Enjoyment 12, first eight pages Enjoyment What is it to enjoy something? The question arises for us because we will, in the next chapter, claim that to believe that something is beautiful is to believe, on the basis of a special kind of enjoyment, that others will also enjoy the item in that way. We premise our explanation and defense of that claim on the account of enjoyment we give in this chapter. An account of enjoyment is, however, of general interest. Enjoyment is, after all, a nexus at which important concepts meet, including reasons for action, happiness, and goodness. An adequate account of enjoyment should exhibit systematic relations between two aspects of enjoyment: enjoyment as a feeling, and enjoyment as an explanation and justification of action. The feeling varies greatly; compare: the watery relief of satisfying an urgent thirst; sexual gratification; a sudden whiff of perfume; learning that one has received a fervently hoped for grant; the thoughts, associations, and feelings aroused by reading the following lines from the end of Faust, spoken by the angels who intervene to snatch Faust from Mephistopheles: “Wer immer strebend sich bemüht,/Den können wir erlösen.” The variety of feeling does not, however, prevent enjoyment from playing a standard explanatoryjustificatory role. When asked, “Why do you play so much chess?” one provides both an explanation and a justification if one answers, “Because I enjoy it.” We offer an account of enjoyment that exhibits systematic connections between enjoyment as a feeling and its explanatory-justificatory role. We do so by completing the following biconditional: x enjoys Φ if and only if ... , where Φ is an experience or an activity of x. The restriction of values of ‘Φ’ to experiences and activities may sight seem questionable. After all, you can enjoy a meal or a painting. But, of course, you can enjoy the meal only if you eat it; and the painting, only if you look at it; and, in general, where y is something other than an experience or activity, one enjoys y if and only if one enjoys Φ, where Φ is a suitable experience or activity involving y. The restriction on values of ‘Φ’ involves no irrecoverable loss of generality. More importantly, if one examines explanations of the form “because he or she enjoys it”, one finds that what is enjoyed is always either explicitly or implicitly understood to be an experience or an activity, and it is this primacy in explanation that motivates restricting values of ‘Φ’ to experiences and activities; for, as the explanations we advance show, we treat as derivative the enjoyment of things other than experiences and activities. The central idea behind our account is that enjoyment consists in a harmony between three elements: the relevant activity or experience; the features which this activity or experience causes you to believe it has; and a desire to for the activity or experience so conceived. The harmony consists in this: the activity or experience causes a desire which it simultaneously causes one to believe is satisfied. The belief and desire form the nexus at which the felt aspect of enjoyment and its explanatory/justificatory role meet. The belief/desire pair is typically a reason to act so as to have the experience or engage in the activity, and the key to characterizing the way it feels to enjoy something is to note that the relevant desire is a felt desire and the relevant belief an occurrent belief. A final preliminary point: When we describe our enjoyments, we sometimes refer to types of experiences or activities; one may, for example, say “I enjoy sailing” and mean thereby that one generally enjoys a sailing. We may also refer to individual, non-repeatable instances of experiences and activities; one may, for example, say, “I am really enjoying sailing today,” meaning thereby that one is enjoying an individual, non-repeatable instance of the activity. We understand Φ, in “x enjoys Φ,” Φ to range over an individual, non-repeatable instances of experiences and activities. No sharp line. I. Enjoyment and Desire We will argue shortly that one enjoys Φ only if one desires Φ. As a preliminary, we note that we understand ‘desire’ in the broadest possible sense to include such diverse sources of motivation as values, ideals, needs, commitments, personal loyalties, and patterns of emotional reaction. Further, the desire to Φ need not exist prior to one’s enjoying Φ. Suppose, for example, that you find yourself cornered by a talking stranger with whom you have no initial desire to converse; however, you eventually find yourself enjoying conversing. Our claim is that as long as you enjoy conversing, you desire to do so. This will seem to be a mistake to those who think that one can only properly be said to desire that which one lacks; however, that is not our conception of desire. We conceive of a desire as a state that not only causes one to seek what one lacks, but to persist once one finds it.1 In support of the claim that desiring to Φ is necessary condition of enjoying Φ, imagine you are listening to an indifferently performed piano piece. The pianist is your friend; he will ask you if you enjoyed the performance, and you know that that you will say you did. In hopes of avoiding an unconvincing lie, you are trying to enjoy it; unfortunately, the indifferent performance leaves you indifferent—neither desiring to listen, nor desiring not to listen. The complete absence of any desire to listen to the This will seem counterintuitive to those who see desire as related to a "perceived lack," but it should cause no problems to those who think of desires as states that move us to action. See, for example, Brian O'Shaughnessy, The Will (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980), 2, p. 295f.: "A brief word on desire. When action occurs, it is in the final analysis this phenomenon that underlies all of the workings of the act generative mental machinery." Thus desire is what explains my acting so as to maintain ongoing experiences and activities whose occurrence I want, even when I know such experiences are occurring (compare quotes from Hobbes below). O'Shaughnessy characterizes desire as a "striving towards an act of fulfillment" (2, p. 296). In this, he agrees with Aristotle; the root meaning of Aristotle's most general word for desire-'orexis'-is "a reaching out after." Plato is one source of the "perceived lack" view (see the Symposium, for example). This view is indefensible as a general characterization of desire. The problem is revealed by Hobbes. In the Leviathan, Hobbes characterizes desire as an "endeavour . . . toward something which causes it," but he restricts the use of 'desire' to cases in which the object of desire is absent. However, he then notes: "that which men desire, they are also said to LOVE: and to HATE those things for which they have aversion. So that desire and love are the same thing; save that by desire, we always signify the absence of the object; by love most commonly the presence of the same. So also by aversion we signify the absence; and by hate, the presence of the object" (Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, in The English Works of Thomas Hobbes, ed. Sir William Molesworth [London: John Bohn, 1939]). Surely, Hobbes is right. If desire requires the absence of the object, we need a word for that attitude that is just like desire except that its object is present-the attitude that explains why one would resist removal of the object. Remove the object and this attitude is 'desire'. But then why not just say that 'love' and 'desire' are just the same state-whether the object is present or absent? Or at least say that 'love' and 'desire' are instances of some single generic desire-state? As Hobbes says, "love and desire are the same thing." 1 music certainly seems sufficient to show you not are enjoying listening to it. The following considerations provide reinforce this conclusion. Imagine Smith was attending a party which he left after only staying a short while; he complains that he wanted nothing the party had to offer. He mitigates these complaints, however, by confessing that the party was not completely wretched, and that he actually enjoyed it a little. If this confession is consistent with Smith's claim that he wanted nothing the party had to offer, then Smith enjoys the party without any relevant desire. But why should one grant that the confession and the claim are consistent? Suppose we ask Smith what it was that he enjoyed about the party. Smith might refuse to answer this question, for he might insist that he just enjoyed attending the party without enjoying any particular aspect of the party. For the moment, however, let's suppose he answers us by saying that he enjoyed dancing, but he denies he wanted to dance, and he does not merely mean that he did not desire to dance prior to dancing, he means that, throughout the time he was purportedly enjoying dancing, he did not desire to dance. As in the indifferently-performed-music example, the complete lack of a desire to dance is sufficient to establish that Smith did not enjoy dancing. The same considerations would apply if Smith said that what he enjoyed was not dancing but talking with friends, or listening to music, or watching the people, or whatever. In fact, it is difficult to see how Smith can provide any convincing answer to the question of what it was about the party that he enjoyed. But, as we already noted, Smith may reject the question and insist that, while he, neither desired nor enjoyed any particular thing the party had to offer, he nonetheless enjoyed attending the party. Suppose that this is what Smith does, and suppose that he also insists that, even though he enjoyed attending the party, he did not want to be there at all. Is this sufficient to cast doubt on the claim that desiring to Φ is a necessary condition of enjoying Φ? Surely not. Smith at no time desires to attend the party, and does not have any desire for anything the party has to offerdancing, music, conversations with friends, or anything else. This is a crystal clear example of not enjoying a party. We conclude that one enjoys having an experience or engage in an activity Φ only if one desires to have or do Φ. This formulation does not, however, provide a sufficiently perspicuous specification of the required desire. To begin with, Φ is an individual experience or activity about which one has a desire. We will express this by saying that one desires, of Φ, that it occur. Thus, if you are enjoying the experience of tasting bittersweet chocolate, we will describe you as desiring, of that experience, that it occur. This is simply an instance of the following standard Quinean convention. Where ‘[’ and ‘]’ are the left and right Quinean corner quotes, a singular term [t] may be substituted salva veritate for a term [t'] in the context [ ... desires, of t, that . . .] given the true identity [t = t’]. We need one further refinement in our description of desires. To this end, imagine you are enjoying the experience of tasting bittersweet chocolate. The bittersweetness creates and pervades a gustatory field that captures your attention, and it is this bittersweetness that is the aspect of the experience that you desire. We will express this by saying that you desire, of the experience of tasting the chocolate, under the feature bittersweet, that it occur. The “of, under” device is cumbersome and largely unnecessary if one is simply describing particular instances of enjoyment (one can just say, for example, “It is the bittersweetness of the taste that Jones enjoys and desires”), but it is essential if we are to have a perspicuous way of talking in general about enjoyment and desire. Our general claim is that when one enjoys having or doing Φ, there is an array A of one or more features such that one desires, of Φ, under A, that it occur. Take experiences first. The essential point is that to experience something is to experience as being some way. To experience the taste of chocolate is to experience it as bittersweet, or sweet, or as chocolaty, or whatever. One’s experiences always present themselves as experiences of a certain sort. There are no “raw feels,” no experiences that we have without apprehending them as experiences of a certain sort. Thus, to desire to have an experience is to desire to have an experience of a certain sort. In our terminology, it is to desire, of the experience, under some array A of features, that it should occur. A similar point holds for activities. Suppose you are enjoying singing along to a rendition of the choral finale of Beethoven’s Ninth Symphony. You hear the music and the singers, and, in a swirl of emotions, memories, and associations, you feel and hear yourself sing “Freudig, wie ein Held zum Siegen.” In short, you are aware of the activity has having a variety of features, and it is the realization of these features (or some subset of them) that you desire. Again, we express this by saying that you desire, of your activity of singing along, under the relevant array of features, that it should occur. To summarize, when one enjoys having or doing Φ, there is an array of features A such that one desires, of Φ, under A, that it should occur. We take it to be clear that when asked, “What did you enjoy about it?”, one answers by specifying (some of) the features in A. In such a case, we will say x enjoys Φ under A. The “under A” simply provides an explicit representation of what is implicit in our day in day out description of people as enjoying experiences and activities: namely, that there is some desire array of features that are the enjoyers would identify in response to the question, “What do you enjoy about it?” We will therefore define enjoyment by completing “x enjoys Φ under A if and only if ...”