The Fall of Icarus and Kepler’s Camera Obscura: The Theme of Forbidden Knowledge in the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries Revisited. Raz Chen-Morris Bar-Ilan University and The University of Sydney chenraz@mail.biu.ac.il 2 The Fall of Icarus and Kepler’s Camera Obscura: The Theme of Forbidden Knowledge in the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries Revisited.1 Thirty years ago the distinguished historian Carlo Ginzburg published an essay entitled “High and Low: The Theme of Forbidden Knowledge in the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries.”2 In this provocative essay Ginzburg traced the formation, persistence and change of certain cultural prohibitions on the investigation of the heavens throughout the Middle-Ages to Early Modern Europe. Ginzburg’s point of departure was the Vulgate mistranslation: Noli altum sapere, sed time, of St. Paul’s admonition against human pride .3 The erroneous translation, according to Ginzburg, turned the moral condemnation of pride into an epistemological prohibition on the inquiry of higher things. In many cases, this was taken literally as indignation of studying the heavens. Ginzburg traces the prevalence of these sentiments into the sixteenth century. Thence, with the advent of the printing press the ancient apprehension of astronomical inquiries adopted a new popular display. In the literature of emblems from the 1530’s onwards the figure of the falling Icarus 1 This paper is part of an ARC supported project, The Imperfection of the Universe (DP0664046). 2 Originally appeared in Past and Present, 73 (1976): 28-42, rep. in Carlo Ginzburg, Clues, Myths, and the Historical Method, trans. John and Anne Tedeschi, Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1989: 60-76. 3 Epistle to the Romans, 11:20. 3 came to represent the danger and folly of astronomical inquiries.4 The new science of the second half of the sixteenth century, however, reshaped these sentiments and anxieties. Ginzburg points to a radical change in the values associated in the emblems’ literature with the figure of Icarus. In the seventeenth century Icarus’ curiosity was vindicated and embraced as a positive value. The medieval religious prohibitions were transgressed, and instead of the warnings of human curiosity, a new slogan “dare to know” was celebrated. This paper concentrates on filling two gaps in Ginzburg's captivating account. These two gaps appear in two crucial points in Ginzburg’s longe durée history of curiosity: The one is concerned with the emergence of the epistemological twist to the moral admonition against pride in patristic literature, and the other appears at its decline, with the emergence of a new mentalité of scientific curiosity: how can a mistranslation have such lasting cultural and intellectual effect? What was there in the culture of late antiquity 4 The denouncement of curiosity is usually associated with a moral prohibition and religious fear: cf. William Eamon, Science and the Secrets of Nature: Books of Secrets in Medieval and Early Modern Culture, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994, pp. 59-65; Peter Harrison, "Curiosity, Forbidden Knowledge, and the Reformation of Natural Philosophy in Early Modern England," Isis, 92 (2001) 265-290; Lorraine Daston, "Curiosity in Early Modern Science," Word and Image, 1995, 11: 391-404; Roger Shattuck, Forbidden Knowledge: From Prometheus to Pornography, New York: St. Martin Press, 1996; Neil Kenny, The Uses of Curiosity in Early Modern France and Germany, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004. 4 that gave such resonance to St. Jerome’s interpretation of St. Paul’s dictum? On the other end of Ginzburg’s narrative: What brought the change about in the 16th century? What enabled astronomers, such as Copernicus, Tycho Brahe, Kepler and Galileo, to transgress these prohibitions and to suggest new celestial knowledge? *** In order to answer these queries it is useful to begin with a renowned sixteenth century image of Icarus. It is Peter Bruegel’s painting in the Musée Royale des Beaux Arts in Brussels of a “Landscape with a Falling Icarus” of 1567(?). The painting depicts a magnificent landscape - in the background, a bay with galleys at twilight; while in the foreground, a peasant is ploughing his field, a shepherd with his flock and dog is watching the cloudless sky, and a fisherman is busy with his nets. To the right, there is a barely perceivable element that constitutes the painting's main subject: It is neither the peasant and his plough nor the old man's corpse on the left-hand side, but rather the two legs of Icarus falling into the sea. The immediate source for deciphering this enigmatic painting is Ovid’s description of the fall of Icarus in Metamorphoses Bk. VIII 5 “And someone while trying to catch a fish with a trembling rod, or a shepherd leaning on his staff, or a ploughman on his shaft saw them and was dumbfounded … he flailed with bare arms, [and] vanished into the dark blue sea, the Icarian Sea, called after him.”5 In Bruegel’s paintings all the protagonists are in place: the fisherman, the shepherd and the ploughman are situated above the bay while Icarus sinks into the deep. Yet there are a few discrepancies, the most conspicuous being that the varied figures are either indifferent to the mythical event or fail to appear amazed and bewildered. It is clear that Bruegel meant his painting to comment on the Ovidian myth, but what exactly is the content of this comment? 6 Art historians searched for textual clues for deciphering the iconography of the painting in several verses from the New Testament concerning the ploughman as a 5 Ovid, Metamorphoses v-viii, ed. And trans. D. E. Hill, Warminster: Aris and Philips Publishers, 1992, Bk. VIII:217-223, p 113. 6 P. Roberts-Jones, Bruegel. La Chute d’Icare (Friburg, 1974); Robert J. Clements, “Brueghel’s Fall of Icarus: Eighteen Modern Literary Readings.” Studies in Iconography 7-8 (1981-2), 25367; Christopher Braider, Refiguring the Real: Picture and Modernity in Word and Image, 14001700 (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993), esp. pp. 71-99; also Ethan Matt Kavaler, Peter Bruegel: Parables of Order and Enterprise, (Cambridge, Cambridge U.P., 1999), pp. 5777; Robert Baldwin, "Peasant Imagery and Bruegel's “Fall of Icarus”, Konsthistorisk Tidskrift, LV, 3, 1986, 101-114. 6 symbol of honest labor towards salvation. As a key to Bruegel's intentions they emphasized especially the following verses from Luke 9:62, “Jesus said to him: No man putting his hand to the plough, and looking back, is fit for the kingdom of God” or St. Paul’s assertion in I Cor. 9-10: “he that ploweth should plow with hope”. Others have turned to a German proverb declaring that: “No plow stops for the sake of a dying man”. Others still turned to the skeleton hidden behind the bushes in front of the plough as a signifier for the admonition of vanity, such as the anamorphic skull in Holbeins’ Ambassadors. While all these are obvious markers for the interpretation of Bruegel's painting, still Icarus, as the main character in Ovid’s version, is excluded from these readings, and is turned into a subsidiary figure. In order to capture Bruegel’s intention there is a need to examine one further discrepancy between Ovid’s version of the myth of Icarus and Bruegel visual depiction of it. In Ovid it is midday and the sun is in zenith. In Bruegel the sun is setting, and in another version of this same painting the sun is rising. These different positions of the sun turn the viewer's attention to the opening verses of Ecclesiastes: “The sun also ariseth, and the sun goeth down, and hasteth to his place where he arose.” Reading further makes it clear that Bruegel could have these verses in mind as a condemnation of Icarus’ curiosity and search for fame and novelty. Against the pagan celebration of the human tragic quest after immortal fame inscribed in the names of geographical places, Ecclesiastes declaims: 7 “The eye is not satisfied with seeing, nor the ear filled with hearing... there is no new thing under the sun… there is no remembrance of former things…" [Ecclesiastes 1:5,8,11] These pronouncements can be directed also against the figure of Icarus as the embodiment of vain curiosity. The author of Ecclesiastes stresses throughout that: “Better [is] the sight of the eyes than the going of the soul." [Ecclesiastes 6:9] The meaning of Icarus’ curiosity becomes his attempt to follow the wanderings of his desire after knowledge of things that are beyond the power of human sight.7 The biblical author denies the human soul's desires for what is not directly given. In such a manner, the moral dimension, aiming at quieting desires and passions, has immediate epistemological implications. One should embrace appearances that are immediately present before one's eyes and not inquire and speculate about hidden meanings and causes. The association of pride and intellectual curiosity and search after vain knowledge is already emphasized in Psalms: “Lord, my heart is not haughty, nor my eyes lofty: neither do I exercise my self in great matters, or in things too high for me.” [Psalms 131:1] Later generations emphasized this epistemological warning against human desire for knowledge and vain curiosity. In the Apocryphal treatise The Book of Sirach, one is warned: 7 In Ovid's words "desertuitque ducem, caelique cupidine tractus altius egit iter" [emphasis added] in Ovid, ibid. lines 224-25. 8 “Seek not (to understand) what is too wonderful for thee, And search not out that which is hid from thee. Meditate upon that, which thou must grasp, And not occupied with that which is hid. Have naught to do with that which is beyond thee, For many are the conceits of the sons of men, And evil imaginations lead astray."8 The sense of Icarus’ curiosity that Bruegel, following Ecclesiastes, denounces is not, therefore, related to the investigation of the heavens specifically but with human dissatisfaction with the immediately given. Icarus’ vanity was in his attempt, guided by his imaginations and desires, to pry into things that are beyond the horizon of one’s visual field. The threshold, however, is not necessarily between high and low, but between what can be perceived directly and what is beyond human sensory grasp. This emphasis on the epistemological barrier that divides what is immediately given and can be fully known and what is distant and beyond human perception is succinctly formulated in Aristotle's De partibus animalium. Aristotle sets the power of human vision as the limit of human knowledge. Certain things, one is told, are too distant and alien for humans to know. 8 The Book of Sirach, 3, 21-25 , The Apocrypha and Pseudepigrapha of the Old Testament, ed. R. H. Charles (Oxford), I, 324. 9 “Of things constituted by nature some are ungenerated, imperishable, and eternal, while others are subject to generation and decay. The former are excellent beyond compare and divine, but less accessible to knowledge. The evidence that might throw light on them, and on the problems which we long to solve respecting them, is furnished but scantily by sensation.” These super-sensual and perfect objects stand in contrast to animal and plants, "living as we do in their midst,” about which ample data is available. An example for such distant and eternal entities is celestial bodies. Of these, although they give so much pleasure in their excellence, one has only “scanty conceptions.” And still humans are excited and curious of them “just as half glimpse of persons that we love is more delightful than a leisurely view of other things, whatever their number and dimensions.” Terrestrial things, because of their affinity and nearness, are known with certitude “in their completeness.” Human knowledge of celestial things is lofty, they are beyond one’s grasp, and are known only as far as “our conjectures could reach.” 9 This epistemological dimension of Icarus' air travel is explicated in the satires of Lucian of Samosata in the second century A.D. His critical attitude is not 9 Aristotle, De partibus animalium, (On the Parts of Animals), Bk. I: Ch. 5, 645a21-645b6 in The Complete Works of Aristotle, ed. Jonathan Barnes, 2 vols, Bollingen Series LXXI.2, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984, pp 1003-1004 (One can compare Aristotle's dichotomy with the above Ecclesiastes' differentiation between "sight of the eyes" and the "going (conjectures) of the soul"). 10 limited to Icarus’ attempt to reach higher things. Lucian embraces Aristotle's epistemological distinction between human knowledge of things close by and their inadequate perception of distant heavenly phenomena. And in the vein of Ecclesiastes and Jewish Hellenistic literature, he denounces the astronomers’ attempt to reach beyond the limits of their senses. "Indeed, my friend, it will make you laugh to hear about the way they bragged and worked wonders in their talk! Why, in the first place, they stood on the ground and were not a bit better than the rest of us who walk the earth; in fact, they were not even sharper sighted than their neighbours, but some of them were actually purblind through age or idleness. In spite of that, however, they claimed to discern the boundaries of Heaven, they measured the sun, they visited the spheres beyond the moon, and you would have thought they had fallen from the stars from the way they told about their magnitudes and presumed to say just how many cubits it is in distance from the sun to the moon, often, perhaps, without even knowing how many furlongs it is from Megara to Athens. And not only did they measure the height of the air and the depth of the sea and the circumference of the earth, but by the description of circles and the construction of triangles on squares and of multiple spheres they actually measured out the cubic content of the Heavens. Moreover, was it not silly and completely absurd that when they were talking about things so uncertain they did not make a single assertion hypothetically but were 11 vehement in their insistence and gave the rest no chance to outdo them in exaggeration? "10 Lucian’s problem is not so much with the height of the heaven or with its symbolic relationship with the divine Godhead, or with social hierarchy, but with the simple epistemological assumption that certainty of knowledge stands in inverse relation to distance: the nearer an object is, the better one can come to know it. One should be satisfied with the here and now not only morally but also epistemologically. What ever is beyond immediate human grasp is senseless. In his descent to the underworld in search of the supreme philosophical truth about the good life, Lucian’s cynic protagonist receives the following answer from Teresias the ancient Homeric prophet: “The life of the common sort is best, and you will act more wisely if you stop speculating about heavenly bodies and discussing final causes and first causes, spit your scorn at those clever syllogisms, and counting all that sort of thing nonsense, make it always your sole object to put the present to good use and to hasten on your way, laughing a great deal and taking nothing seriously.”11 The moral and the epistemological emphases on the “here and now” are entwined together in Lucian’s “True Histories”, his most pointed disparagement of 10 Lucian, Icaromenippus, or the Sky-Man translated by A. M. Harmon, in Lucian, 8 vols. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1913, vol. II, 277-279. 11 Lucian, Menippus or the Descent into Hades, ibid. vol. IV, 107-109. 12 curiosity. This satirical exposition is composed of a set of fantastic voyages, taking the story teller to the moon, into the bowels of a whale, and to a series of islands constituting the imaginary regions of dreams and the after-life. This strange trip is set in motion by idle curiosity to reach beyond the limits of what is possible to know. Lucian identifies symbolically the transgression of these limits with sailing beyond the Pillars of Hercules in quest of vain knowledge of the unknown. “Once upon a time, setting out from the Pillars of Hercules and heading for the western ocean with a fair wind, I went a-voyaging. The motive and purpose of my journey lay in my intellectual activity and desire for adventures, and in my wish to find what the end of the ocean was, and who the people were who lived on the other side.” 12 Through these voyages, Lucian is setting the limits of what can be known and of what is worth knowing! The quest for whatever lies beyond these limits will produce nothing but ridiculous and worthless stories. This quest is so futile that such life-wasting curiosity in search of the unobtainable receives its due punishment only in the afterlife: “Sentence was given that for being inquisitive and not staying at home we should be tried after death.”13 Staying at home means for Lucian not investigating what is beyond one’s reach: neither forward in space – it serves no rational purpose to venture crossing the Pillars of Hercules; nor into the future – Lucian’s greatest lie, as one of the earliest commentators adds in the 12 Lucian, A True Story, ibid. vol. I, p. 253. 13 Ibid., p. 313 13 margin, was his promise to tell more stories in his future work; nor investigating what is above – as the result is the grotesque voyage to the moon; nor what is below us – into the belly of the whale who inhabits the depth of the ocean. Finally any attempt to truly know the past is futile and will result in absurd answers, such as Homer who discloses that he is actually a Babylonian. Lucian is setting the horizon of any possible knowledge, identifying it with the actual horizons of one’s visual grasp. Only what is immediate can be known, and is worth knowing. A much similar echo of such sentiment is found in the 2nd Century Jewish literature. At the opening of Bk. III of the treatise Hagiga dealing with the nature of esoteric knowledge, the following admonition is asserted: “Every one who tries to know the following four things, it was better for him if he had never come into the world, viz.: What is above and what is beneath, what is in front (i.e. what was before), and what is behind (i.e. what will be after). “14 It is possible, now, to point to a common grain of critical attitude to curiosity prevalent in late antiquity.15 It was not an outcome of a mistranslation and it was not restricted to the knowledge of higher things. The culture of the early centuries A.D. was highly susceptible to such interpretation of St. Paul’s indignation of “high 14 The Mishnah, “Hagiga” 2.1, in The Mishnah, trans. And introduction and notes by H. Danby, (Oxford, 1933), 213. 15 See also P. G. Walsh, "The Rights and Wrongs of Curiosity (Plutarch to Augustine)," Greece & Rome 2nd Ser., 35 (1988), 73-85. 14 heartedness” as an epistemological prohibition on seeking knowledge of the beyond. Furthermore, this resentment of curiosity was not concerned only with knowledge of higher things (such as astronomy) but in general with the quest after knowledge of things that are beyond the reach of human senses. The origin of these prohibitions and admonitions was not only in religious fear, but more so in a real epistemological problem: in order for one to know, one has to come into as direct contact with the objects of knowledge as possible. To know something is actually to grasp it.16 Icarus' desire to truly know heavenly phenomena led him to attempt to fly there in a vain and disastrous effort to perceive them closely and directly. *** How do such instructions and admonitions accommodate both Jewish as well as Greek celebration of human intelligence, learning and desire for true knowledge? How is knowledge possible, if all one can truly and fully know is in the immediate field of perception? How can human striving after knowledge be kept on the middle path ('medio' que 'ut limite curras, Icare,' ait 'moneo…'), commended by Daedalos to Icarus? A possible answer is found in one of the Talmudic stories following the above Mishnaic admonition. The sages tell of the mystical experience of four who 16 Stanley Rosen, "Thought and Touch: A Note on Aristotle's De Anima,” in his The Quarrel Between Philosophy and Poetry: Studies in Ancient Thought (New York and London: Routledge, 1988), pp.119-126. 15 entered an orchard “Ben Azai, Ben Zoma, Other, and Rabbi Akiva. Told them Rabbi Akiva when you come upon stones of pure marble do not say water, water, as it is said “he that telleth lies shall not tarry in my sight. “ Ben Azai cast a look and died… Ben Zoma peeped and [was mentally] impaired… Other cut the plantation [a heretic], Rabbi Akiva departed in peace.”17 Rabbi Akiva's advice is simple: in one’s progress towards knowledge of the divine, the most important thing is not to get confused. In order to stand in God’s sight one has to be careful in deciphering what is in front of one’s own eyes. The symbolic signification of confusing marble for water is the demarcating line between the artificial and the natural, or the dynamic and its static representation. In any case the message is that at each stage of the mystical progression one is to verify and check only what is in one’s immediate field of vision, and not to peep, or steal a glance of what is not yet open to sensory grasp. In other words, curiosity is again interpreted as an attempt to look beyond what is given, and is still a dangerous temptation because it leads to erroneous perceptions and confusion between the different domains of the divine realm. Another way of progression towards knowledge is the Aristotelian method. For all their difference these two ways of knowing share two similar principles: knowledge is based on what is immediately given, and going beyond that 17 The Babylonian Talmud, "Hagigah" 14b. For a slightly different translation: The Babylonian Talmud: Seder Mo'ed- Hagigah, translation, notes, glossary and indices under the editorship of Rabbi Dr. I. Epstein, London: The Soncino Press, 1938, p. 91 16 inattentively leads to error; and confusing the different domains of knowledge is a categorical mistake to be avoided at all costs. One of the aims of Aristotelian scientific method is to define the limits of human desire for knowledge, and to determine what is knowable and to what extent it can be known. Any science, according to Aristotle, begins with direct sense perceptions. In On Generation and Corruption and in the fourth book of Meteorology Aristotle defines the object of natural philosophy as being the potentially perceptible body, corpus potentia sensibile. These perceptions are mixed and an act of analysis and division, differentiating the diverse aspects of the phenomena and assigning each its proper characteristics is demanded. For each aspect of the observed phenomena there exists a special scientific treatment: Consideration of change are treated by the science of physics, considerations of shape are a geometrical matter etc. Each and every science has its own principles of demonstration, and scientific demonstrations must be from proper principles and cannot pass from one subject to another. In the Posterior Analytics Aristotle asserts that: “One cannot, therefore, prove anything by crossing from another genus (metabasis eis allo genos) – e.g. something geometrical by arithmetic.”18 At the core of the Aristotelian scheme is a basic notion of order (cosmos), where each thing in the world has one unique characteristic that defines it, and in accordance a unique place in the universe (its natural place). Thus, each science has 18 Aristotle, Posterior Analytics, bk I, ch. 7, 75a38, in The Complete Works of Aristotle, p. 122. 17 its own unique principles in accordance with its subject matter, just as each sense organ has its unique sensibilia. This attitude led the Aristotelian tradition to an intricate discussion of the nature of mathematical sciences, such as astronomy, music and optics. In these cases physical phenomena of change and motions were not explained according to the precepts of physics but through mathematical demonstrations. In a sense, these sciences demanded one to pry beyond the immediate given and to mobilize a causal account from a different field of knowledge. The question of what exactly was the status of such demonstrations haunted commentators of Aristotle through the Middle-Ages and the Renaissance, leading to such notions as scientia media, or “mixed sciences”. Such disturbing notions became even more alarming in the context of emerging scholasticism of the 12th and 13th centuries.19 19 For extensive discussions of this theme see: W. Roy Laird, “Robert Grosseteste on the Intermediate Sciences,” in Traditio 43 (1987), 147-169, and his “Galileo and the Mixed Sciences,” in Method and Order in Renaissance Philosophy of Nature: The Aristotle Commentary Tradition (eds.) D. A. Di Liscia, E. Kessler, and Ch. Metheun, 1997 253-270. See also: Carlos A. Ribeiro do Nascimento, “Le Statut epistemologique de ‘sciences intermédiaires’ selon s. Thomas d’Aquin,” in cahiers d’Etudes Medievales,2 (1974), 33-95; R. D. McKirahan, Jr., “Aristotle’s Subordinate Sciences,” in British Journal for the History of Science 11 (1978), 197-220; S. J. Livesey, “Metabasis: The Interrelationship of the Sciences in Antiquity and the Middle Ages,” PhD thesis, Univ. California at Los Angeles 1982; idem, “The Oxford Calculatores, Quantification of Qualities, and Aristotle’s Prohibition of metabasis,” in Vivarium 24 (1986), 5069; idem, Theology and Science in the Fourteenth Century: Three Questions on the Unity and 18 Early Scholasticism merged together the two strands of finding one’s way through the woods of religious revelation and the logical order of the sciences. A good example of such an effort is Hugh of St. Victor’s Didascalicon. In discussing the right method for studying the Scripture, Hugh presents the following parable: “Consider two men both travelling through a wood, one of them struggling around in bypaths but the other picking the short cuts of a direct route: they move along their ways with the same amount of motion, but they do not reach the goal at the same time. But what shall I call Scripture if not a wood? It thoughts, like so many sweetest fruits, we pick as we read and chew as we consider them. Therefore, whoever does not keep to an order and a method in the reading of so great a collection of books wander as it were into the very thick of the forest and loses the path of the direst knowledge.” 20 In the Talmudic story the question of method is but alluded to, Hugh is explicit that in order not to go astray in the great forest of religious mysteries caution is a necessary principle of conduct: “Two things are necessary, namely work and method for that work… He who works along without discretion works, it is true, but he does not make Subalteration of the Sciences from John of Reading’s Commentary on the Sentences (Studien und Texte zur Geistesgeschichte des Mittelalters 25), Leiden, 1989. 20 Hugh of St. Victor, The Didascalicon of Hugh of St. Victor: Medieval Guide to the Arts, trans. With introduction and notes by Jerome Taylor (New York and London: Columbia University Press, 1961) 126-7 19 progress, and just as if he were beating the air, he pour out his strength upon wind. “21 The method is the logical Aristotelian separation between the different disciplines and ways of inquiry. The beginning of all learning is in this act of division and of mapping the right path for one’s intellectual endeavor: “But although all the arts tend toward the single end of philosophy, they do not all take the same road, but have each of them their own proper businesses by which they are distinguished from one another. “ 22 Such acts of separation and clear perception of what is before one eye’s is a safeguard against getting lost: “Seek, therefore, in every art what stands establish as belonging specifically to it… Do not strike into a lot of by-ways until you know the main roads: you will go along securely when you are not under the fear of going astray.”23 Those who do not follow the precepts of Hugh’s method are the impudent curious who seek hidden things that can be revealed only as a final meditation not before. “There are still others who … wish to search into hidden matters and to hear about un-heard of things… their will is not evil, only senseless. “24 21 ibid. 22 ibid. 71. 23 ibid. 90. 24 ibid. 134. 20 This search after the curious facts leads the mind in a disorderly way to collect different materials that lead to haughtiness and confusion: “Certain persons, while they omit nothing which ought to be read, nonetheless do not know how to give each art what belongs to it… It is not the teaching of others that they accomplish in this way, but the showing off of their own knowledge … Only consider how perverse this practice is. Surely the more you collect superfluous details the less you are able to grasp or to retain useful matters. ” 25 Such curiosity was equated to impudence: “Impudence arises when we do not keep to the suitable order and method of the things we are learning.”26 The right order begins with separation borders. Only then can the path to hidden things be disclosed with no confusion: “The method of expounding a text consists of analysis… We analyse through separation into parts when we distinguish from one another things which are mingled together. [Then] [w]e analyse by examination when we open up things which are hidden.” 27 25 ibid. 89. 26 ibid. 127. 27 ibid. 150. 21 These strictures and warnings are not concerned solely with confusion and ambiguity but with the anxiety of glancing at something that is not yet in full view. Successful meditation of hidden mysteries takes place only at the end of the learning process. Any other attempt to traverse beyond the actual scenery exposed at each stage of student progression can be disastrous. The curious, in search of hidden things, collects facts haphazardly that cannot be integrated into an intelligible picture. This was intimately connected with the specifically medieval art of memory as a mode of thinking and composing. “In terms of mnemotechnic, curiosity constitutes both image “crowding” – a mnemotechnical vice, because crowding images together blurs them, blocks them, and thus dissipates their effectiveness for orienting and cueing – and randomness, or making backgrounds that have no pattern in them.”28 *** These anxieties gave rise to a vast literature on the classification of knowledge, in an attempt to secure the proper order of progress toward knowledge, and what can be learned and viewed at each of the specified stages. These medieval treatises combined didactic devices together with metaphysical concerns that shaped the way different sciences were practiced. A case at hand is Scholastic treatment of optics and vision. The first exponents of the new Arabic optics in the West were attracted to the manner in which it combined mathematics 28 Mary Carruthers, The Craft of Thought: Meditation, Rhetoric, and the Making of Images, 400- 1200, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998, p. 82 22 and physics. Together with the Biblical status of light as the firstly created entity, it enabled thinkers such as Robert Grosseteste and Roger Bacon in the 13th century to install it as a corner stone for their theological speculations. This unique amalgamation traversed the border-lines between the disciplines set in such treatises as Hugh of St. Victor’s Didascalicon, in a way that seemed to allow real opportunity for a theological revival leading to new revelations and salvation. Roger Bacon asserted, in his discussion of the utility of the mathematical sciences for divine matters, that geometry can serve as a mighty tool in explicating the spiritual meaning of the Scripture. In order to decipher such mysteries as Noah’s Ark, the Temple of Solomon and Ezekiel or Aaron’s vestments, one has to be "well acquainted with the books of the Elements of Euclid and Theodosius and Milleius and of the other geometricians.” Deciphering these geometrical secrets will transform human sense of sight and will lead to the deepest mysteries contained in the Scripture. “Oh, how the ineffable beauty of the divine wisdom would shine and infinite benefit would overflow, if these matters relating to geometry, which are contained in Scriptures, should be placed before our eyes in their physical forms! For thus the evil of the world would be destroyed by a deluge of grace.” Understanding the geometrical principles underlying such biblical constructions would lead to a new visibility where the exposed mysteries would reveal 23 themselves not as allegorical and in spiritual form but would materialize in front of the human contemplator. “And with Ezekiel in the spirit of exultation we should sensibly behold what he perceived only spiritually, so that at length after the restoration of the New Jerusalem we should enter a larger house decorated with fuller glory. Surely the mere vision perceptible to our senses would be beautiful, but more beautiful since we should see in our presence the form of our truth, but most beautiful since aroused by the visible instruments we should rejoice in contemplating the spiritual and literal meaning of Scripture …which the bodies themselves sensible to our eyes exhibit. Therefore I count nothing more fitting for a man diligent in the study of God’s wisdom than the exhibition of geometrical forms of this kind before his eyes.”29 This radical program aimed at instilling geometry into corporeal nature as well as into the literal meaning of Scripture. Bacon hoped that this would lead to a direct and immediate visual perception of the spiritual significance that lay concealed beyond human post-lapsarian sensual grasp. Such a program threatened the meticulous structure of scholastic progression toward knowledge and was rebuked both on philosophical grounds and also because of its transgression of the set borders of the disciplines. Bacon’s views 29 Roger Bacon, The Opus Majus of Roger Bacon, edited with introduction and analytical table by John Henry Bridges (Oxford: 1897) Vol. 1, pp. 210-11, trans. Robert B. Burke (Russel and Russel Inc., New York: 1962) vol. 1, pp. 223-234 24 were condemned in 1278 and he was put under arrest. In 1280 John Pecham has undertaken to correct and re-arrange the science of optics in order to prevent any future transgressions and confusions. In the preface of his treatise Perspectiva Communis Pecham is well aware that in the science of optics "glory is found physically as well as mathematically so that perspective is adorned by the flowers of both." Yet this glory had its own dangers and Pecham is set to re-establish the border-lines separating mathematics and physics, lines that were obscured in former treatises on the subject: “I shall compress into concise summaries the teachings of perspective, which [in existing treatises] are presented with great obscurity.” This is mainly concern with the differentiation between mathematical and physical demonstrations “according to the type of subject matter”. It is especially important to put the subject of light and vision into order as exactly at this transitional area one is lured to peep beyond what is directly given: “As the Master – the light – of all men deems the investigator of light worthy of illumination.” 30 Pecham structures his treatise exactly in response to this challenge. Each traditional topic of the theory of vision receives its appropriate modicum of mathematics. In some cases Pecham rejects the mathematical explanation as unsuitable. In the case of radiation of light through pinholes, for instance, Pecham 30 John Pecham, John Pecham and the Science of Optics – Perspectiva communis, edited with an introduction, English translation, and critical noted by David C. Lindberg (Madison: The University of Wisconsin Press, 1970) p. 61. 25 rejects the mathematical explanation (“cannot serve as the whole cause”), and prefers a physical explanation concerned with the nature of light (“light is naturally moved towards this shape”).31 Pecham, by rearranging the propositions of optics, neutralized the radical implications suggested by Bacon, and re-establishes that one can see clearly only what in front of one’s face and only at an appropriate distance.32 *** The waning of the scholastic system and of the medieval universities, together perhaps with the new voyages of discovery that left behind the Pillars of Hercules brought the anxiety of “metaphysical voyeurism”33 back to the surface of the European intellectual culture. Questions of knowledge and demonstration were discussed in different social and cultural spheres of activity. Debates concerning the scientific method took place all through European centers of learning from Padua through the Lutheran universities of Germany to Paris and Oxford. A common thread running through all these discussions and treatises was an attempt to defend these threatened disciplinary boundaries for fear of confusion. “Parmenides and Melissus committed similar errors, transferring to physics not physical reasons but mathematical ones, confusing therefore the limits of 31 32 33 Ibid. Proposition 5, pp. 70-71. For instance ibid. propositions 48, 49, 63 pp. 130-131; 140-141. This expression from Walter Stephens, Demon Lovers: Witchcraft, Sex, and the Crisis of Belief (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2002) p.32. 26 the disciplines … one should diligently observe not to confuse the limits and terms of the sciences; this is plainly the first step in any method.”34 Together with these admonitions the sixteenth century witnessed the revival of the mythical figure of Icarus and of the lessons derived from his fall. The trouble with Icarus’ curiosity, from the vantage point of sixteenth century scholars, was not only in his endeavor to reach out to a forbidden sphere of knowledge, but in his futile and absurd attempt to see and know things that are completely beyond the grasp of human senses and reason. This renewed interest in Icarus was linked up with a revival of the Lucian–style mocking of astronomers. These derisions aimed not at astronomers’ attempt to know what is above, but at their presumptuousness to inquire what is beyond the range of human perception. And thus Erasmus repeats Lucian's ridicule: "Theirs is certainly a pleasant form of madness, which sets them building countless universes and measuring the sun the moon, stars and planets by rule of a thumb or a bit of string, and producing reasons for thunderbolts, winds, eclipses and other inexplicable phenomena. They never pause for a moment, as if they'd access to the secrets of Nature, architect of the universe, or had 34 Jacob Schegk, De demonstratione libri xv. Nuvum opus: Galeni librorum eiusdem argumenti, iacturam resarciens antehoc non visum, sed nunc primum in lucem, (Basle, 1564), fol. 147 Quoted in Sachiko Kusukawa, "Lutherans Uses of Aristotle: a comparison between Jacob Schegk and Philip Melanchton", in Philosophy in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries: conversations with Aristotle, co-edited with Constance Blackwell, Aldershot: Ashgate, 1999. p.177 27 come to us straight from the council of gods. Meanwhile Nature has a fine laugh at them and their conjectures, for their total lack of certainty is obvious enough from the endless contention amongst themselves on every single point."35 This was not only the aversion of a humanist scholar to the mathematical practitioners, but it was an epistemological frustration that troubled astronomers themselves in the sixteenth century. Icarus signified for sixteenth century astronomers an acute awareness of the limits of their knowledge: "God the Creator placed these bodies so far away from our senses that we are unable to produce principles of demonstration for them (as we can in the sciences of other things) or to discover what is natural and familiar, by means of which we may afterwards set out the causes of particular appearances." 36 This is not a politico-religious prohibition but a technical discussion of the possibility of visually experiencing heavenly events as physical events and not only as mere appearances. According to the basic percepts of Euclidean optics the 35 Desiderius Erasmus, The Praise of Folly, trans., B. Radice (London, 1971), 151. 36 Frischlin, Nicodemus. 1586. De astronomicae artis, cum doctrina coelesti, et naturali philosophia, congruentia. . . . Frankfurt: Spies.p. 41, quoted in Jardine, Nicholas. 1988. "Epistemology of the Sciences." Pp. 685-711 in The Cambridge History of Renaissance Philosophy, eds. by C. B. Schmitt, et al. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, p. 700. See also Peter Barker and Bernard Goldstein, "Realism and Instrumentalism in Sixteenth Century Astronomy: A Reappraisal" Perspectives on Science 6.3 (1998) 232-258. 28 distance at which an object is seen is inversely proportionate to the size of the angle of vision and beyond a given distance it is no longer visible on account of the decrease in the size of the angle.37 Theological discussions of the power of sight emphasized that only in the afterlife the Blessed can enjoy a perfect vision: “The Blessed have keener eyesight, so they will see a thing under an angle however small, and thus, however small a thing is and however far away it is placed, they will see it. Hence there will remain no imperfection in them as there is in us.”38 Thus even the great observational astronomer Tycho Brahe had to admit this drawback. In his debate with Hartman over the question of the heavenly matter he acknowledged that in the final account as a physical problem the matter of the heavens was inscrutable (imperscrutabilis).39 It is in this context that the significance of the figure of Icarus in the sixteenth century (both in the literature of emblems and in Bruegel’s picture) is divulged. This was not only an expression of anxiety from transgressing into illicit domains, 37 Euclide, L’Optique et la catoptrique, French trans. By Paul Ver Eecke (Paris, 1959), propositions III and V, pp. 3-4. 38 Alphonso de Tostado de Rivera Madrigal (1401-54/55), “Commentaria in IV. Part. Matthaei,” cap. XVII, qu. CXVI, in Opera Omnia, edn (Cologne, 1613), vol.X, p. 414. 39 Tycho Brahe, Epistolarum astronomicarum libri (Uraniburg, 1596), p. 111, in Tycho Brahe Opera Omnia, ed. J. L. E. Dreyer, 15 vols. (Copenhagen, 1913-29), reprinted, Amsterdam, 1972, vol. VI, p. 140. 29 but also a frustration in the face of the shortcomings of human ability to know. In the repeated warnings and admonitions of Icarus, one can sense that, to paraphrase Hamlet’s mother: “They did protest too much, me thinks.” A careful examination of Bruegel’s painting will noticeably reveal this ambiguity; the general message of the image is the realization that “there is no new thing under the sun… there is no remembrance of former things…” Yet, the painting itself repeats the myth of Icarus and contributes to the perpetuation of his fame. A further element is the sailing ships with their blown sails: Are they returning safely to the harbor, or are they sailing out to the open sea, westward towards the setting sun, aiming to cross the Pillars of Hercules for the new world, like a similar boat a few decades later on the frontispiece of Francis Bacon’s Instauratio magna? One witnesses in the falling of Icarus the clash between two sets of values: the pagan notion of Fame and the Judeo-Christian quietism, the innate limits on human capacity to know, and the human urge to break through these barriers. The same tension underlies other depictions of Icarus of the sixteenth century and especially those Ginzburg put forward from the literature of emblems. The apparent and straightforward expression of warning and indignation of those “which paste theire reache doe mounte, whoe seeke the thinges, to mortall men 30 deny’de,”40 is presented entwined with the emblem’s aspiration to disclose hidden meanings. The literature of emblems was a bold attempt to create new devices of knowledge, through paradoxical games that conflated together different levels of interpretation with different systems of sensory experience. By combining a verbal expression, a puzzle and a picture, the emblem enabled the reader to bridge gaps and inconsistencies in the different textual traditions, to look beyond language and to conjure up the invisible secrets of nature. It combined in one picture the transmission of knowledge, the explanation of its hidden meaning, together with the potency of the image to create magical effects in the physical world as well as in the human psyche. The emblem produced this effect by suggesting initially, a fictive, yet rigid, spatial arrangement, within which a dramatic and fantastic action took place. It further emphasized its paradoxical appearance by combining visible signs with verbal puzzles, thus displaying different and only artificially connected sensory systems. Michael Maier characterizes his alchemical treatise of emblems, Atalanta fugiens of 1617 as: 40 Whitney, Geffrey. A Choice of Emblemes, and other devises, For the moste part gathered out of sundrie writers, Englished and Moralized. And divers newly devised. / by Geffrey Whitney. Imprinted at Leyden, In the house of Christopher Plantyn, by Francis Raphelengius, 1586, p. 28. 31 "Partly adapted to the eyes and the intellect, with copper-etchings, and added sentences, Epigrams and notes, partly [adapted] to the ears and to the recreation of the soul with less than 50 musical fugues in three voices ... to be seen, read, meditated, understood, judged, sung and listened with particular pleasure."41 Maier's intention is the paradoxical combination of solitary contemplation and sensual pleasure. The emblem makes it possible for the contemplative spectator to awaken his mnemonic powers, not in order to induce fantasies of the sensual and material realm but to rise into that garden where “roses of philosophy bloom”. The alchemical emblems tackled the gap between the realm of concrete visual signs and the hidden realm of universal concepts by turning this gap into a paradox, into a serious play.42 In this play the “serious conclusions” are always ephemeral, always hinting that things are not what they seem, and that any serious truth 41 Michael Maier, Atalanta Fugiens, hoc est, Emblemata nova de secretis naturae chymica (Oppenheim, 1617). 42 On “Serious Jokes” and their role in late sixteenth century and early seventeenth century intellectual world see: R.Colie, Paradoxia Epidemica: The Renaissance Tradition of Paradox (Princeton NJ, 1966), Findlen, Paula. "Jokes of Nature and Jokes of Knowledge: The Playfulness of Scientific Discourse in Early Modern Europe," Renaissance Quarterly 43 (1990), 292-331, and Thomas DaCosta Kaufmann, "Arcimboldo's Serious Jokes: "Mysterious but Long Meaning," The Verbal and the Visual: Essays in Honor of William S. Heckscher, eds. K. L. Selig and E. Sears, (New York,1990) 59-80. 32 arrived at, will evaporate immediately in front of the frustrated gaze of the sinful human mind. The emblems distort reality and force the human mind to turn its gaze inside in search of a profound and invisible truth. Francois Beroalde de Verville in his alchemical novel of 1610, Le Voyage des Princes Fortunez summarized this practice as: "The art of representing plainly that which is easily conceived but, which under the coarsened features of its appearance, hides subjects quite other than that which seems to be represented; this is practiced in painting when some landscape or harbour scene or portrait is shown which conceals within itself some other figure which can be discerned by looking from a certain viewpoint determined by the artist. This is done also in writing, when an author discourses at large on plausible subjects that unfold some other Excellencies which are known only when read from a secret angle which uncovers splendours concealed from common appearance."43 Within these visual images lay an urge to approach the invisible truth. These visual tricks were machinated in order to let the spectator glimpse beyond the epistemological barrier at the invisible realm “concealed from common appearances”. It was a matter of a technical apparatus and solution to a crucial epistemological problem, not only an act of transgression. 43 Translated in Stanislas Klossowski de Rola, The Golden Game: Alchemical Engravings from the Seventeenth Century (London: Thames and Hudson, 1988), p. 28. 33 The same technical barrier allowed astronomers to deal only with distant and blurred appearances and not with physical phenomena and causes. On the close of the sixteenth century this became a source of both epistemological anxiety and a technical concern. Various philosophers and astronomers (Jacopo Zabarella, Lodovico Carbone, Ursus to name but a few) argued that astronomy had but a limited claim for knowledge, and that it was based on mere fictitious hypotheses. Tycho Brahe’s plan to reform astronomy and bypass these difficulties with better contraptions and instruments of observation stumbled over sundry problems of measurements and analyses of observed celestial phenomena (his polemics with Hartman over the refractions of stellar light, the changing size of lunar diameter during solar eclipses, and his bitter confrontation with Ursus). The failure of Icarus to reach the heavens designates the common denominator of the methodological discussions over astronomy towards the end of the sixteenth century: Since one cannot reach the heavens, one cannot perceive heavenly phenomena directly. Therefore, astronomy is condemned to treat apparent motions only and is unable to investigate hidden causes, but to confine itself in suggesting possible and reasonable causal hypotheses.44 Just a few years later the Imperial mathematician and famous astronomer Johannes Kepler 44 For instance see: M. Maestlin, De astronomiae principalibus et primis fundamentis disputatio (Heidelberg, 1582), folA2v: "Astronomia… enim est scientia, quae motus corporum coelestium scrutatur et explicat… Apparentia enim motuum non physicis, sed mathematicis rationibus demonstrantur." 34 commented on Alciati's emblem of the falling Icarus that: “no one falls, laying flatly on the earth.”45 With these words Kepler hinted that astronomical knowledge can be attained without flying into the heavens, and without directly perceiving heavenly phenomena. What has allowed Kepler to suggest this change in astronomical knowledge? How can true knowledge (and for Kepler this meant causal knowledge) evolve without direct and immediate contact with its objects? *** In 1604, an increasing sense of crisis led Kepler to the conclusion that a new optics is needed in order “to uphold astronomy’s dignity and to subdue the hostile fortress of doubt.”46 The task was to find a new view point and “a secret angle” from which celestial phenomena could be measured and be physically known. With this mission in mind, he published his optical treatise Ad Vitellionem paralipomena, quibus astronomiae pas optica traditur.47 Examining this couplet "Astronomiae pars optica" against the backdrop of classical and medieval philosophy 45 Kepler's complete comment reads "Nemo cadit, recubans, terrae de cespite planae; Ocuras hominum, o quanta est in rebus inane." (Francisco Sanchez of Salamanca, Commentary on Alciati's Emblemata, Lyons 1573, in the British Library, Egerton MS 1234). 46 Johannes Kepler, Ad Vitellionem paralipomena, quibus astronomiae pars optica traditor (Francofurti, 1604) published in Johannes Kepler, Gesammelte Werke, eds. Walter von Dyck and Max Caspar, 24 vols. (Munich, 1937-), vol. 2, ed. Franz Hammer, p.6 [my translation]. 47 Unless otherwise is stated I have used the following English translation: Johannes Kepler, Optics: Paralipomena to Witelo and Optical Part of Astronomy, translated by William H. Donahue, Santa Fe, New Mexico: Green Lion Press, 2000. 35 discloses a surprising oxymoron: can there be optics, that is, an account of visual experience, of the heavens? Since classical theories of visual perception, as noted above, accentuated direct contact with the perceived object, the remoteness of the stars leaves the observer with only indirect and uncertain appearances. The heavenly visual signs are only hints to a reality one cannot perceive directly. All that an astronomer has to fall back on are hypothetical conjectures. The outcome of this classical epistemological position was a divorce between observation and the actuality of the heavens. Kepler's new optics intended to do just this, to allow observation of distant, and almost invisible, objects to grant knowledge as valid as the observation of things at hand. Such new optics would allow measurement of invisible lines and circles and yet these measurements would substantiate physical truths far more certain than the measurements of static solid and corporeal objects. Paradoxically, Keplerian optics would prefer indirect visual experience of shadows and virtual images over direct experience of tangible entities. What is the mechanism that allows such apparently absurd optics to work? What are the epistemological foundations of such a scientific oxymoron: optics - or a science of visual experience - of things that are beyond the power of one's eyesight? At the opening sentences of his optics Kepler presents geometry and mathematics as the tools that would allow astronomers to observe the heavens as if directly. 36 “Astronomy… fl[ies] up into heavens, supported … by (as it were) a pair of wings, geometry and arithmetic.” 48 These mathematical disciplines would serve like the wings of Icarus to lift the human observer to the sky. However, these wings would not melt and, unlike Plato’s allegory of the winged soul, would allow the astronomer more than a mere ephemeral glimpse at the celestial phenomena. Kepler trusts that these new tools would transform astronomy into a physical science. Through careful application of mathematics, astronomy would be able to investigate not appearances but “the motions of the heavenly bodies” themselves. The mission Kepler sets for his new science is to "direct the eyes to the central mystery of the cosmic machine". 49The only way to achieve this task is by reformulating the nature of visual experience in general and the nature of scientific observation in particular. How can Kepler assess an optical theory that concerns 48 Kepler, Optics, p.13. The obvious allusion is to Plato's allegory of the winged soul in Phaedrus, 246. Closer in time is P. Melanchton, Praefatio in arithmeticen Joachimi Rhetici (1536): "Sunt igitur alae mentis humanae, Arithmetica et Geometria. Has si alligaverit sibi aliquis praeditus ingenio non sordido, facilime penetrabit in coelum ac libere in coelestium coetu vagabitur, et illa luce ac sapientia fruetur." In Corpus Reformatorum, ed. C. G. Bretscneider, vols. 1-21 (18341860), vol. 11, 288. Quoted in Charlotte Metheun, Kepler's Tubingen: Stimulus to a Theological Mathematics (Aldershot: Ashgate, 1998) p. 75. See also Nicholas Jardine, The Birth of History and Philosophy of Science: Kepler's A Defence of Tycho against Ursus with Essays on Its Provenance and Significance (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1984), p. 186 n.168. 49 Kepler to Maestlin, 1/11 June 1598, GW vol. 13, p. 225. 37 itself with invisible elements? How does such optics supply the means to measure an empty space? To tackle such a task Kepler cannot content himself with reiterating traditional optical theory; he has to redefine the tenets of optics in order for it to accomplish these expectations. The main revision is ontological. At the core of medieval theory of perspective lay the notion of species as a physical expression or communication of the visible body itself. The multiplication of species was molded into a visual ray in the case of sight and into physical radiation in other cases of action at a distance (such as in the case of a magnet), light being just a paradigmatic case. Kepler’s revolutionary alteration takes place almost unnoticed: “The things optics considers in astronomy are either the things themselves set before the sense of sight, where the species of things, that is light and shadow are considered.” 50 The identification of species with light and shade radically undermines medieval optics and theories of cognition. The objects of sight are no longer emanations of physical things, that can guarantee the success of the cognitive process in keeping direct contact with external reality, but merely light or its absence reflected back from the visual field. Kepler abandons visual rays and physical emanation and reduces them all to a radiation of light. This discreet maneuver releases optical research from 50 Kepler, Ad Vitellionem, p. 15. [my translation] 38 psychological considerations of intentions and cognition, allowing Kepler to take optics as a physical study of light. It allows him, further, to reduce these studies to the questions of the transition of light through media: “The medium, through which light the carrier of species travels, by the cause of it, one way or another, light reaches us refracted.” 51 Besides light and its travel through different media, optics deals with the instruments of observation and the eye as receptors of these refractions. In this way Kepler reduces all visual experience to refractions of light, and therefore there is no difference in observing the distant heavenly bodies or an object in the immediate visual field. The images produced are, in the final account, effects of refractions of light. This becomes clear when Kepler moves on and narrows the general definition of optics and discusses specifically the celestial bodies. Here he emphasizes that the astronomer considers only the species of these bodies transmitted as light, and that these species are nothing but their mathematical properties, namely figure and size. Therefore in order to capture visual phenomena there’s no need for a complete imagery, with all its sensual details of colors and texture. Since light transmits quantifiable properties only, also mere shadow can now suffice as the foundation for true analysis of physical phenomena. Kepler thus reduces the entire visual world to a theatre of reflections and refractions of light, turning the absence of 51 Kepler, Ad Vitellionem, p. 15 [my translation] 39 material bodies into a foundation of true knowledge of creation. His intuition is based on the role of eclipses (in other words the absence of the luminaries) in instituting astronomical science. “For the most noble and ancient part of astronomy is the eclipse of the sun and the moon, a subject that, as Pliny says, is in the entire study of nature the most wondrous, and most like a portent.”52 The disappearance of the luminaries is the basis of any inquiry and is the invitation God left the human race to study His creation. This invitation is ordered like a theatre with signs and allusions to be deciphered by the human mind which is the likeness of God Himself: Anyone who ponders this [the eclipsed luminaries] carefully will find … both that there is God, founder of all nature, and that in the very mechanics of it he had care for the humans that were to come. For this theatre of the world is so ordered that there exist in it suitable signs by which the human minds, likenesses of God, are not only invited to study the divine works… but also are assisted in inquiring more deeply. Emphasizing the theatrical metaphor, Kepler compared the eclipsed luminaries to playful jests Nature performs to lure the human mind to contemplate the true order of the world. 52 Kepler, Optics, p. 15. 40 This process is aptly described in the introductory epigrams to Ad Vitellionem. One of the Epigrams presenting a dialogue between the eyes and the minds ends with the latter guarantying to restore the damage suffered by the eyes on its behalf and to radiate starry brilliance from the "stains" and defects.53 What is this "stain," radiant with knowledge and what is the knowledge Kepler hoped to gain from such a defect? Kepler explicates these words in the preface: "Now, one may consider, that all the rest of Astronomy is closely associated with the motion of the Sun and the important assistance given us by the Moon, participating in the days just as in the nights, when all other means failed us: it is believed rightly that universal astronomy is born from this obscurity of the luminaries. Just as these darknesses may be the eyes of the astronomers, these defects may be a rich source for doctrines, and these stains may illustrate the most precise pictures on the mortal mind. O most excelled and commendable argument for all the nations about the glory of the shadow." 54 53 Kepler, Ad Vitellionem, GW, vol.2: Mens: Qua licet expediam; faueat modo fama loquenti; Mortales chartis perpetuabo meis. Hic etiam referam, quae pro me damna tulistis: Hicque suum et naeuis irradiabo iubar. 54 Kepler, Ad Vitellionem, p.16 "Iam qui perpenderit, quam arcte tota reliqua Astronomia cum Solis motu copuletur, quantumque nobis Luna, diei noctisque particeps, opitule'tur, quando nos 41 Kepler, in a surprising turn of phrase, turns the Platonic allegory of the cave on its head. It is the shadows, the obscurity, and the material effects of light that become the source of knowledge.55 The astronomer is not supposed to observe the sun itself but to examine its shadow in order to portray the true picture of the universe and to reveal its secrets. The quantification of shadows (i.e., the absence of the material object) is the key to Nature's powers. In sharp contrast to both Platonist and Aristotelian philosophy, Kepler asserts that a true investigation of the shadows, one that will define them correctly, then measure and analyse them accurately, will finally expose the true structure of the universe. “And thus the quantity of the image which the moon or the sun, whether whole or eclipsed, shows us, and of the shadow which the earth stretches out to the moon, must be carefully investigated by the astronomer.”56 Kepler points to the difficulties involved in such a research: omnia alia media deficiunt: iure credet, vniuersam Astronomiam his luminium obscurationibus inniti, adeo ut hae tenebrae sint Astronomorum oculi, hi defectus doctrinae sint abudantia, hi naeui mentes mortalium preciosissimis picturis illustrent. O eximium et omnibus gentibus commendabile argumentum de Vmbrae laudibus." [my translation] 55 For the epistemological status of shadows in Kepler's science see: Raz Chen-Morris, "Shadows of Instruction: Optics and Classical Authorities in Kepler's Somnium," Journal of the History of Ideas 2005, 66: 223-243. 56 Kepler, Optics, 16 42 “Even though these images are obvious to everyone’s eyes, all practicing astronomers complain that it is with difficulty that they are measured. This is partly because the bodies have a very narrow apparent size, and partly because they constrict the eye with their exceptional light, so as to prevent their fulfilling their function in seeing.”57 It is here that Kepler introduces instruments of observation as a corrective to the feeble human eyes. The prototype of such instruments is the camera obscura: “Nature has not forsaken those desirous of learning, for she has shown us a procedure by which we may accomplish in darkness, without detriment to the eyes, what is completely impossible in clear light, with the eyesight directed towards the sun.”58 Kepler constructs a new place for astronomical observation; instead of the human eye as the natural and obvious instrument of sight, it is the camera obscura as a theatre of light and shadows. Within this theatre the main characters in nature’s play are eclipses or blemishes that baffle the human senses and intrigue the human mind. In such a theatre the observer is able to artificially produce shadows and stains of light as the exact representations of the heavenly bodies, and to measure them. An important part of the optics will have to account for the possibility of observation through artificial instruments as a substitution to the natural naked-eye 57 58 ibid. ibid. 43 gaze at the heavens: “For aside from this, no other sure procedure can be established for measuring something that happens in the sky.”59 In reducing visual phenomena to light and shade, their measurable dimensions and motions, Kepler is able to condense heavenly phenomena, and literally to bring them down into his “dark chamber”. As light is the divine messenger communicating all terrestrial and celestial occurrences60, there is no need to fly to the sky or to come down from the stars in order to account for them. Kepler's camera obscura supplied seventeenth century science with a paradigmatic case of artificial observation, leading only a few years later to Galileo's telescope. Building over this paradigm the new slogans of the new science with their emphasis on sapere aude meant nothing else but the courage to apply the new instruments of observation and to artificially re-produce the hidden secrets of nature in the safety of the laboratory. 59 60 Kepler, Optics, p. 57 For instance ibid. pp.19-20: "[I]f I say, this principle… the chain linking the corporeal and spiritual world, has passed over into the same laws by which the world was to be furnished. The sun is accordingly a particular body, in it is this faculty of communicating itself to all things, which we call light." 44