Draft only for discussion – Not to be quoted, shared or published online without consent Comments welcome at arkadiusz.gornisiewicz@uj.edu.pl Arkadiusz Górnisiewicz The Jagiellonian University, Kraków (De)legitimizing modernity? On the uses of the secularization thesis in Karl Löwith, Hans Blumenberg, and Carl Schmitt 1. My paper will try to address what I believe is the foreground of the problem suggested by the workshop’s organizers. It seems that no serious discussion of the intricate relatedness of theology, modernity, and social sciences could avoid the problem that reveals its most conspicuous presence, namely, the secularization thesis. My aim here is to argue that there exists an interesting connection between the use of the secularization thesis and the problem of legitimacy of modernity. The names appearing in the title of my talk have not been picked up at random; the reason behind taking into account Löwith, Blumenberg and Schmitt, though these thinkers seem to differ significantly, is that they all engaged in a very intricate and illuminating exchange of ideas on the notion of secularization and the meaning of modernity. Let me explain at the very outset what is meant here by the notion of legitimacy of modernity, or rather by the notion of the problem of legitimacy of modernity. The question about the legitimacy of modernity is being posed here with regard to the relation of Christianity and modernity. The so called secularization thesis is one of the most hotly debated attempts at an understanding of this relation, and what I claim here is that accepting or rejecting it can be viewed as the key factor contributing towards justification or disapproval of modernity’s claim to be legitimate. The concepts provided by the three thinkers in question, that is Karl Löwith’s classical formulation of the secularization thesis, Hans Blumenberg’s polemical rejection of it, and Carl Schmitt’s rejoinder to the latter, will serve here as model statements on the relation between Christianity and modernity. In order to illustrate my point I will present a brief outline of the debate on the consequences of the secularization thesis, and then proceed to elucidate in what way their distinct approaches towards this theorem correspond with their assessment of 1 modernity’s legitimacy or illegitimacy. I am limiting here to discussing three books, that is Löwith’s Meaning in History, Hans Blumenberg’s The Legitimacy of Modernity, and Carl Schmitt’s Political Theology II, which I must admit is scarcely a limitation. 2. First of all, let us take a glance at Karl Löwith’s secularization thesis which is widely regarded as its classical formulation. It avers that the modern historical consciousness could be basically understood as the result of secularization of Christianity. The key element in Western historical consciousness is accorded by Löwith to the predominance of the eschatological motif, which can be identified in the original Biblical prophets as well as in the modern ones, such as Hegel or Marx. In other words, without having recourse to eschatology – both in its primeval and secularized forms – we are unable to understand one of the most important features of modernity, namely, its historical dynamic and historical restlessness. The importance of the Biblical religion for modern mind (and by this term Löwith understands the common eschatological heritage of Judaism and Christianity) can be really appreciated if one takes into account the profound difference between Greek and Biblical understanding of the relation between God (gods), world, and man. For Greeks – and here we have to leave all ‘buts’ aside – world constitutes a firm order known as kosmos, in which man finds his not all that important place. The world is usually not created, eternal, and even those philosophers – like Plato – who claim it to be created, they do it in a way that recognizes necessities or limitations prior to the creation, which at the same time excludes the idea of an omnipotent God creating world out of nothing. The Greek model of understanding history has much to do with their vision of cosmos and mankind since they take their bearings not on a eschatological belief in transcendent personal God, but rather on cosmos-related law of coming into existence and perishing away of all beings. They know their lot in advance since every man must finally submit to the fate or necessity, ananke, that governs all cosmic reality. According to this view reality is confined within eternal returns, which do not give much hope for coming into being anything that is radically new or previously unknown. Löwith shows that the cyclical conception of time is present both in great Greek historians and philosophers (Herodot, Thucydides, Polybius, Plato). Löwith’s views may be summarized briefly as follows: We would not ask the questions about the meaning of history if this meaning was revealed by the very historical occurrences, but, 2 on the other hand, we could proclaim history to be nonsense only after it has failed to conform to our expectations. These expectations towards history has been established by the Hebrew and Christian thinking that brought the question about the ultimate meaning of history into existence. Since for Jews and Christians history is primarily a history of salvation, the Biblical concept of history is progressive and linear, and it overcomes the ancient reverence for fate and fortuna. Löwith claims that the Biblical concept of history is futuristic. Why? Because it is directed towards the final goal which is salvation: In the Hebrew and Christian view of history the past is a promise to the future(…) the interpretation of the past becomes a prophecy in reverse, demonstrating the past as a meaningful ‘preparation’ for the future. The Church fathers developed theology of history that underlined such transcendent and salvation-oriented themes as creation of the world, incarnation or Judgment Day, whereas modernity progressively replaced it with philosophy of history, which still operates within a horizon of future, with this crucial exception that the goal of history is no longer claimed to be transcendent or other-worldly but immanent or inner-worldly. By presenting the turning points in the process of secularization Löwith tries to convince us that were it not for Jewish and Christian faith, the modern concept of progress would have barely occupied the central place of the modern historical consciousness. Carl Schmitt expressed his general approval of Löwith’s view on the origin of progressive thinking and especially agreed with his claim that the pagan world is essentially unable to develop any kind of genuine historical thinking. In turn, the main difference between them does not relate to any details of the historical narration on secularization, but rather the relation between Christianity and history. While Löwith’s thesis focuses on the birth of modern historical consciousness, Schmitt’s concept of secularization applies primarily to the political and juristic field. In oft-quoted phrase from Political Theology Schmitt says that All significant theological concepts of the modern theory of the state are secularized theological concepts. According to Schmitt it is crucial to understand not only the historical transmission of theology into political theory, but also the structural similarity that connects one with the another (for example, an analogy between God and the omnipotent lawgiver, miracle and the state of exception). It is also worth noticing that this structural similarity extends much beyond, since the metaphysical image that a definite epoch forges of the world has the same structure as what the world immediately understands to be appropriate as a form of its political organization. The determination of such an identity is the sociology of the concept of sovereignty. Accordingly, 3 XVII century theism corresponds with absolute monarchy, while deism – with its rejection of an active God’s involvement with the human affairs – relates to the modern state, which has its origins in the Enlightenment rationalism and rejects the very possibility of the exceptional situation as it denies the very possibility of miracles. 2. In his monumental book The Legitimacy of Modernity Hans Blumenberg takes on the secularization thesis by claiming that it is seriously flawed and develops his own position that aims to account for the emergence of the modern idea of progress. He claims that the so called secularization thesis has become increasingly influential and widely accepted. Blumenberg has launched a multilayered attack on the concept of secularization, especially as proposed by Löwith, whose approach he takes as an exemplary; here we will underline some of the most characteristic elements of his criticism. First of all, he doubts whether what comes under the term of secularization can be historically proven. His skepticism is based on the fact that the theories of secularization usually establish an unambiguous relation between what they claim to be original or primordial historical source and what has become secularized. Secularization thesis presupposes the existence of uncorrupted substance which in turn becomes alienated from the original and its function, though it still preserves something that allows us to claim that the latter is derived from the former (i.e, the Marxist Kingdom of freedom as a secularized version of the Kingdom of Heaven). Blumenberg’s rejection of the category of historical substances is based on the belief that it is impossible to preserve an identity of content through vast periods of times, as well as to claim absolute rights to ownership of ideas (i.e., the concept of Providence is crucial for Christianity, but it cannot claim its ownership since it is of Stoical origin). Blumenberg reconsiders the concept of progress and argues that there are striking obstacles that should have prevented the emergence of the idea of progress out of the Christian eschatology. Firstly, the future projected by the idea of progress is the product of the immanent historical development and has little in common with a vision of Messianic intervention in history. Secondly, if hope is claimed to be the common denominator between the eschatological expectations of Christianity and that of secular idea of progress, then it is also inaccurate since the Christian position towards the final things was characterized rather not by hope but fear for much part of its history. He proposes his own account of the birth of the concept of progress, and modernity in general. In looking for its historical origins he pays attention not so much to the 4 early modernity, but to the late Middle Ages. In his view the key for the birth of modernity is the emergence of voluntarism and nominalism associated with the doctrines of John Duns Scotus and Willliam Ockham. By bringing to the central place the issue of God’s omnipotence and free will, they succeeded in undermining the scholastic philosophy which was based on the effort to reconcile faith and reason. Voluntarism and nominalism in this way shattered the belief in the cosmic order which has been defended by the scholastic Aristotelianism. Given the absolute and unbound God’s power to create and annihilate everything what He pleases, the finite world becomes completely contingent and no longer can be viewed as the realization of the perennial pattern (as in the case of Plato’s Timaeus). According to Blumenberg, with the embracing of voluntarism and nominalism Middle Ages arrived at a sort of theological and historical “dead end”. Now there are basically two possibilities: one is to crave for salvation which ultimately has less to do with human doings than with God’s grace which cannot be put under man’s scrutiny; another possibility is to venture beyond this point by trying to create an environment that would lend support to man’s uneasy position. To follow the second path is to embark on an existential project that Blumenberg describes with the term self-assertion (Selbstbehauptung), which by no means could be identified with the Hobbesian notion of self-preservation (Selbsterhaltung). His conclusion is that the emergence of the concept of progress is due to the medieval theological and philosophical crisis, it is in fact a response to the claims of theological absolutism and it cannot be seen as a result of secularization of Christian eschatology. For Blumenberg it is no coincidence that there exists connection between late medieval nominalism and early modern atomism: the process of materialization of nature is correlated with theological absolutism because man deprived by God’s hiddenness of metaphysical guarantees for the world (…) constructs for himself a counterworld (Gegenwelt) of elementary rationality and manipulability. However, the question remains: Why the empirical notion of progress, which Blumenberg conceives as an limited and “local” was overstretched and eventually became part of modern philosophy of history and served to answer the question about the historical process in general? Blumenberg has his own intriguing answer to this appropriation of the notion of progress. In order to explain this process he introduces the concept of “relocation” or “reoccupation” (Umbesetzung). This concept is very similar – although Blumenberg never acknowledges this – to the concept of the pseudomorposis in Oswald Spengler’s The Decline of the West. The very term is derived from geology and applied to explain historical phenomena. It 5 describes the process when water washes out the content of rock-stratum and then something else – a material that is of foreign origin – fill up the empty spaces: Thus there arise distorted forms, crystals whose inner structure contradicts their external shape, stones of one kind presenting the appearance of stones of another kind. By the term "historical pseudomorphosis" I propose to designate those cases in which an older alien Culture lies so massively over the land that a young Culture, born in this land, cannot get its breath and fails not only to achieve pure and specific expression-forms, but even to develop fully its ownself-consciousness. Blumenberg’s concept of relocation serves exactly the same end. He claims that the new culture or new contents of modernity, especially the idea of progress, have been forced to perform the old function within a system of problems that was not his own, but inherited from the Middle Ages. The idea of progress was forced to answer the questions about the meaning of history and became part of modern philosophies of history, but those questions were not the original questions of modernity. They were inherited and the idea of progress simply filled up the empty spaces left by the theological absolutism. The idea of progress is the new content filling up the old empty rock-stratum and it is forced to perform function that is alien to its origin. 3. Now we can see that in Blumenberg’s alternative picture of the birth of modernity there is no place for secularization thesis. We have arrived at a point that reveals the major discrepancies between the three thinkers in question. Löwith’s secularization thesis may be used to undermine the legitimacy of modernity because it reveals modernity’s Christian origins and anti-Christian consequences. In response Blumenberg examines the secularization thesis and comes to a conclusion that it is a category of historical injustice. When he criticizes secularization thesis and proposes his alternative view on the origins of modern idea of progress, he is at the same time disarming secularization as a scientific tool that may be used to undermine the legitimacy of the modern age. It would not be presumptuous to claim that his criticism of secularization thesis is conducive towards his major task known as the defense of modernity’s legitimacy. But if modernity is most of all defined in terms of self-assertion and autonomy, if it really embarked on a completely new path of emancipation from the tradition, then the question arises why Blumenberg poses the very question about its legitimacy. Where is the tribunal before 6 which one could provide such a justification? That’s the serious and profound question asked by Carl Schmitt in his postscript to Political Theology II. Schmitt develops his polemical statement by shedding light on the notion of legitimacy. He reminds us that the word legitimacy was understood for centuries as the monopoly for the legitimation of dynasties. In other words, it was a justification of continuity, tradition, upbringing and heritage. Blumenberg completely reverses this meaning because in his project modernity’s legitimacy seems to be simply grounded in a justification issuing from the novelty, from the very fact that modernity constitutes break with the tradition. Thus Schmitt accuses Blumenberg of having confused the legitimacy (rechtmassig) and legality (gesetzmassig); and legality since the French Revolution was regarded to be a new mode of legitimacy because it was a message from the goddess of Reason, from the new opposed to the old. Now it seems that we can justly claim that for Schmitt there is no legitimacy without some kind of historical continuation. Secularization would be then in certain sense a category of legitimation since it creates historical identity and still grants us access to the theological depths. At this point we also begin to grasp the difference between Löwith’s and Schmitt’s understanding of Christianity. Löwith perceives Christianity as an essentially eschatological religion which above is concerned with salvation and not with historical process. Schmitt, on the contrary, conceives Christianity above all as a great civilization, as an awe-inspiring edifice of the Holy Roman Empire, thus he pays much more attention to historical continuity. Taking care of it reveals itself to be a major task since it holds back the forces of Antichrist and in this way delays the end of the world. The concept of translatio imperii and of the Restrainer (Aufhalter, katechon) are very closely linked and provide the common ground for coming together of eschatology and historical effectiveness: The belief that a restrainer holds back the end of the world provides the only bridge between the notion of an eschatological paralysis of all human events and a tremendous historical monolith like that of the Christian empire of great Germanic kings. Schmitt’s disagreement with Blumenberg runs very deep indeed. In Schmitt’s view the most threatening aspect of Blumenberg’s project can be labeled as an attempt at detheologization of modernity. It is striking that Schmitt interprets Blumenberg’s project as a scientific attempt at a closure of political theology reminding us about a completely different – because based on intra-theological and not scientific arguments – attempt made thirty years earlier by Erik Peterson. Modernity in Blumenberg’s view becomes detheolgized because it aims to exclude 7 theology both in its pure and secularized forms, and in this way it threatens something which is of highest importance for Schmitt. Blumenberg also claims that modernity is the second after St. Augustine – and this time successful – attempt at overcoming Gnosticism. For this reason, in the light of Schmitt’s thesis of correspondence between the metaphysical picture of an epoch and its political structure, modernity as an emancipation from theology must at the same time be a depolarization of the political sphere. In other words, it undermines the political which – as we all know – Schmitt defines as being driven by the distinction between friend and enemy. The theological root of the political is either the Manichean enmity between God and Devil or Gnostic enmity between God of creation and God of salvation. For Schmitt’s concept of the political is theologically grounded and ultimately concerns the very nature of God. That is why Schmitt in his late treatise engages in his own Christological speculation: he does it in order to theologically support his concept of the political. In the final analysis, what proves to be at stake in the debate on secularization is the political itself. If theology is no longer taken into account, any discussion about the legitimacy of modernity seems to lose its ground. The very impossibility of raising the question regarding the legitimacy of modernity becomes apparent. According to Schmitt by eliminating theology even in the form of secularization or relocations modernity would become totally enclosed and no longer susceptible of having to justify its claims and positions. The alleged autism or selfconcealment of modernity would be then brought to its completion. 8