suspected breaches, of state law.11 But note Caren’s claim: ‘It makes no moral sense to provide people with purely formal legal rights under conditions that make it impossible for them to exercise those rights effectively.’ This claim is, I think, a slight mis-statement since, even under conditions in which irregular migrants can be reported to the border police when going to hospital or reporting a crime, this does not make it impossible to exercise the right effectively or (as might also be intended) effectively impossible to exercise the right. Rather it makes effective exercise of the right unreasonably costly in terms of the consequences that can lawfully follow from such exercise. In respect of human rights, this reformulation has the same consequences for Carens’ argument, but it is less clear that it retains this consequence if a firewall policy is extended to a range of civic rights as Carens argues it should be. Thus, for example, Carens’ goes on to address work-related rights as well as social and administrative rights, arguing that the irregular migrants should enjoy a considerable range of these rights where effective enjoyment of them requires the extension of the firewall argument. But we should pause here to note that Carens’ argument, like my own, is operating with the methodological strategy of assuming that the state has a basic right to control who enters and resides within its borders. This being the case, it follows that it is also morally nonsensical for the state to have a formal right to control its borders under conditions that make it unreasonably costly for the state to exercise this right effectively. In the case of human rights, we accept that it as a function of these rights that they place constraints on how the state can pursue its projects; the firewall policies needed to ensure that irregular migrants can exercise basic human rights are justified even if they present significant problems for a state’s pursuit of its legitimate border policies. But the same point does not straightforwardly extend to civic rights which also raise the costs of the state’s exercise of its rights in respect of border policies if these costs are unreasonable in that either they make it impracticable for a state to pursue its legitimate border policies or entail that a state can only practicably pursue its border policies by increasing its powers – for example, powers of surveillance – in ways that reduce the overall civil liberty of all persons resident on the territory of the state. Once we recognise this consequence of the internal structure of Carens’ argument, we confront a fundamental issue, namely, the determination of what counts as unreasonable burdens on the state’s exercise of its right of border control in relation to what count as unreasonable burdens on the rights of irregular migrant’s. An adequate response to this question is beyond the scope of this essay and highlights another point at which the limitations of the methodological choices that I have adopted act to focus our attention on, to foreground, norms that have been placed in the background for the sake of this inquiry. The key point in relation to this essay is that we simply cannot specify what the scope of effective, rather than formal, civic rights for irregular migrants should be if we hold fixed the norm that state’s should enjoy a right to control entry to, and residence on, their territory. Conclusion The substantive claims that this argument has attempted to establish can be summarised as four claims. First, it makes a normatively consequential difference whether a given class of migrants has a clear route to citizenship which means essentially whether they have a clear route to permanent resident status. If it is the case either that they do not have access to such a route or that they lack a nationality or that they possess a nationality but effectively lack the rights to which it would normally entitle them, then the state has an additional duty of care toward the type of migrant in question where the nature and scope of that duty is dependent on the specific form of civic marginalisation characteristic of the relevant class of migrants. Second, habitual residents, (more or less) serial short-term contract workers (or students), stateless persons, refugees and long-term irregular migrants should all enjoy a route to national citizenship. Third, human rights should be available to all migrants on reasonable terms of exercise even if this significantly constrains the range of legitimate policies through which the (methodologically presumed) right of the state to control its own border regime can be exercised. Fourth, socio-economic rights should be broadly available to migrants other than first-time short-term workers who are exempt from a duty to contribute to the state and possibly also irregular migrants although this is indeterminate within the selfimposed methodological limits of this essay. However, I have also sought to draw attention to the way in which the methodological choices that I have adopted can bring to light points at which background norms which are taken, for the purposes of argument, as justified can be thrust into the foreground in ways that require a fuller account of global justice to reflect on their legitimacy. David Owen Politics and International Relations/Centre for Citizenship, Globalization and Governance School of Social Sciences University of Southampton Southampton SO17 1BJ dowen@soton.ac.uk Acknowledgments I am grateful to Jonathan Seglow and Phillip Cook for their organisation of the conference The Margins of Citizenship at which an earlier draft of this paper was presented and for their detailed comments as well as to the other participants for very helpful discussion. Some elements of this essay were also trialled at a conference Non-citizens in liberal democracies – republican and liberal perspectives at the University of Wales, Newport organised by Marit Hovdal Moan and I owe thanks to Marit as well as Iseult Honohan, Chris Bertram, Megan Benton, Phillip Cole, Enzo Rossi, Stuart White and Jules Holroyd for stimulating discussion. Thanks are also owed to my colleagues Andy Mason and Chris Armstrong as well as to Rainer Baubock and Joe Carens for discussion of the arguments that I offer here. Bibliography Baubock, R. (2009) ‘The Rights and Duties of External Citizenship’, Citizenship Studies, vol. 13, no.5, October 2009: 475‐499. Bosniak, L. (2006) The Citizen and the Alien, Princeton, Princeton University Press. Carens, J. (2005) ‘The Integration of Immigrants’, Journal of Moral Philosophy, 2 (1): 29-46. Carens, J. (2008a) ‘Live-in Domestics, Seasonal Workers, and Others Hard to Locate on the Map of Democracy’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 16 (4): 419-445. Carens, J. (2008b) ‘The Rights of Irregular Migrants’, Ethics and International Affairs, 22 (2): 163–186. Dahl, R. (1989), Democracy and Its Critics, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Habermas, J. (1994) ‘Struggles for Recognition in the Constitional Democratic State’ in A, Gutman (ed.) Multiculturalism (2nd edition), pp.107-48. Honohan, I. (2009) ‘Reconsidering the Claim to Family Reunification in Migration’, Political Studies, 57 (4): 768–787. Miller, D. (2007) Nationality Responsibility and Global Justice, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Miller, D. (2008a) ‘Irregular Migrants: An Alternative Perspective’, Ethics and International Affairs, 22 (2): 193-97. Miller, D. (2008b) ‘Immigrants, Nations and Citizenship’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 16 (4): 371-90. Owen, D. (2010) ‘Resident Non-Citizens, Non-resident Citizens and Voting Rights’ in G. Calder et al. Citizenship Acquisition and National Belonging, Basingstoke, Palgrave, pp.52-73. Owen, D. (2011) ‘Transnational Citizenship and the Democratic State’, Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 14 (5): 641-663. Rawls, J. (2005) Political Liberalism (2nd edition), New York, Columba University Press. Rubio-Marin, R. (2000) Immigration as a Democratic Challenge, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Schleffler, S. (2001) Boundaries and Allegiances, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Seglow, J. (2008) ‘Arguments for Naturalisation’, Political Studies 57 (4): 788-804. Tully, J. (2002) ‘The Unfreedom of the Moderns in Comparison to Their Ideals of Constitutional Democracy’, The Modern Law Review, 66 (2): 204-28. Walzer, M. (1983), Spheres of Justice , New York: Basic Books. 1 The methodological reflections and choices of this essay are deeply indebted to the examples and work of Rainer Baubock and Joe Carens. 2 There is a further limitation which I also adopt in this essay largely for reasons of space given the range that I am attempting to cover which is that I focus on 1 st generation adult migrants and not on the case of children. This case in its various dimensions is well covered by Carens (2005, 2008a and 2008b). Partly for this reason I also leave aside family reunion migration. For an illuminating analysis of this topic, see Honohan (2009). 3 For an excellent analysis of the place of this claim in Walzer’s theory, see Bosniak (2006). 4 This point is also central to Rogers Smith (2008) in his argument for the closely related ‘principle of constituted identities’ and is similarly stressed by Carens (2005) in relation to children. 5 Notice, however, that Miller is very careful to limit the potential scope of citizenship tests to exclude cultural issues that don’t directly relate to citizenship and he is also very clear on the social, cultural and political obligations owed by the state to new immigrants and new immigrant communities (2008b: 380-88). 6 We might note that the provision of braille newspapers, of subtitled and signed news programmes as well as increasingly good translation software and global news media already play a significant role in lowering the costs of acquiring political knowledge and engaging in effective civic participation for a range of traditionally marginalised groups. 7 In this essay, for purposes of simplification, I am leaving aside complexities concerning, for example, the option of distinguishing between ‘political membership’ and ‘national citizenship’ which I address elsewhere (Owen 2011). 8 Figures from UNHCR accessed at: http://www.unhcr.org/pages/49c3646c26.html on 30/11/11. 9 Carens does not mention the right to pass on the nationality of the state, presumably because he also argues that children born in, or residing in, a state to have a right to nationality of that state nor does he address external citizenship rights in this context. 10 Nor do they specify whether the status of permanent resident should be a voluntary or mandatory status, an issue that I will also suspend for this discussion. 11 Notice though that a firewall policy fits some human rights better than others. Consider the basic human right of freedom of expression. This right may be thought particularly significant since freedom of speech is basic to the public articulation of claims of injustice. Suppose, then, that an irregular migrant wants to exercise this right to draw attention to abuses of the basic human rights of irregular migrants. This requires public speech and it may matter to the credibility and effectiveness of the testimony offered that the speaker is identified as an irregular migrant. To some extent, this problem may be addressed in this type of case by the use of anonymity strategies in the media (face and voice disguise) combined with credible testimony by the journalist of the irregular status of the speaker, however, even if this protects the right of freedom of speech, it limits the available forms of its exercise. The significance of this point is that it draws attention to the point that we can be said to enjoy human rights more or less fully depending on the range of ways available to us to exercise such rights. In the case of freedom of speech (and related considerations will apply to rights of assembly and protest), the implication is that irregular migrants enjoy a less expansive practical form of this right than other residents of the state and, hence, even when protected by a firewall policy occupy a more marginal position with respect to the civic exercise of rights.