David Lewis, "Truth in Fiction" Notes M. Davidson, CSUSB Phil 387 Suppose you don't want to say there is a nonexistent object, Sherlock Holmes, that is the referent of "Sherlock Holmes." (This would be Meinong's view.) How can sentences like "Sherlock Holmes lives at Baker Street" come out true if "Sherlock Holmes" has no referent? (Note that Lewis doesn't consider the option that Sherlock Holmes is an abstract object. We will consider this option next.) Lewis: Why not use a truth-in-fiction operator? When are we to take fictional sentences to involve a hidden truth-in-fiction operator? Context will tell us. Consider (1) Holmes lived at Baker Street. and (2) Holmes really existed. The first sentence seems to be equivalent to (1') In the Sherlock Holmes stories, Holmes lived at Baker Street. The second doesn't seem to involve a truth-in-fiction operator; it purports to be about the way things really are as opposed to the way things are in the stories. The same goes with (3) Holmes is a fictional character. Lewis says this is false, again, because "Holmes" doesn't refer. Truth in fiction is closed under implication. Let "TF" stand for a truth-in-fiction operator, then, If TFp and p->q, then TFq. Lewis: TFp is true iff p is true at a certain set of possible worlds specified by the fictional stories in question. So which worlds? Attempt 1: Those worlds in which characters perform those actions and stand in relations that Holmes, Watson, etc. do. R: There may be a circularity here. It may be that figuring out what occurs in a story requires understanding the truth-in-fiction operator. 1 R: Suppose that there actually were a person named "Sherlock Holmes" who had the same properties and stood in the same relations as Holmes does in the stories. AC Doyle has no idea of the existence of such a person. Would our world then make true various claims about what is true in the Holmes fiction? No, Lewis (and Kripke) say. The Holmes stories aren't about this person AC Doyle did not know about. Attempt 2: Think of stories as concrete things that occur at a particular time, as opposed to abstract sets of sentences or propositions or the like. The relevant worlds are those where an individual tells the same story here (a token of the same story type) as fact. When a story is told fictionally, the sense of a name in the fiction assigns it no reference. So then, Analysis 0: A sentence of the form "in the fiction f, p" is true iff p is true at every world where f is told as known fact rather than fiction. Problem: Aren't there truths in a fiction that aren't explicitly mentioned (background facts)? (E.g. it's true that Holmes wasn't a flamenco dancer, even though this is never mentioned in the stories.) Then Analysis 1: A sentence of the form "In the fiction f, p" is non-vacuously true iff some world where f is told as known fact and p is true differs less from our actual world than any world in which f is told and p is not true. There may be claims (e.g. "Holmes has an even number of hairs on his head") that are neither true nor false in a fiction, and this is because there are ties between various worlds in which f is told as to whether this claim is true or not. Analysis 1 analyzes truth-in-fiction counterfactually. What is true in a fictional story depends crucially on what our world is like. What if the author is unaware of some facts about the world, and this winds up changing the stories (e.g. the facts about the speckled band Lewis mentions, that in the actual world such a snake can't climb ropes)? Consider two sets of worlds: Those where the collective background beliefs of the community of the storyteller are true, and those in which the fiction is told as fact. The former gives the content of the background beliefs, the latter the content of the story. We don't want to take those worlds that are parts of each set. There may be none, as fiction contains claims that aren't believed to be true by the relevant community. So then, 2 Analysis 2: "In the fiction f, p" is non-vacuously true iff, whenever w is one of the collective belief worlds of the community of origin of f, then some world where f is told as known fact and p is true differs less from the world w, on balance, than does any world where f is told as known fact and p is not true. It is vacuously true iff there are no possible worlds where f is told as known fact. Can't other sentences true in fiction affect what is true in a fiction f, either from other fictions (see other stories based on the Holmes stories) or from the same fiction? What about fictions that aren't possibly told as fact? This may be true because the fiction is impossible, or it's not possibly told. Then any proposition is vacuously true in such a story. This may be fine (Lewis thinks) if the fiction is impossible (a guy who befriends a married bachelor, e.g.). But is this true? Is it also then thereby true that in such a world there is a dragon? Or, what if the author contradicts himself or herself? Two options Lewis suggests: Go with revised stories that don't contain contradiction that otherwise are as close as possible to the original. What is true in the story is what is true in all of these worlds. And in some of them (if we're concerned with the location of Watson's war wound, as Lewis discusses) will have Watson getting war-wounded in one place, and some of them another place. So there will be nothing definitely true about the location of his war-wound. Second option: Suppose the closest world in which a story is told as known fact contain truths that clearly aren't in the original story (e.g. the case of an author claiming carelessly that a person is in one place one minute and thousands of miles away in another--the closest worlds to the actual world in which this story is told as a truth might be ones with teleportation, which might be odd to add to a story). In these cases, we might want to take one of the slightly revised stories as the actual story. 3