D:\116103060.doc Printed On 2/12/2016: International Law and Rogue States: The Failure of the Charter Framework Anthony Clark Arend The concept of “rogue state” has been much maligned in the past. Appearing to some to be nothing more than an ideological tag with no content, the term was being eased out of much official discussion. As is well noted, the Department of State had changed its designation from “rogue states” to “states of concern.” But in the wake of the terrorist attacks of September 11, 2001, the idea of a “rogue state” seems to have returned. Indeed, in his State of the Union Address in January 2002, President George W. Bush went so far as to place three states -- Iran, Iraq, and North Korea -- in an “Axis of Evil.”1 Without going to that extreme, the moniker “rogue state” nonetheless does seem to be useful for understanding the behavior of certain regimes in light of international law. In a sense, a rogue state is one that does not follow the rules. While almost all states may at times violate international legal rules, a rogue state would be a perennial violator. It would, in essence, be a state whose identity is to some extent defined by acting outside of the standard rules of international law.2 But from the perspective of international jurisprudence an even greater problem is that while as such a state may be violating well-established international legal rules, it may also be engaging in behavior that was not anticipated when the rules were developed. In particular, a rogue state may use military force in ways that classic international law did not address. And here is the problem for international law. Since the rules developed to respond to certain classic uses of force, it is often unclear how the traditional rules of international law apply to the behavior of rogue states. How does international law respond to actions by Professor of Government and Adjunct Professor of Law, Georgetown University. The author wishes to thank Robert J. Beck for his collaboration on these issues over the years and Michael J. Glennon for his recent work on the use of force. This article draws upon Professor Glennon’s approach to these crucial legal questions. 1. George W. Bush, State of the Union Address (January 29, 2002) available at http://www.whitehouse.gov/news/releases/2002/01/20020129-11.html (“States like these [Iraq, North Korea, and Iran], and their terrorist allies, constitute an axis of evil, arming to threaten the peace of the world”). 2. An analogy could be drawn to a criminal organization. The very identity of such an organization is tied to the fact that it is acting outside established legal norms. 735 D:\116103060.doc 736 Printed On 2/12/2016: NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 36:4 rogue states that fall outside the parameters of traditional international law? If a rogue state engages in covert actions against another state, supports rebels in another state, supports the work of terrorist groups, commits human rights abuses against its own citizens, or develops weapons of mass destruction, how does the existing international legal regime respond? The purpose of this article is to explore several of the challenges posed by rogue states relating to the recourse to force and to explore some efforts to respond to these challenges. In order to do this, this article will do four things. First, it will discuss the United Nations Charter framework for the use of force -- the most widely accepted legal paradigm for contemporary international law relating to the recourse to force. Second, it will explain several problems that rogue states pose to that framework. Third, it will explore efforts by the international community to respond to those problems, arguing that the international community has not yet developed a clear approach to the challenges of rogue states. Fourth, it will conclude that the challenges posed by rogue states are merely a part of the challenges posed to the Charter framework by the community of states at large and suggest that efforts need to be made to establish a general rule-based regime for the use of force. I. THE UNITED NATIONS CHARTER FRAMEWORK FOR THE RECOURSE TO FORCE Over the years, customary international law has come to recognize two elements of the international law dealing with the use of force: the jus ad bellum and the jus in bello. The jus ad bellum deals with the legal rules concerning the recourse to force.3 It asks the question of when an actor has the right to take recourse to military force against another actor. Can, for example, Iraq lawfully invade Kuwait? Can other states use force to respond to that invasion? Can the United States use force against Iraq for its noncompliance with the weapons inspections regime established by the United Nations Security Council? The jus in bello contains the rules dealing with the conduct of hostilities. It explores the rules concerning how all actors in a conflict have to behave, irrespective of who had the right to initiate hostilities in the first place. Thus, the jus in bello asks questions such as: what types of targets are permissible in combat? How are non-combatants to be treated? How are prisoners are war to be cared for by their captors? While both sets of rules would apply to the behavior of rogue states, this article 3. For a discussion of the law relating to the recourse to force, see generally ANTHONY C LARK AREND & R OBERT J. B ECK, INTERNATIONAL LAW AND THE U SE OF F ORCE: B EYOND THE U.N. C HARTER P ARADIGM (1993); CHRISTINE GRAY , INTERNATIONAL LAW AND THE USE OF F ORCE (2000). D:\116103060.doc 2002] FAILURE OF THE CHARTER FRAMEWORK Printed On: 2/12/2016 737 will focus on the jus ad bellum– the legal rules that address the question of when an international actor can permissibly use force. Since 1945, most discussions of the law relating to the recourse to military force have begun with an exploration of the United Nations Charter framework. Coming out of two devastating world wars, the founders of the United Nations sought to establish an extremely restrictive approach to the use of force. To do this, the Charter begins with a fundamental presumption against the recourse to force. Article 2, paragraph 4 of the Charter provides: All Members [of the United Nations] shall refrain in their international relations from the threat or use of force against the territorial integrity or political independence of any state, or in any other manner inconsistent with the Purposes of the United Nations.4 This provision seemed to constitute a basic proscription on both the actual use and the threat to use force against another state. It is even more restrictive than the much-criticized Kellogg-Briand Pact of 1928,5 which only prohibited “war” not all uses and threats of force. In the Charter, there are only two explicit exceptions to this Article 2(4) prohibition that are still applicable: self-defense, and force authorized by the United Nations Security Council. The first exception is contained in Article 51, which provides in part: Nothing in the present Charter shall impair the inherent right of individual or collective self-defence if an armed attack occurs against a Member of the United Nations, until the Security Council has taken measures necessary to maintain international peace and security.6 Thus, if a state is experiencing an “armed attack,” it is permissible for that state to use military force against the states that have instituted that attack. The victim state can also call upon other states to help it fend off the attacker in collective self-defense. So, for example, when Argentina attacked the Falkland Islands in 1982,7 the United Kingdom responded in self-defense in response to an armed attack and could have asked other states for assistance in this effort. The second exception to the Article 2(4) prohibition is contained in other portions of Chapter VII of the Charter. Under Article 39, the Security Council is empowered to determine if there has been a “threat to the peace,” 4. U.N. CHARTER , art. 2, para. 4. 5. Kellogg-Briand Pact, Aug. 27, 1928, Stat. 46, 2343, T.S. No. 796, 94 L.N.T.S. 57. 6. U.N. CHARTER , art. 51. 7. On the Falklands War, see generally LOWELL F. GUSTAFSON , THE S OVEREIGNTY DISPUTE OVER THE F ALKLAND (M ALVINAS) ISLANDS (1988); THE F ALKLANDS W AR : LESSONS FOR S TRATEGY , DIPLOMACY , AND INTERNATIONAL LAW (Alberto R. Coll & Anthony C. Arend eds., 1985). D:\116103060.doc Printed On 2/12/2016: 738 NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 36:4 a “breach of the peace,” or an “act of aggression.”8 If the Council so determines, it is further authorized under Article 419 to impose diplomatic and economic sanctions and under Article 4210 to impose military sanctions. This is precisely what happened in the Gulf War.11 After the invasion of Kuwait on August 2, 1990, the United Nations Security Council met and immediately condemned the Iraqi invasion.12 Soon thereafter, the Council adopted resolution 661,13 which imposed sweeping economic and diplomatic sanctions on Iraq. Ultimately, the Council decided to adopt resolution 678,14 authorizing states with troops deployed in the region to use force to remove Iraq from Kuwait. II. ROGUE STATES AND THE CHARTER The Charter framework seems quite well suited to address the types of force with which the framers of the Charter would have been most familiar - clear, overt acts of aggression undertaken by regular military forces of states. No doubt, these were the kinds of uses of force that the framers were 8. Article 39 provides: The Security Council shall determine the existence of any threat to the peace, breach of the peace, or act of aggression and shall make reco mmendations, or decide what measures shall be taken in accordance with Articles 41 and 42, to maintain or restore international peace and sec urity. U.N. CHARTER ., art. 39. 9. Id. art. 41. 10. Article 42 provides: Should the Security Council consider that the measures provided for in Article 41 [diplomatic and economic sanctions] would be inadequate or have proven to be inadequate, it may take such action by air, sea, or land forces as may be necessary to maintain or restore international peace and security. Such action may include demonstrations, blockade, and other operations by air, sea, or land forces of Members of the United Nations. Id. art. 42. 11. For a discussion of international law and the Gulf War, see Oscar Schachter, United Nations Law in the Gulf Conflict, 85 AM . J. INT’ L L.452, 452 (1991). 12. See U.N. S.C. Res. 660, U.N. SCOR, 45th Sess., 2932nd mtg., U.N. Doc. S/RES/660 (1990). . 13. U.N. S.C. Res. 661, U.N. SCOR, 45th Sess., 2922rd mtg.,U.N. Doc. S/RES/661 (1990). . 14. Resolution 678 authorized: Member States co-operating with the Government of Kuwait, unless Iraq on or before 15 January 1991 fully implements, as set forth in paragraph 1 above, the above-mentioned resolutions, to use all necessary means to uphold and implement resolution 660 (1990) and all subsequent relevant resolutions and to restore international peace and sec urity in the area. U.N. S.C. Res., U.N. SCOR, 45th Sess., 2963rd mtg., U.N. Doc. S/RES/678 (1990). D:\116103060.doc 2002] FAILURE OF THE CHARTER FRAMEWORK Printed On: 2/12/2016 739 envisioning when the Charter was written in San Francisco in the spring of 1945.15 The world had just been shaken by the aggressive actions of Germany, Japan, and Italy. Under the Charter system, such actions would be clearly prohibited, and states would be empowered to respond, either in selfdefense or as authorized by the Security Council. The problem is that most of the uses of force that have taken place in the world since 1945 have not fallen easily into the neat definitions provided by the framers of the Charter. In particular, many of the challenges posed by rogue states are not clearly addressed by the Charter framework. Three challenges seem most acute. First, rogue states often do not engage in obvious armed attacks, but instead use force against other international actors in ways that do not squarely fall under the textbook definition of “armed attack.” Second, rogue states frequently engage in actions against their domestic populations that do not constitute international aggression, but may nonetheless be horrible violations of international human rights law. Third, rogue states may possess or seek to possess or develop weapons of mass destruction. While the mere possession of these weapons, or potential possession of these weapons, does not constitute an actual armed attack, such actions by the rogue states may still threaten international peace. The Armed Attack Threshold When a state launches a conventional military attack against another state -- when armies cross the borders, bombs are dropped on the territory of a state, or naval vessels fire cruise missiles -- an armed attack has occurred. Hence, the Iraqi invasion of Kuwait clearly was an armed attack that engendered a right of self-defense under Article 51. But, while rogue states like Iraq are not strangers to this type of action, many of the uses of force undertaken by such states do not fall under the standard definition of armed attack. Several such uses of force include: covert action, intervention in support of rebels, and, perhaps most notably, various forms of support for terrorist actions. Covert Action and Support of Rebels A covert action is an act by a state in which it attempts to influence the political, economic, or other conditions of the state without that action being known. While commentators often only think of the most dramatic types of covert actions -- such as efforts to assassinate state leaders -- covert actions run the spectrum from the least forceful, such as propaganda, financial support of political parties, bribing of government officials, to the most force- 15. For a discussion of the United Nations Charter, see generally THE C HARTER UNITED N ATIONS: A COMMENTARY (Bruno Simma ed., 1994). OF THE D:\116103060.doc 740 Printed On 2/12/2016: NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 36:4 ful, such as blowing up military installations in another states and forcible actions against regime elites. From the perspective of international law, the critical question is under what circumstances such actions would rise to the level of an armed attack. A similar problem presents itself when a state intervenes -- either covertly or overtly -- in an on-going civil conflict to support rebel groups that are challenging the existing regime. This type of involvement in internal conflict has occurred repeatedly during the period since World War II. During the Nicaragua conflict in the 1980's, for example, the United States accused the Sandinista government of Nicaragua of providing various types of financial and other support to the Farabundo Marti de Liberacion Nacional (the “FMLN”) rebels in El Salvador.16 While such actions would constitute impermissible interference in the internal affairs of a state, when does assistance– money, arms, training, logistical support, etc. – reach the point of being tantamount to an armed attack? When could the aggrieved state take arms against the intervening state? A. Terrorism In light of the September 11th attacks and the response of the U.S. and its allies, one of the most pressing questions regarding the armed attack threshold relates to terrorism. While efforts to “define” terrorism have been undertaken numerous times over the years,17 terrorism will be defined here as the threat or use of force, undertaken for political purposes, by a non-state actor that intentionally targets civilians and other non-combatants in violation of existing law relating to the conduct of hostilities. Hence, actions such as the attacks on the World Trade Center would clearly meet the definition of terrorism. Not surprisingly, rogue states are frequently involved in supporting, in one way or another, the efforts of terrorist groups. During the recent action in Afghanistan, for example, the Taliban regime was found by the Security Council to have provided support to the Al Qaeda terrorists in their efforts against the United States and other targets throughout the world.18 16. For an exploration of the American position, see generally JOHN NORTON M OORE, THE S ECRET WAR IN CENTRAL AMERICA (1987); ROBERT F. TURNER , NICARAGUA V . UNITED S TATES: A LOOK AT THE F ACTS (1987). 17. See Walter Gary Sharp, Sr., The Use of Armed Force Against Terrorism: American Hegemony or Impotence?, 1 CHI. J. INT ' L L. 37, 37-39 (2000) (“Although the international community began a concerted effort to control international terrorism in the late 1920s, it has never been able to agree on a definition of international terro rism.”) (footnote omitted). 18. In Resolution 1390, the Council condemned the Taliban for allowing Afghanistan to be used as a base for te rrorists training and activities, including the export of terrorism by the Al -Qaida network and other terrorist groups as well as for using foreign merc enaries in hostile actions in the territory of Afghanistan . . . . D:\116103060.doc 2002] FAILURE OF THE CHARTER FRAMEWORK Printed On: 2/12/2016 741 But once again, the interesting legal question is: when does state support to terrorists rise to the level of an armed attack under Article 51? Clearly, there are a number of different levels of support that states could be providing to terrorists. At the high end of the spectrum, states could be directing and controlling terrorist groups. In other words, states could essentially be using terrorists as proxies in the international system. This level of state involvement might be termed state sponsored terrorism.19 At a lower level, states could be providing financial and military assistance to terrorists. This level could be termed state supported terrorism. And at yet a lower level, states could be tolerating and otherwise harboring terrorists. This would be a circumstance where “a state does not sponsor or support terrorist groups within its borders, but knows of their existence and fails to suppress them.”20 This level could be termed state tolerated terrorism. At what level would state involvement in terrorism rise to the level of an armed attack? Clearly, different observers could draw the line at different places. B. The Internal Use of Force While rogue states may very well become pariahs because of their actions abroad, such states may also engage in the use of military force against their own citizens. The notorious actions of the Khmer Rouge in Cambodia, the horrors of Rwanda, and the ethnic cleansing of the Serbian regime immediately come to mind. Prior to World War II, international law, did not address the matter of how a government treated its own people. It was not until the abomination of the Holocaust that the international community decided to make human rights norms a major part of international law. In 1945, the drafters of the U.N. Charter proclaimed their determination “to reaffirm faith in fundamental human rights, in the dignity and worth of the human person, in the equal rights of men and women . . . .”21 Following the adoption of the Charter, the United Nations proceeded to adopt a host of instruments dedicated to the establishment of an elaborate regime of international human rights law. These include the Genocide Convention,22 the Covenant on Civil and Political Rights,23 and the Covenant on Economic, U.N. S.C. Res. 1390, U.N. SCOR, 54th Sess., 4452nd mtg., U.N. Doc S/RES/1390 (2002).. 19. This follows the categories suggested in AREND & B ECK, supra note 4,at 142. 20. Id. (footnote omitted). 21. U.N. CHARTER , preamble. 22. Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Cri me of Genocide, Dec. 9, 1948, 78 U.N.T.S. 277 [hereinafter Genocide Convention]. 23. International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, G.A. Res. 2200A, U.N. GAOR, 21st Sess., Supp. No. 16, at 1, U.N. Doc. A/6546 (1966), reprinted in 999 U.N.T.S. 171 [hereinafter Covenant on Civil and Political Rights]. D:\116103060.doc 742 Printed On 2/12/2016: NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 36:4 Social, and Cultural Rights.24 When states violate applicable human rights law , they are clearly breaching their international legal obligations, yet they are not engaging in an armed attack against another member state. If the Security Council determined that such abuse of human rights would constitute a threat to international peace and security, and subsequently, authorized the use of force under Article 42 of the Charter, military action against the state would seem to be lawful. But in the absence of Security Council action, the Charter framework would seem to outlaw forcible action by states against the offending regime, even if the purpose of such force was to prevent massive violations of human rights. C. Weapons of Mass Destruction When the Charter was drafted in the spring of 1945, only a few people were aware of the potential power of the atom. Consequently, the Charter framework was, as one advisor to the United States delegation, John Foster Dulles, would later say, a “pre-atomic” document.25 While chemical and biological weapons were certainly known to the delegates at San Francisco, their use as “weapons of mass destruction” was probably not on the minds of the Charter framers. After all, the use of chemical weapons in the First World War had generally been regarded as a strategic mistake and, indeed, such use had been prohibited by the 1925 Geneva Gas Protocol.26 But in the world after Hiroshima and Nagasaki and with increasing evidence of the production and stockpiling of various chemical and biological agents, the unique threat posed by weapons of mass destruction presents a particularly acute problem in the wake of rogue regimes. At first blush, the problem may seem unremarkable. These weapons, like any others, would be subject to standard laws of armed conflict. Several conventions prohibit the possession and use of chemical and biological weapons, and while the use of nuclear weapons is not clearly prohibited under customary international law,27 the use of such weapons in an indis- 24. International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, adopted Dec. 21, 1966, 993 U.N.T.S. 3 [hereinafter Covenant on Social and Cultural Rights]. 25. See, ANTHONY C LARK AREND , P URSUING A JUST AND D URABLE P EACE: JOHN F OSTER DULLES AND INTERNATIONAL ORGANIZATION 231 (1988). 26. Protocol for Prohibition of the Use in War of Asphyxiating, Poisonous or Other Gases, and of Bacteriological Methods of Warfare, June 17, 1925, 26 U.S.T. 571, 94 L.N.T.S. 65 [hereinafter Geneva Gas Protocol]. 27. The International Court of Justice in its advisory opinion on The Legality of the Threat or Use of Nuclear Weapons declined to rule that the use of nuclear weapons would be unlawful in all circumstances. Legality of the Threat or Use of Nuclear Weapons, 1996 I.C.J. 226 (July 8, 1996). For a discussion of the case, see generally Dale Stephens, Human Rights and Armed Conflict -- The Advisory Opinion of the In- D:\116103060.doc 2002] FAILURE OF THE CHARTER FRAMEWORK Printed On: 2/12/2016 743 criminate way or in a manner that causes unnecessary suffering would be proscribed.28 But the problem with rogue regimes lies at a deeper level. If certain states have a history of violating acceptable norms of international behavior, how should the international community respond to any efforts on the part of these states to develop such weapons of mass destruction? Following the Gulf War, the United Nations Security Council was so troubled by the prospect of Iraq acquiring weapons of mass destruction, that it imposed strict disarmament requirements and ordered Iraq to destroy chemical, biological, and nuclear weapons facilities and submit to an inspection regime.29 Since Iraq was a party to both the Nuclear Non-Proliferation Treaty and the 1972 Biological Weapons Convention,30 it was already prohibited from possessing nuclear and biological weapons. At the time of the Security Council action, however, there was no explicit prohibition on the possession of chemical weapons.31 Iraqi compliance with these requirements has been less than satisfactory and on several occasions, the United States and some of its allies have used force against Iraq to secure compliance with the inspections regime.32 These uses of force raise the question that weapons of mass destruction pose for the Charter framework: Does the mere possession of weapons of mass destruction present such a threat to international peace and security that states can unilaterally intervene to abate this threat? If so, at what point, can states take such action? In 1981, Israel bombed the Osarik Reactor in ternational Court of Justice in the Nuclear Weapons Case, 4 YALE H UM .RTS. & D EV. L.J. 1 (2001). 28. The Hague Convention on the Laws and Customs of War on Land prohibits the use of “arms, projectiles, or material calculated to cause unnecessary suffering.” Convention (no. IV) Respecting the Laws and Customs of War on Land, with Annex of Regulations, Oct. 18, 1907, 36 Stat. 2277, T.S. No. 539, 1 Bevans 631, Annex, art 23, e. 29. See U.N. S.C. Res. 687, U.N. SCOR, 46th Sess., 2983rd mtg., U.N. Doc. S/RES/687 (1991). 30. Convention on the Prohibition of Development, Production, and Stockpiling of Bacteriological (Biological) and Toxin Weapons and on Their Destruction, Apr. 10, 1972, 26 U.S.T. 583, 1015 U.N.T.S. 163. 31. The Chemical Weapons Convention was not signed by the U.S. until 1993 and did not enter into force until April 29, 1997. See Convention on the Prohibition of the Development, Production, Stockpiling and Use of Chemical Weapons and Their Destruction, Jan. 13, 1993, S. TREATY DOC . NO. 21, (1993), 1974 U.N.T.S. 3. 32. The United States used force in 1993 and again in 1998 to secure Iraqi compliance with the weapons inspections regime established by the Security Council under Resolution 687. For a discussion of the lawfulness of these actions, see generally Jules Lobel & Michael Ratner, Bypassing the Security Council: Ambiguous Authorizations to Use Force, Cease-Fires and the Iraqi Inspection Regime, 93 AM . J. INT’ L L. 124 (1999); Nigel D. White & Robert Cryer, Unilateral Enforcement of Resolution 687: A Threat too Far, 29 CAL. W. INT’ L L. J. 243 (1999). D:\116103060.doc 744 Printed On 2/12/2016: NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 36:4 Iraq, claiming that the reactor was to be used to produce weapons-grade material that would produce weapons that would be used to threaten Israel. While the members of the Security Council, including the United States, condemned Israel for its actions, the history of the Iraqi nuclear weapons program and its regular rejection of arms inspectors, raise similar questions today. III. ADDRESSING THE PROBLEMS POSED BY ROGUE STATES In light of these challenges that rogue regimes pose for the United Nations Charter framework, scholars and international actors have attempted to apply the basic Charter principles to these problems not anticipated by the framers of the Charter. Accordingly, a series of arguments have been developed about the questions posed in the section above. A. The Armed Attack Threshold 1. Covert Action and the Support of Rebels In the scholarly literature, there seems to be general agreement that both covert actions and support of rebels can rise to the level of an armed attack, thus engendering the right of self-defense. The difficulty is determining precisely at what point the armed attack threshold is reached. The most instructive case on this matter is the Nicaragua case. As noted earlier, in that case, the United States alleged that Nicaragua was providing various forms of support to the FMLN, a rebel group in El Salvador. While the International Court of Justice did not find any evidence of assistance from the Government of Nicaragua to the FMLN, the court did comment on the circumstances under which assistance to rebels would rise to the level of an armed attack. It explained that: [I]t may be considered to be agreed that an armed attack must be understood as including not merely action by regular armed forces across an international border, but also “the sending by or on behalf of a State of armed bands, groups, irregulars or mercenaries, which carry out acts of armed force against another State of such gravity as to amount to” (inter alia) an actual armed attack conducted by regular forces, “or its substantial involvement therein.”33 This was a crucial statement by the court for two reasons. First, it was the first judicial acknowledgment that “indirect aggression” could rise to the 33. Military and Paramilitary Activities (Nicar. v. U.S.), 1986 I.C.J. 14 (June 27) para. 195 [hereinafter Nicaragua Case]. D:\116103060.doc 2002] FAILURE OF THE CHARTER FRAMEWORK Printed On: 2/12/2016 745 level of an armed attack. At some point, the support for rebels could be so great that it would justify a forcible response in self-defense against the intervening state. Second, the court’s decision was also a comment on the point at which support would be tantamount to an armed attack. For the court, this occurred only in sending in “armed bands, groups, irregulars or mercenaries” that use force at a level equivalent to an armed attack by regular military forces. Despite American arguments to the contrary, the court explicitly rejected the notion that anything short of sending in such armed bands would ever rise to the level of an armed attack. The court noted that while providing arms and other assistance to rebel groups may indeed violate Article 2(4),34 the court did “not believe that the concept of ‘armed attack’ includes not only acts by armed bands where such acts occur on a significant scale but also assistance to rebels in the form of the provision of weapons or logistical or other support.”35 This second conclusion by the court has raised a great deal of scholarly concern.36 The court seems to suggest that a state could be in a most untenable position. An outside state could be providing significant military, logistical, financial, and other assistance to rebels within the territory of a state. While such assistance might violate the Charter provisions on the use of force, as long as assistance did not actually involve the sending in of armed bands, the victim state would be unable to respond in self-defense. In essence, an outside state could do as much damage by providing weapons and money to rebels as it would if it had launched an outright attack, and yet Article 51 would not be triggered. Such a position– especially in light of the potential threat from rogue regimes– seems to contradict the very essence of a right of effective self-defense established in the Charter. Indeed, as will be noted below, subsequent decisions by the Security Council on terrorism would seem to reject such a restrictive interpretation of armed attack. 34. See id. The court noted that: “such assistance may be regarded as a threat or use of force, or amount to intervention in the internal or external affairs of other States.” Id. 35. Id. 36. Professor John Norton Moore, for example, has strongly argued against this “high threshold” approach to armed attack. Following the decision of the court , he concluded that the court had “announced, contrary to the Charter, a restrictive inte rpretation of the right of defense that could deny individual or collective defense against secret warfare, the most serious contemporary threat to world order.” Joh n Norton Moore, The Nicaragua Case and the Deterioration of World Order, 81 AM . J. INT’ L L. 151, 152 (1987). D:\116103060.doc 746 Printed On 2/12/2016: NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 36:4 2. Support for Terrorism Until the events of September 11th, most of the discussion about how assistance to terrorist groups related to the armed attack threshold came in a variety of scholarly debates. Not surprisingly, scholarly opinion was all over the map. Some scholars supported a “high threshold” approach, arguing that a terrorist attack should only be considered to be tantamount to an armed attack if such attack occurs within the territory of the aggrieved states. Presumably, these scholars would want the victim states to prove direct state sponsorship of the terrorist group. At the other extreme, other scholars argued for a “low threshold.” Under such a conception, terrorist actions could rise to the level of an armed attack even if they did not occur within the territory of the victim states. It would also make sense that low threshold supporters would also require less than full sponsorship from a state aiding terrorism to be held responsible for an armed attack. Somewhere in between these two would be a “moderate level” threshold. Using the logic of the Nicaragua case, it would seem that the International Court of Justice was in the high threshold camp. Indeed, this was the conclusion reached by Michael Glennon in his recent analysis of the American response to the September 11thactions.37 The act in question would need to occur in the territory of the state and the state aiding the terrorist would have to have be engaging in state-sponsored terrorism. As Glennon notes, quoting from the Nicaragua case, “[a]ctive, not passive, support– an actual ‘sending’ of ‘armed bands, groups, irregulars or mercenaries’ or ‘substantial involvement therein’ -- is necessary to meet the armed attack requirement.”38 “Indeed,” as Glennon continues, “the entire approach of the United States in fighting terrorism -- refusing to distinguish between terrorists and those who harbor them, which has come to be called the ‘Bush Doctrine’ -is outlawed by this precept to the extend that it precludes any use of force against states that only passively provide a safe harbor for terrorists and avoid substantial involvement in terrorists’ activities.”39 Yet, despite this approach by the International Court of Justice, in recent months it appears that the Security Council articulated a bit lower threshold. In Resolution 1373, the Council was very strong in its condemnation of providing any kind of assistance to terrorist groups.40 The Council also reaf- 37. See generally Michael J. Glennon, The Fog of Law: Self-Defense, Inherence and Incoherence in Article 51 of the United Nations Charter, 25 HARV. J.L. & P UB. P OL’ Y 539 (2002). 38. Id. at 542 (citation omitted). 39. Id. at 543-44. 40. See U.N. S.C. Res. 1373, U.N. SCOR, 56th Sess., 1385th mtg., U.N. Doc. S/RES/1373 (2001). In this Resolution, the Council: D:\116103060.doc 2002] Printed On: 2/12/2016 FAILURE OF THE CHARTER FRAMEWORK 747 firmed the “inherent right of individual or collective self-defence as recognized by the Charter of the United Nations as reiterated in resolution 1368 . . . .”41 As noted earlier, in Resolution 1390, the Council went on to condemn the Taliban regime for its support for Al Qaeda. In light of these actions by the Council, and in the wake of American actions against the harboring of terrorists, its seems that the Council has been willing to go further than the International Court of Justice in expanding the definition of an armed attack. But neither the Security Council nor any other authoritative decisionmaker has articulated a clear definition of the armed attack threshold. Decide[d] also that all States shall: (a) Refrain from providing any form of support, active or passive, to e ntities or persons involved in terrorist acts, including by suppressing recrui tment of members of terrorist groups and eliminating the supply of weapons to terrorists; (b) Take the necessary steps to prevent the commission of terrorist acts, including by provision of early warning to other States by exchange of information; (c) Deny safe haven to those who finance, plan, support, or commit te rrorist acts, or provide safe havens; (d) Prevent those who finance, plan, facilitate or commit terrorist acts from using their respective territories for those purposes against other States or their citizens; (e) Ensure that any person who participates in the financing, planning, preparation or perpetration of terrorist acts or in supporting terrorist acts is brought to justice and ensure that, in addition to any other measures against them, such terrorist acts are established as serious criminal offences in domestic laws and regulations and that the punishment duly reflects the seriousness of such terrorist acts; (f) Afford one another the greatest measure of assistance in connection with criminal investigations or criminal proceedings relating to the financing or support of terrorist acts, including assistance in obtaining evidence in their po ssession necessary for the proceedings; (g) Prevent the movement of terrorists or terrorist groups by effective border controls and controls on issuance of identity papers and travel doc uments, and through measures for preventing counterfeiting, forgery or fraudulent use of identity papers and travel documents. Id. 41. Id. Resolution 1368 was the first that condemned the September 11th attacks. See U.N.S.C. Res. 1368, U.N. SCOR 56th Sess., 4370th mtg., U.N. Doc. S/RES/1368 (2001). D:\116103060.doc 748 Printed On 2/12/2016: NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 36:4 B. The Internal Use of Force For many years, there have been extensive debates about the lawfulness of the use of force to prevent a state from committing genocide or other massive human rights violations. Using the rubric of “humanitarian intervention” scholars and public officials alike have deliberated upon the possible legal justification for such actions. Most commentators can be understood as falling into one of two categories -- restrictionists and counterrestrictionists.42 The restrictionists argue that the language of the Charter is clear on this point. Unless the Security Council authorizes the use of force, states cannot intervene in another state to stop a government from engaging in human rights violations. Counter-restrictionists, however, present three primary arguments, or variants thereof, to claim that in cases where a state engages in genocide or other violations of fundamental human rights, intervention should be lawful -- even in the absence of an explicit Security Council authorization. The first of these arguments relates to the protection of human rights. While it is true that the Charter sought to establish a restrictive regime relating to the recourse to force, it also endeavored to create a legal regime to protect human rights. As Professor Fernando Tesón has noted, “the promotion of human rights is as important a purpose in the Charter as is the control of international conflict.”43 As a consequence, it could be argued that in certain extreme cases, the protection of human rights should trump the Charter’s prohibition on the use of force. Professors Reisman and McDougal explain that the Charter’s “repeated emphasis upon the common interest in human rights indicates that the use of force for the urgent protection of such rights is no less authorized than other forms of self-help.”44 A second argument presented by some counter-restrictionists contends that there has been a revival of a customary right of humanitarian intervention. Here, counter-restrictionists argue that because the United Nations Security Council has been, for the most part, unable to act effectively to prevent human rights abuses, a pre-existing right of self-help has been revived. A final argument in support of the lawfulness of humanitarian interven- 42. We have used these categories previously. See AREND & B ECK, supra note 4, at 131-36. The discussion of humanitarian intervention here draws upon our prev ious discussion. 43. F ERNANDO TESÓN , HUMANITARIAN INTERVENTION : AN INQUIRY INTO LAW & M ORALITY 131 (1988). 44. Michael Reisman & Myres S. McDougal, Humanitarian Intervention to Protect the Ibos, in HUMANITARIAN I NTERVENTION AND THE UNITED N ATIONS 172 (Richard B. Lillich, ed. 1973). D:\116103060.doc 2002] FAILURE OF THE CHARTER FRAMEWORK Printed On: 2/12/2016 749 tion claims that using force solely for humanitarian purposes falls below the “Article 2(4) threshold.” This argument is based on a close reading of the language of Article 2(4). The text of that provision does not literally prohibit all threats or uses of force, but only those directed against the “territorial or political independence” of states or which in some other way transgresses the “Purposes of the United Nations.” Hence, it is contended, a use of force to protect human rights is lawful, since “[a] genuine humanitarian intervention does not result in territorial conquest or political subjugation.”45 Indeed, it could be argued that the true political independence of a state lies in the people of the state, not in the ruling elite. Using force to protect these suffering people, thus, would actually be affirming the political independence of the state. Despite these scholarly arguments, one of the real problems with the concept of humanitarian intervention has been the difficulty finding examples where states made unambiguous claims of engaging in humanitarian intervention, and the international community responded to those claims. Only with the NATO action in the Kosovo crisis has there been a relatively clear case of humanitarian intervention. Even in that case, the United States did not explicitly justify its actions based on that doctrine.46 Nonetheless, Kosovo may be a turning point. Given the many positive reactions to NATO’s actions, seeming support from the Secretary-General, and muted criticism from the rest of the world, Kosovo may be the crucial stage in the emergence of a clear doctrine of humanitarian intervention. In a sense, it may still be too soon to tell, but the reaction of the international community to a subsequent use of force to promote human rights may well indicate that states are now prepared to accept humanitarian intervention.47 The law, however, remains unclear at present. 45. TESÓN , supra note 42, at 131. 46. The United States was rather inconsistent in the justifications it gave for the NATO action. See Contemporary Practice of the United States Relating to Intern ational Law, 93 AM . J. INT’ L L. 628, 631 (Sean D. Murphy, ed. 1999) “The U.S. Government based its position on the lawfulness of the air strikes under international law on various factors, which changed in emphasis over time.” Id. While the United States did, at times, make reference to humanitarian reasons, it also noted other vio lations of international law by Yugoslavia and previous Security Council resolutions. See id. 47. For a lengthier exposition of the current state and possible future of h umanitarian intervention, see Christopher C. Joyner & Anthony Clark Arend, Anticipatory Humanitarian Intervention: An Emerging Legal Norm?, 10 U.S. A.F. ACAD . J. L. S TUD. 27 (1999/2000). D:\116103060.doc 750 Printed On 2/12/2016: NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 36:4 C. Weapons of Mass Destruction As noted above, weapons of mass destruction in the hands of a rogue state pose a unique threat to the international system. But would such possession or efforts to gain possession of such weapons give rise to a right of forcible self-help on the part of an outside state? Under customary international law that pre-dated the Charter, many scholars would argue48 there was a right of anticipatory self-defense. Based on the famous Caroline test of 1837, a state could use force in self-defense prior to an actual armed attack if two criteria were met: necessity and proportionality. First, the state seeking to use force would need to demonstrate that some attack was imminent. Second, the response by the soon-to-be victim state would have to be proportionate to the threat. Such guidelines are fine when applied to conventional warfare in the 1800’s. They become more problematic when applied to modern warfare -- in particular, in the face of the threat of weapons of mass destruction. The necessity prong is particularly troublesome. In the original formulation given by the American Secretary of State in the Caroline case, a state using force in anticipatory self-defense would have to demonstrate that “the necessity of that self-defense is instant, overwhelming, and leaving no choice of means, and no moment of deliberation.”49 Yet with nuclear weapons or other weapons of mass destruction, by the time this test is met, it is probably too late. As noted earlier, the Security Council criticized Israel following the bombing of the Iraqi reactor for failure to meet the test of necessity. The reactor was not yet on-line, it was unclear that when it did come on-line that it would produce nuclear weapons -since Iraq was a party to the Nuclear Non-Proliferation Treaty -- and the mere possession of weapons would not constitute an imminent threat of their use. While hindsight may judge Israel’s action differently, the legal questions posed at the time remain the same today. Certainly, the strict test of necessity that Daniel Webster described does not make a great deal of sense in the age of weapons of mass destruction. But what is the appropriate test? The international community does not seem to have developed a clear alternative. 48. For an examination of the scholarly debate on anticipatory self-defense, see AREND & BECK, supra note 4, at 71-79. Scholars supporting the existence of such right include William V. O’Brien, Derek W. Bowett, Myres S. McDougal, and Julius Stone. 49. J.B. Moore, Destruction of theCaroline, in 2 DIGEST OF INTERNATIONAL LAW 412 (1906) (quoting M. Webster, Sec. of State, to Lord Ashburton, British plen., Aug. 6, 1842). D:\116103060.doc 2002] FAILURE OF THE CHARTER FRAMEWORK IV. Printed On: 2/12/2016 751 CONCLUSIONS AND RECOMMENDATIONS In light of the preceding discussion of the challenges posed by rogue states, several conclusions become clear. First, the United Nations Charter framework for the use of force did not anticipate the ways in which rogue states would use force. As a consequence, it is unclear how the literal language of the Charter can be applied to various actions of rogue states. Second, while the international community has attempted to respond to some of these challenges through international organs– such as the International Court of Justice and the Security Council -- and the efforts of international legal scholars, international law is still very much in dispute. When does a covert action or efforts to support rebels rise to the level of an armed attack? What level of involvement with terrorist groups is necessary for a rogue state to have itself committed an armed attack? Can force ever be used to prevent a rogue state from engaging in genocide or other human rights violations? Can weapons of mass destruction in the hands of a rogue state give others the right to preemptively use force? The answers to all of these questions are by no means clear. So what does this mean for the Charter framework? Most scholars have sought to salvage the United Nations Charter framework in the wake of these and other challenges. They have attempted to preserve the core of the Charter provisions on the use of force, modifying them based on their understanding of customary international law.50 Such approach, however, seems to miss the fundamental point. While it is indeed true that the actions posed by rogue states challenge the efficacy of the Charter regime, so too do the actions of non-rogue states. The true test of whether a putative rule of international law is actually law is whether that rule has both authority and control.51 First, is the rule authoritative? Is it perceived by the decision-making elites in states to be the law -- does it have opinio juris? Second, is the rule controlling of the behavior of international actors? Is it reflected in the practice of states?52 If the rule in question is the Charter framework for the use of force -- no threat or use of force unless undertaken in self-defense following an armed attack or as authorized by the Security Council -- my conclusion is that it fails the test. 50. Elsewhere, we have called these individuals “core-interpretists.” They argue that the “core” of Article 2(4) is still good law, but contend that a reading of 2(4) as prohibiting all threats or uses of force is not an accurate understanding of that provision. See AREND & BECK supra note 4, at 182-84. 51. For a more elaborate examination of the “authority-control” test, see ANTHONY C LARK AREND , LEGAL R ULES AND INTERNATIONAL S OCIETY (1999). 52. As Professor Mark Weisburd has noted: “A putative rule cannot survive contrary practice no matter how that practice is characterized.” A. Mark Weisburd, USE OF F ORCE: THE P RACTICE OF S TATES S INCE W ORLD WAR II 24 (1997). D:\116103060.doc 752 Printed On 2/12/2016: NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 36:4 First, the rule of the Charter is not authoritative. While states may give lip service to the Charter framework, since 1945 states from all quarters of the international system have consistently claimed the right to use force in circumstances that fall outside of any reasonable interpretation of the Charter.53 Second, the rule is not controlling of state behavior. Despite protests to the contrary, states have actually used force hundreds of times in ways that are inconsistent with the Charter rules.54 As Professor Glennon aptly concludes, “[s]o many states have used force with such regularity in so wide a variety of situations that it can no longer be said that any customary norm of state practice constrains the use of force.”55 If this is indeed the case, if the Charter framework for the use of force does not reflect existing international law, then what does this mean for rogue states? Does it mean that there is nothing that can be said about the lawfulness of their actions? To me, it says that now is the time to begin creating new rules about the behavior of rogue states. Democratic states must unite to develop a set of rules relating to the use of force that will truly criminalize the behavior of rogue regimes. But in doing so, those states must understand that a rule-based regime must apply to them as well. As Glennon notes, “[n]o rules will work that do not reflect underlying geopolitical realities.”56 “The use-of-force regime set out in the U.N. Charter failed,” he explains, “ because the Charter sought to impose rules that are 53. See AREND & B ECK, supra note 4, at 181. (“ For obvious political reasons, states have not overtly argued that the Charter norms are invalid. But as noted earlier, states have on numerous occasions claimed the right to use force in circumstances that are, nevertheless, clearly antithetical to the principle enshrined in Article 2(4). Given these claims, it seems incorrect to contend that states still hold 2(4) in very high e steem. Admittedly, the provision may command some perceptions of legitimacy, but they seem to be far below those required for a healthy rule of law.”) (footnotes omitted). 54. In his brilliant work, Limits of Law, Prerogatives of Power, Michael Glennon provides the most recently exploration with respect to state practice. He examines numerous uses of force since the Charter was adopted and then asks this question -“What lesson is to be drawn from this sorry record?” M ICHAEL J. GLENNON , LIMITS OF LAW, P REROGATIVES OF P OWER : INTERVENTIONISM AFTER KOSOVO 84 (2001). He answers the question by concluding: It is impossible to avoid the conclusion that use of force among states simply is no longer subject – if it ever was subject – to the rule of law. The rules of the Charter do not today constitute binding restraints on i ntervention by states. Their words cannot realistically be given effec t in the face of widespread and numerous contrary deeds. Id. 55. Glennon, supra note 38, at 554. This is consistent with the conclusion that Professor Beck and I reached in 1993. Although at the time, we argued that there did still seem to be an authoritative and controlling prohibition on the use of force for pure territorial aggrandizement. AREND & BECK, supra note 4, at 187-88. 56. Glennon, supra note 38, at 557. D:\116103060.doc 2002] FAILURE OF THE CHARTER FRAMEWORK Printed On: 2/12/2016 753 out-of-sync with the way states actually behave.”57 Consequently, “[a] new use-of-force regime that does work will have to rest far more firmly upon actual patterns of practice that reveal, with solid empirical evidence, what regulation of force is possible and what is not.”58 The starting point for this new regime, its “core,” could be “rogue behavior.” Rather than attempting to create a full-blown legal system to restrict the use of force, if the United States and its allies that seek to establish a rule-based regime would begin by prohibiting “rogue” actions, they may be able to develop rules that would truly be authoritative and controlling. What would such a regime look like? That remains to be seen. But whatever regime the United States and other democratic states seek, it must be a regime that they are willing to follow. Otherwise, such putative legal regime will be just as illusory as the Charter regime has become.59 57. Id. 58. Id. 59. Commenting as early as 1970, Professor Thomas M. Franck observed that “[t]he practice of these states has so severely shattered the mutual confidence which would have been the sine qua non of an operative rule of law embodying the precepts of Article 2(4) that, as with Ozymandias, only the words remain.” Tho mas M. Franck, Who Killed Article 2(4)? Or: Changing Norms Governing the Use of Force by States, 64 AM . J. INT’ L L. 809, 809 (1970).