I. Thomson’s case for the permissibility of abortion. Thomson presents a defense of the claim that abortions are primafacie permissible, that is, if some particular abortion is morally impermissible, this is not because it is an abortion, but because this particular act of abortion does something else that is wrong. She grants (for the sake of argument) that fetuses have a right to life from conception, but argues that abortions are nonetheless not, per se, morally impermissible. More precisely, Thomson claims: 1) Even if fetuses have rights to life, abortion will not in general violate those rights. 2) Except in special cases, cases in which the mother has intentionally undertaken an obligation to bring the fetus to term, abortions will not violate any other right of the fetus. 3) Abortions will sometimes violate duties of beneficence, but will not generally do so unless those duties are much more stringent than we generally take them to be. II. Background Thomson’s defense proceeds in stages. She first argues for an interpretation of rights to life on which not all killings violate rights to life. On that interpretation, abortions will violate fetal rights to life only if the fetuses have a property right to their mothers’ bodies. So she next argues for a principle about the transfer of property rights on which mothers won’t confer such rights on a fetus without explicitly intending so to do. Finally, she considers whether duties of beneficence are violated by abortions; she does not defend any particular formulation of such duties, but rather says any cogent formulation will have to count some particular abortions as permissible, and others as impermissible. In between those two kinds of cases there is a large grey area—her position is that the debate about abortion ought to focus on what duties of beneficence requires of mothers in that grey area. Rights=a source for moral obligations. Rights are rights to something, to some good (this can be a thing, a service, a liberty, etc.). Rights are also rights against someone else—a right is infringed in that someone else deprives one of the good in question. Put differently, rights generate obligations; if I have a right against someone to a certain good, that someone is obliged not to infringe on by use of that good. Sometimes a right is against one particular person—a contractual property right is a case in point. If I have sold the bricks in my back yard to X, then X has a right against me that I should allow her to retrieve the bricks; I have the related obligation. But you may well not have that obligation. So I am obliged to unlock my gate so she can get access to the bricks. But you are not obliged to open the gate for her. Other rights are rights against everyone—human rights are like this; the right not to be tortured is a right against everyone, because anyone who tortures X violates her right not to be tortured. Some rights are positive—they are rights to be given the good in question, while others are negative—they are rights not to be interfered with while pursuing or using the good in question. The right to a k-12 education is a positive right against all our fellow citizens; the right to freedom of conscience is a negative right against all our fellow citizens. We also need a distinction between ‘active’ and ‘passive’ killing. Roughly, a killing is passive if it is a ‘letting die’—one stands by while other causes produce the death; it is active if one directly causes the death. So, e.g., if one motors by in one’s boat Igor, who is drowning, without stopping to help, the killing is passive. If one throws Igor out of one’s boat, and then motors off, the killing is active. As it turns out, the distinction is not well formulated, but it is intuitive, and fairly commonly drawn. Finally, some terminology. Thomson thinks there are two ways an action can be wrong. It can violate a duty of beneficence, in which case it is said to be indecent and wrong for this reason. Or It can violate a right held by somebody, in which case it is said to by unjust and wrong for this reason. Actions can be both indecent and unjust, and so doubly wrong. Unjust actions are always morally impermissible, for Thomson. So too are indecent actions—TO SAY AN ACTION IS INDECENT IS TO SAY IT IS MORALLY WRONG, IMPERMISSIBLE, EVIL. The difference between indecent and unjust acts is just that though each violates some obligation, the source of those obligations differs. III. The argument for weak negative rights to life. Thomson aims to defend a principle about what rights to life require of us with respect to their bearers—just when does a killing violate a right to life? She never explicitly formulates the principle, but it can be put this way: P: If X, or someone Z acting on X’s behalf, kills Y by depriving Y of G, where Y requires G to survive, but X has a right to G while Y does not, then Y’s right to life is not violated. If principle P is correct, three things must be true. Rights to life are negative; that is, they are rights against being unjustly killed (whatever this turns out to mean), but they are not rights to all that is required to survive. Rights to life are not necessarily violated by ‘active’ killings. Rights to life are not necessarily violated when third parties kill one person to protect the property rights of another. Thomson argues for each in turn. In each case she does so by presenting a scenario, an ‘analogy’, about which (she thinks) we will have very strong intuitions which are consistent with the claims above, and so with principle P, but which are not consistent with alternative principles about rights to life on which abortion violates those rights. A. Rights to life are negative—i.e. they are not rights to all that is required to survive. Thomson asks us to consider the case of the violinist: the most famous violinist in the world is dying, but he can be saved if you are used to filter his blood (you and only you have the right genotype to do this). The society of music lovers kidknaps you and, against your will, hooks you up to the violinist. At this point, if you unhook yourself in order to make your escape, the violinist will die. She then considers several versions which differ in the amount of time you must be hooked up to violinist if he is not to die—9 days, 9 weeks, 9 years, forever. She thinks that, in one of these cases, you will agree that it is ok to unplug yourself. But if you do, you kill the violinist. So you must think in that case no injustice is done (for then the unplugging would be morally impermissible, and so not ok). Hence, it cannot be that you violate the violinist’s right to life when you do this. But you are depriving him of that which he requires to survive, namely your body. Hence, the right to life cannot be a positive right to all that is required for survival. It is instead a negative right against being unjustly killed. And in particular, one does not violate a right to life if one deprives another of that which they require to survive, provided one has a right to it and one’s victim does not. B. Rights to life are not necessarily violated by active killings. Thomson asks us to consider a case of active killing in self defense. A women is trapped inside her own house with a growing child. She is not responsible for the child being in the house; someone snuck it in. She cannot escape except by killing the child; if she does not kill the child the child will grow so big it crushes her to death. Thomson thinks we will think that in this case it is ok for her to actively kill the child in order to save her life. (The example is implausible; it suffices here to think of any active killing in self defense, of which there are any number of real cases). If you say about this, or any other, active killing that it is permissible, then it cannot be that a killing violates a right to life simply because it is active—for if that were true, every active killing would be unjust, and therefore morally impermissible. C. Rights to life are not necessarily violated if some third party acts to secure one’s property from a victim who requires it to survive but does not have a right to it. Thomson asks us consider Smith and Jones. Both are indigent, and will freeze to death on this particular winter night without a coat. Jones owns a coat, but Smith has taken it. Thomson thinks that we will think that it is ok if a passer by takes Jones’s coat back from Smith, and that certain people, e.g. police, are morally obliged so to do. But doing that kills Smith, since he then freezes without the coat. So this third party intervention, though a killing, cannot violate Smith’s right to life, for if it did, the killing would be unjust, and therefore impermissible. IV. Application of principle P to Abortion. Thomson makes one further, and more or less undefended assumption: people own their own bodies. One has a property right to one’s body, i.e. a right against everyone else that they shall not infringe upon your use of your body. Thomson is then in a position to argue for the prima facie permissibility of abortion, i.e. that abortions do not, per se, violate fetal rights to life. In an abortion an doctor (third party) acts to secure for a woman a bit of her property (her body). She has a right to her body, and her fetus does not. But the (pre-term) fetus requires to the body to survive. In depriving the fetus of the body, the doctor kills the fetus. But this is not a violation of the fetuses’ right to life—it does not have a right to that which it requires for survival, and so when it is deprived of this and so dies, its right to life has not been violated. Possible Objections: 1. An alternative conception of the right to life on which abortions violate that right, but the killings in the violinist, house, and coat cases do not. Morally relevant facts to exploit—whether a death results from the deprivation of that which is required to survive, or is produced in order to deprive it of that which is required to survive. D2. Deny that people own their bodies. V. Special Obligations. One might respond to the case so far by claiming that while Thomson’s case about rights to life is ok, and so to the claim that women have property rights to their bodies, the claim that the fetus does not have a right its mother’s body is mistaken. Mother’s somehow have a special obligation to their fetuses, and those obligations amount to a right of the fetus against the mother for the use of her body. Thomson considers such a line of response. She replies by defending a principle about the transfer of property rights. According to this principle, one transfers a property right to another only if one implicitly or explicitly undertakes the associated obligations, and one does this only if one intends to undertake them. She defends the principle by arguing against an alternative, which would, if it were right, provide a source for the special obligation between mothers and fetuses. On this principle, which we will call the risk principle, a women transfers to a fetus the property right to her body if she engages in actions which risk pregnancy. The risk principle is motivated by the following thought. When women voluntarily act in ways that risk pregnancy, they are in part responsible for the existence of any resulting fetus. This responsibility entails moral obligations, which amount to transferring to the fetus a property right to the mother’s body. A. Suppose you open a window, through which a burglar enters. You have risked the burglar coming into possession of your property. On the risk principle, you will therefore have transferred to him a property right to your house and possessions. You cannot now kick him out if he sits down to watch the game while drinking your beer. This, we think, is absurd, so we must reject the risk principle. One does not transfer a property right simply by voluntarily acting in a way that risks another coming into possession of your property. B. If the risk principle were right, every pregnancy would involve a special obligation—one can prevent pregnancy by seeking a voluntary hysterectomy. Not doing so is a voluntary action that risks pregnancy. Hence, given the risk principle, any pregnancy involves the transfer of a property right to the fetus, and so involves the associated obligations. Since we must reject the risk principle, we need another. What is common to all the cases in which our intuitions are inconsistent with the risk principle is that while we act voluntarily in ways that risk another coming into possession of our property, we do not intend, either explicitly or implicitly, by those acts or any others, to transfer a property right. So Thomson infers that property rights are transferred only when one intends to transfer them, only when one intends to undertake the obligations associated with such a transfer. It should be pointed out that, for Thomson, once a property right has been transferred to a fetus, for whatever reason, the fetus may not be aborted. Even if the life of the mother is threatened by continued pregnancy, once she has transferred to the fetus a property right to her body, the abortion would be an unjust killing of the fetus, and so would violate its right to life. VI. Beneficence. Thomson draws a distinction between duties of beneficence and duties generated by rights using the Henry Fonda, Chocolate, and Kitty Genovese cases. Given the distinction, she says beneficence requires minimal decency, but not good Samaritanism—small sacrifices are required to do large benefits. Large sacrifices aren’t required. So, e.g., Henry Fonda is morally required to walk across the hospital hall to save Thomson’s life; he is not morally required to fly across the country to do so. Similarly, the bystanders in the Genovese case are morally required to call the cops; they are not required to take baseball bat in hand and descend to fight on her behalf. Doing this would be supererogatory, and so a case of Good, rather than merely Minimally Decent, Samaritanism. She does not say exactly how much sacrifice must be endured. But she does say there are cases of abortion which clearly do, and other cases which clearly don’t, violate our duties of beneficence. If a women aborts a pregnancy in the eighth month in order to go on a trip to Paris, and for no other reason, this would be indecent. The trip is a small sacrifice, the life of the fetus is a large benefit. The women is therefore morally wrong if she aborts. On the other hand, a teen pregnant from rape is not morally required to carry a pregnancy to term, and she is not indecent if she aborts; on the contrary, she is a more than good Samaritan if she carries the pregnancy to term, for doing this is supererogatory. Objections: 1) find a principle about the transfer of property rights consistent with the burglar and hysterectomy cases, but on which pregnancies from voluntary sexual activity (or voluntary sexual activity without use of birth control) does confer a property right to the fetus. 2) define a standard of decency on which all, or almost all, abortions violate the standard.