Constitutional Interpretation and the Notion of

advertisement
ANCL-RADC ANNUAL CONFERENCE – ‘The Internationalisation of Constitutional
Law’ Rabat, Morocco, 2-5 February 2011
WORKING PAPER
Please do not use this paper without contacting the author on: djolowu1@yahoo.co.uk
CONSTITUTIONAL INTERPRETATION AND THE NOTION OF
UNENUMERATED RIGHTS:
CIRCUMVENTING THE EXCLUSION OF SOCIO-ECONOMIC RIGHTS IN
AFRICA
’DEJO OLOWU
ABSTRACT
In every State where the rule of law and separation of powers are recognized as norms, it
is the judicial organ of the State that bears the exclusive responsibility of interpreting the
fundamental law of the land, by whatever name it is called. The judicial organs in diverse
States have therefore evolved various approaches in carrying out this onerous
responsibility. Experience shows, however, that in interpreting constitutions, particularly
in matters implicating life, liberty, and livelihood, the courts in some jurisdictions have
identified or recognized claims and entitlements which are often beyond the rights
explicitly guaranteed in such constitutions, and some continue to do so, albeit with some
degree of inconsistency. This essay acknowledges that the notion of unenumerated rights
constitutes an affront to the more entrenched concepts of positivism and formalism and
even challenges age-long ideas about the philosophical foundations of human rights.
However, extrapolating from case law, juridical pronouncements and ongoing scholarly
discourses on the idea of unenumerated rights from different jurisdictions around the
world, this essay evaluates the potential of this path of judicial innovation in promoting
democratic governance, social justice and human rights in general, and in particular, the
genre of socio-economic rights in African States. While not oblivious of the broad range
of arguments against the notion of unenumerated rights in general terms, this essay
advocates vibrant intellectual engagement with its long- and short-term implications for
qualitative judicialism, access to justice, and genuine democratic claims in Africa, and
proffers some trajectories towards the formulation of proactive strategies.
I.
INTRODUCTION

LL.B (Hons.), LL.M, Obafemi Awolowo University, Ile-Ife, Nigeria; LL.M Human Rights &
Democratization in Africa, University of Pretoria, Pretoria, South Africa; PG Dip. Int’l Human Rights, Åbo
Akademi University, Turku, Finland; JSD Cum Laude, University of Notre Dame, Notre Dame, Indiana,
USA; Barrister & Solicitor (Nigeria); Research Professor of Law, North-West University (Mafikeng
Campus), South Africa. Email: djolowu1@yahoo.co.uk
The very nature of a ‘constitutional state’ – cherished in law-ordered societies – is
intrinsically linked to the rule of law; requiring that all authority be subject to, and
constrained by law as opposed to the whims of one man, group, or party. However, it is
axiomatic that the notion of the rule of law demands vital institutional attributes for its
sustenance in any society. Among these are comprehensive laws, adequately equipped
and independently functioning judiciary, and trained law enforcement personnel.1 Since
the interpretation of the body of laws governing a state, and in particular, the Constitution
– the fundamental law of several states in the modern world – is traditionally the
responsibility of the judicial arm of government, it becomes inevitable that the existence
and sustenance of a virile judiciary, or the absence of such, will indicate a benchmark for
measuring a state’s commitment to the rule of law.
In the context of this essay, what is central is the impact of the technique of
constitutional interpretation on the normative development of human rights. A critical
review of judicial pronouncements and scholarly views demonstrates that it is no longer
novel, could be desirable, and may indeed be inevitable, for courts to interpret written
constitutions in such a way as to accommodate human rights norms that are not expressly
enumerated in codified bills of rights. This cannot but be an attractive trend for
constitutional discourses in African states where democratization, governance and human
rights encounter enormous implementation challenges. The questions to ask, therefore, is
whether the interpretative power of the courts will cover the expansion of the body of
rights recognized in written constitutions; whether African courts can adopt proactive
1
See Randy Barnett, Can Justice and the Rule of Law Be Reconciled?, 11 HARV. J. L. & PUB.
POL’Y 597, 619-621 (1988); JEROME FRANK, LAW AND THE MODERN MIND 165-166 (1963); Rachel
Kleinfeld, Competing Definitions of the Rule of Law: Implications for Practitioners, Carnegie Paper No.
55, Jan. 2005.
2
techniques in constitutional interpretation to enhance human rights and democratic
culture; and whether this is a desirable path altogether.
An effort is made over the next few pages to examine the historical and
philosophical foundations of unenumerated rights within the framework of the judicial
function of constitutional interpretation; controversial and ‘grey areas’ in global
constitutional jurisprudence and scholarship; the impact and influences of this sort of
judicial functioning; and to evaluate the potential implications for constitutionalism and
constitutional adjudication in contemporary Africa.
II.
CONSTITUTIONALISM: BULWARK OF HUMAN RIGHTS PROTECTION
Although recent empirical studies usually trace the roots of modern political systems
from the philosophical ideas of the Greek Republics all the way through eighteenth and
nineteenth century intellectual enquiries, it has never been an easy task delimiting the
historical details of law-ordered societies.2 The earlier political thoughts – the ideas of
Plato and Aristotle; the liberalism of Locke and Rousseau as advanced in later years by
Voltaire in France, the cautious empiricism of David Hume and Adam Smith, the
utilitarianism of Immanuel Kant and Jeremy Bentham as promoted by John Stuart Mill,
and the ideas of Thomas Jefferson and James Madison as evident in the Constitution and
the Bill of Rights of the United States (US) – were all products of human history.3
2
See generally RUSELL HARDIN, LIBERALISM, CONSTITUTIONALISM AND DEMOCRACY 41-81
(2003) (contending, after an analysis of the historical development of political and economic liberalism in
the works of diverse thinkers, that “the welfarist core”, a metaphor for the guarantee of the “survival” of the
individual under any form of government, was the centrifugal idea behind all their conceptions). See also
Bruce Yandle, Sir Edward Coke and the Struggle for a New Constitutional Order, 4(2) CONST. POL. ECON.
263, 264 (1993) (evaluating the protracted political struggles against feudalism in England that culminated
in the Magna Carta of 1215, and identifying same as the basis for the “constitutional entrepreneurship” that
ensued in later times).
3
See A.E. Dick Howard, The Essence of Constitutionalism, in CONSTITUTIONALISM, AND HUMAN
RIGHTS: AMERICA, POLAND, AND FRANCE 3-41 (Kenneth W. Thompson et al, eds., 1991); ALBERT P.
BLAUSTEIN, CONSTITUTIONS OF THE WORLD 2-4 (1993).
3
History had taught those philosophers and political thinkers that when it comes to the use
of power, those who possess excessive amount of personal ambition are often the most
influential and, invariably, most dangerous; necessitating, therefore, that limits to
governmental powers must be defined by law. Plausibly, therefore, this was where the
seeds of constitutionalism were sown.4
With the enduring debates on the latitude of governmental power and the
determination of the relationship between the government and the governed, the narrow
passage of compromise among liberal-welfarists, contractarian constitutionalists, strict
constructivists, realists, conventionalists, and minimalists alike, had largely been the need
for formalized set of restrictions on those officials who wield political power –
restrictions that must be founded on the rule of law.5 This ordering of a society and its
governmental powers through the dictates of law, and limiting those powers – the
conceptual basis of which lies in classical Western political thought – is what some
scholars have described as “old constitutionalism” or “generic constitutionalism.”6
4
For a broad array of divergent perspectives on the evolution of political theories and their impact
on discourses on constitutionalism, democracy, and governance through the ages, see G EORGE CHARLES
ROCHE III, LEGACY OF FREEDOM (1973); JUDITH A. SWANSON, THE PUBLIC AND THE PRIVATE IN
ARISTOTLE’S POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 95-131 (1992); SCOTT GORDON, CONTROLLING THE STATE:
CONSTITUTIONALISM FROM ANCIENT ATHENS TO TODAY (1999) [hereinafter CONTROLLING THE STATE];
Williamson M. Evers, Social Contract: A Critique, 1(3) J. LIBERT. STUD. 185-194 (1977); David B. Suits,
On Locke’s Argument for Government, 1(3) J. LIBERT. STUD. 195-203 (1977); Randy E. Barnett, Towards
a Theory of Legal Naturalism, 2(2) J. LIBERT. STUD. 97 (1978); Suri Ratnapala, Eighteenth Century
Evolutionary Thought and its Relevance in the Age of Legislation, 12(1) CONST. POL. ECON. 51-75 (2001);
Geoffrey M. Hodgson, The Evolution of Institutions: An Agenda for Future Theoretical Research, 13(2)
CONST. POL. ECON. 111-127 (2002); Adam Gifford, The Evolution of Social Contract, 13(4) CONST. POL.
ECON. 361-379 (2002); Ariel L. Bendor, On Aristotelian Equality, the Fundamental Right to Equality, and
Governmental Discretion, 8 REV. CONST. STUD. 1-19 (2003).
5
See HARDIN, supra note 2, at 80-81, 84; Noel B. Reynolds, The Ethical Foundations of
Constitutional Order: A Conventionalist Perspective, 4(1) CONST. POL. ECON. 79-95 (1993).
6
See Stephen L. Elkin, Constitutionalism: Old and New, in A NEW CONSTITUTIONALISM:
DESIGNING POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS FOR A GOOD SOCIETY 20-37 (Stephen L. Elkin et al, eds., 1993)
[hereinafter A NEW CONSTITUTIONALISM]; Karol Edward Soltan, Generic Constitutionalism, in A NEW
CONSTITUTIONALISM, 70-93.
4
Notwithstanding the fact that constitutionalism continues to imply different things
to different writers in different political contexts, certain notions have become its
invariable parameters.7 In today’s legal parlance, constitutionalism implies governance
according to the rule of law, an important universal norm that negates arbitrary rule.8
Closely linked to this neo-liberal conception is the existence of a written constitution that
stipulates separation of governmental powers; checks and balances; judicial review;
accountable governance; and, of course, a bill of human rights.9
With the collapse of communism following the dramatic socio-economic and
political events of 1989, the ground had been laid for radical global policy reforms that
would assert the earlier day values of liberalism, free market economy and human rights
as opposed to the collectivist ideology of the defunct Eastern bloc. 10 What became
obvious, however, in the process of supplanting the old ideological divide was the
realization of the inadequacy of merely ousting the old communist order as a guarantee
7
There has been a remarkable level of discussions among scholars about the elements of
constitutionalism. While some contend that it requires a set of codified norms in written form, others have
argued that the unwritten constitutional model of the United Kingdom dispenses with the necessity of a
written constitution. Various reasons are usually canvassed by constitutionalists on these arguments. See
e.g. Jed Rubenfeld, Legitimacy and Interpretation, in CONSTITUTIONALISM: PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS
214, 216 (Larry Alexander ed., 1998) (proposing that it is the rules of a text that a government “lays down
and lives up to” that confers on it legitimate authority). Cf. Wil Waluchow, Constitutionalism, in THE
STANFORD ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY (Edward N. Zalta, ed., 2004), at
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/constitutionalism/ (last visited Jan. 14, 2011) (contending that “long
standing social rules and conventions” can become “clear and precise, as well as more rigid and entrenched
than written ones”). For other opinions, see R.W. CARSTEN, THE MEDIEVAL ANTECEDENTS OF
CONSTITUTIONALISM 3-48 (1992); JANOS KIS, CONSTITUTIONAL DEMOCRACY 112, 119, 131 (2003).
8
Louis Henkin, Elements of Constitutionalism, 60 REV. INT’L COMM’N JUR. 11, 12 (1998).
9
Id., at 12-15. See also Ernst-Ulrich Petersmann, Human Rights and International Economic Law
in the 21st Century: The Need to Clarify Their Interrelationships, 4(1) J. INT’L ECON. L. 3, 11-16 (2001)
(demonstrating through historical analysis that from the Greek Republics to the guarantees of modern
treaties, “the progressive and continuing evolution of constitutionalism has focused on the following eight
core principles”, namely, “rule of law”; “limitation of governmental powers by checks and balances”;
“democratic self-government”; “national constitutionalism”; “human rights”; “international
constitutionalism”; “social justice”; and “cosmopolitan constitutional law.” But see MICHEL VILLEY, LE
DROIT ET LES DROITS DE L'HOMME [RIGHT AND THE RIGHTS OF MAN] (1983) (challenging the philosophical
justification for constitutionalizing human rights).
10
See Katharina Pistor, The Demand for Constitutional Law, 13(1) CONST. POL. ECON. 73, 81-84
(2002).
5
for sustainable reforms. The consensual path was the gradual ascendancy of a global
culture of human rights and the rule of law, enhanced through the instrumentality of
constitutionalism.11
In the post-Cold War era, the ideals of democracy, rule of law and a culture of
human rights, rooted in constitutionalism, have become entrenched in the consciousness
of states.12 In the light of those tremendous changes that marked the end of the Cold War,
Fukuyama had exclaimed:
As mankind approaches the end of the millennium, the twin crises of
authoritarianism and socialist central planning have left only one
competitor standing in the ring as an ideology of potentially universal
validity: liberal democracy, the doctrine of individual freedom and popular
sovereignty. Two hundred years after they first animated the French and
American revolutions, the principles of liberty and equality have proven
not just durable but resurgent.13
An enduring normative idea since the age of the earlier liberal thinkers has been
the overarching imperative of human rights protection and promotion through
11
See, id., at 77-80.
See generally Diamond Larry, Is the Third Wave Over?, 7(3) J. DEM. 20-37 (1996) (showing
that as at 1996, there were over one hundred democracies in the world, and that all but three of them –
Great Britain, Israel and New Zealand – had no written constitutions even though he acknowledges their
being “democratic”). While Great Britain is readily cited as a “democracy without constitutionalism”, one
should be mindful of the great impact that the European regional human rights system has continued to
have on its human rights profile. Sight must also not be lost of instances where nations without written
constitutions have adopted distinct Bills of Rights through statutes. Glowing examples of this are the
Human Rights Act, 1998 of the United Kingdom as well as the New Zealand Bill of Rights, 1990. See
Shadrack B. O. Gutto, Current Concepts, Core Principles, Dimensions, Processes and Institutions of
Democracy and the Inter-Relationship Between Democracy and Modern Human Rights, Seminar on the
Interdependence Between Democracy and Human Rights, Geneva, Nov. 25-26, 2002, 7, available at
http://www.unchr.ch.
13
Francis Fukuyama, The End of History?, THE NAT’L. INT., No. 16 (Summer 1989), at p. 3;
Francis Fukuyama, Second Thoughts: The Last Man in a Bottle, THE NAT’L. INT., No. 56 (Summer 1999),
at p. 16. The world-wide spread of constitutional democracy since the 1990s would seem relentless. From
Latin America, across Africa, and to South East Asia, military and one-party dictatorships are being
replaced almost everywhere by elected civilian regimes. Although the indices might depict the triumph of
constitutional democracy, communist rule remains in modified form in Romania, Serbia (former
Yugoslavia) and in some parts of the former Soviet Union. Its “purer” form endures in China, Cuba, Laos,
North Korea, and Vietnam. For an insight into what has been described as the “challenge from within” to
post-Communist triumph of constitutional democracy, see Alberto Calsamiglia, Constitutionalism and
Democracy, in DELIBERATIVE DEMOCRACY AND HUMAN RIGHTS 136-142 (Harold Hongju Koh et al, eds.,
1999) [hereinafter DELIBERATIVE DEMOCRACY].
12
6
constitutional provisions. Some scholars have argued that since individuals are
themselves prone to abusing the liberties of others just as those who govern can abuse
their powers, human rights constitute the best safeguards for the defense of individual
liberties against tyranny.14 The desirability of including human rights provisions within
the body of a national constitution or as an appendage to it is an idea that has found
robust validation in ample scholarship. There is a contention that the inclusion of a bill of
rights in a constitution translates such rights into a device for “legitimacy…and political
stability” in pluralistic societies.15 Gavison also argues that “[t]he high visibility and
solemn nature of most constitutions help in making the commitment to human rights a
part of civil religion and civil-shared culture.”16 While critics of the constitutionalization
of human rights contend that the inclusion of a bill of rights is neither necessary nor
adequate to secure human rights protection,17 there is no denying the fact that the mere
existence of such explicit provisions are potent in building, institutionalizing, and
sustaining the processes that would ensure their promotion and protection as they gain
more popular and informed cognition.18
See Petersmann, supra note 9, at 10. See also Peter C. Ordeshook, Are ‘Western’ Constitutions
Relevant to Anything Other than the Countries they Serve?, 13(1) CONST. POL. ECON. 3, 8-11 (2002)
(contending that beyond being “universal necessity for coordination”, constitutions serve the purposes of
balancing “countless alternative equilibra” in all societies).
15
Ordeshook, id., at 17.
16
Ruth Gavison, What Belongs in a Constitution?, 13(1) CONST. POL. ECON. 89, 96 (2002)
(emphasis in the original).
17
See e.g., Hanna Pitkin, Obligation and Consent – I, 59(4) AM. POL. SCI. REV. 990-991 (1965)
(dismissing constitutional rights as being mere “essays in advocacy” since they end up addressing political
problems that might have become obscure with time); Thomas, M. Scanlon, Human Rights as a Neutral
Concern, in HUMAN RIGHTS AND U.S. FOREIGN POLICY 83-92 (Peter G. Brown et al, eds., 1979)
(contending that constitutional rights are not “fully available to articulation” and that “it is extremely
difficult…to give a coherent statement of any of our familiar rights”, at 84).
18
See Gavison, supra note 16, id. See also Elaine Scarry, On Philosophy and Human Rights, in
DELIBERATIVE DEMOCRACY, supra note 13, 71, 75-76 (demonstrating that the strength of the argument of
the opponents of constitutionalization of human rights never lies in the “justness” or “unjustness” of their
inclusion, but in the fear that “their inclusion will make the new country culturally indebted to the west or
to the north”).
14
7
As De Waal, Currie and Erasmus have argued, beyond strengthening the rule of
law, democratic accountability, separation of powers as well as checks and balances – all
fundamental principles of a constitutional order –
Bill of Rights overrides ordinary law and conduct inconsistent with it. In
addition, subject to considerations of justiciability and constitutional
jurisdiction, the Bill of Rights generates its own set of remedies…At the
same time [it] contains a set of values that must be respected whenever
ordinary law is interpreted, developed or applied. This form of application,
which aims at creating harmony between the Bill of Rights and ordinary
law, is termed the indirect application of the Bill of Rights.19
The 1787 Constitution of the US (together with the subsequent Bill of Rights,
1791)20 has been credited with the pride of being the first written constitution to have an
entrenched bill of rights.21 Today, numerous states across the world have written
constitutions with entrenched bills of rights, all African states inclusive except
Swaziland.
By virtue of its long history of juridical engagement with the interpretive
dynamics of a written constitution and constitutionalized rights, therefore, the influence
of the US judicial system understandably looms large, not the least in the common law
world. Whatever criticisms there may be against the stance of US courts in certain
19
JOHAN DE WAAL, IAIN CURRIE & GERHARD ERASMUS, THE BILL OF RIGHTS HANDBOOK 27
(4th ed. 2001) [hereinafter DE WAAL ET AL].
20
Constitution of the United States of America and Bill of Rights, reprinted in CONSTITUTIONS OF
MODERN STATES: SELECTED TEXTS AND COMMENTARY 207-217 (Leslie Wolf-Phillips, 1968) [hereinafter
CONSTITUTIONS OF MODERN STATES].
21
See BLAUSTEIN, supra note 3 at 4; Nadine Strossen, United States Ratification of the
International Bill of Rights: A Fitting Celebration of the Bicentennial of the U.S. Bill of Rights, 24 U. TOL.
L. REV. 203 (1992). See also Agust Thor Arnason, Constitutionalism: Popular Legitimacy of the State?, in
THE WELFARE STATE AND CONSTITUTIONALISM IN THE NORDIC COUNTRIES 29, 44-45 (Martin Scheinin,
ed., 2001) [THE WELFARE STATE AND CONSTITUTIONALISM] (asserting that “modern constitutionalism
is…the child and the cradle of the independence struggle of the United States”). In his letter to President
James Madison, urging the incorporation of a bill of rights in the U.S. Constitution, Thomas Jefferson had
written, inter alia: “Let me add that a bill of rights is what the people are entitled to against every
government on earth, general or particular, and what no just government should refuse or rest on
inference….” See Thomas Jefferson’s Letter to James Madison, Dec. 20, 1787, quoted in TIMOTHY A.
AGUDA, THE JUDICIARY IN THE GOVERNMENT OF NIGERIA 41 (1983).
8
cases,22 there can be no gainsaying the fact that their tradition of radical constitutional
interpretation impels intellectual scrutiny in a discourse of this nature.
III.
CONSTITUTIONAL INTERPRETATION: COMPARATIVE TRADITIONS AND
INFLUENCES
A constitution is central to a country’s legal system because it defines the principles on
which the system is based. It sets up the most important institutions of government, states
their principal powers and makes broad rules about how those powers are to be exercised.
In several countries, those principles and rules are written down in one documentary
piece and that document is called the constitution. Most modern democracies are thus
characterized by the existence of written constitutions which usually contain the profound
political and social values that determine the structures of governance and legal system.23
The presence of a written constitution has been described as naturally preferable as it
offers a realistic platform for the exercise of judicial review, and the assurance of
separation of powers, checks and balances, and the rule of law.24
It must be borne in mind from the onset that notwithstanding the codification of
the fundamental rules relating to powers, privileges, rights and liabilities in written
constitutions, their contents do not cease to create problems of interpretation for the
judiciary – the organ traditionally assigned the responsibility of constitutional and
For some robust critique of the US Supreme Court’s work in constitutional interpretation, see
Alexander M. Bickel, The Supreme Court, 1960 Term – Forward the Passive Virtues, 75 HARV. L. REV. 40
(1961); MARK TUSHNET, TAKING THE CONSTITUTION AWAY FROM THE COURTS 134-135; 148 (1999); CASS
R. SUNSTEIN, ONE CASE AT A TIME: JUDICIAL MINIMALISM ON THE SUPREME COURT (1999); Gerard J.
Clark, An Introduction to Constitutional Interpretation, Suffolk University Law School Faculty
Publications, Paper 9, 2002, pp. 7-8.
23
Even though Israel, the United Kingdom, New Zealand and Swaziland do not have such single
bodies of codified constitutions, they are nonetheless generally referred to as constitutional states..
24
Andrei Marmour, Constitutional Interpretation, University of Southern California Public Policy
Research Paper No. 04-4 (2004), p. 2; JED RUBENFELD, REVOLUTION BY JUDICIARY: THE STRUCTURE OF
AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW 145-150 (2005).
22
9
judicial review in modern democracies.25 With the supremacy usually preserved by
written constitutions over all other municipal laws; the futuristic and enduring values
entrenched; the rigid posture; their general, abstract, and yet far-reaching contents; and
the normativisation of high ethical values usually couched as bill of rights, all make
constitutional interpretation a distinctively problematic experience for judiciaries.26
While the legitimacy of the powers of judges and the courts to interpret the
Constitution has occupied the minds of many legal critics, it is the manner in which
judges and courts so interpret written constitutions that has generated more prolific
debate. Legal pundits have attempted value-neutral approaches to constitutional
interpretation, ranging from originalism, purposivism, objectivism, to liberal and strict
constructionism.27 To these have been added diverse other labels like grammatical or
literal interpretation, systematic or contextual interpretation, teleological interpretation,
historical interpretation, comparative interpretation, and many others.28 Much scholarly
effort has been devoted to these abstractions and it serves no purpose to revisit them
here.29 Suffice to say, however, that plausible as these approaches and labels might
appear, there remains the challenge of debunking the neutrality of those theories, of
25
See Clark, An Introduction to Constitutional Interpretation, supra note 22, at 9.
Marmour, supra note 24, at 4.
27
For various theories of constitutional interpretation identified in Anglo-American tradition, see
Lourens du Plessis, “Constitutional Interpretation”, at
http://www.chr.up.ac.za/closa/chapters/CLoSA%20Ch%203%20Outline.pdf (last visited Jan. 14, 2011).
28
See Tom O’Connor, “The Jurisprudence of Constitutional Interpretation”, at
http://faculty.ncwc.edu/TOConnor/410/410lect02.htm (last updated 10 March 2007).
29
For some readings on the subject of constitutional interpretation across diverse jurisdictions, see
LAURENCE H. TRIBE & MICHAEL C. DORF, ON READING THE CONSTITUTION (1991); Jeffrey Goldsworthy,
Originalism in Constitutional Interpretation, 25 FED. L. REV. 1 (1997); Jeremy Kirk, Constitutional
Interpretation and a Theory of Evolutionary Originalism, 27 FED. L. REV. 323 (1999); David Tucker,
Textualism: An Australian Evaluation of the Debate between Professor Ronald Dworkin and Justice
Antonin Scalia, 21(4) SYDNEY L. REV. 567-596 (1999); KEITH E. WHITTINGTON, CONSTITUTIONAL
INTERPRETATION: TEXTUAL MEANING, ORIGINAL INTENT, AND JUDICIAL REVIEW 1-14 (1999); PETER
HOGG, CONSTITUTIONAL LAW OF CANADA (2005).
26
10
exposing misleading criticisms, and of articulating effective and accessible methods of
interpretation to give full meaning to the guarantees contained in Constitutions.
While there exist diverse quasi-judicial, non-judicial and inquisitorial bodies
within various national configurations that may implicate constitutional interpretation,30 it
is the role of the judiciary (or court system) that is of critical importance. The evaluation
of the role of the judiciary here should not be construed as a “tendency to judicialize
politics and politicize the judiciary.”31 Although it would be erroneous to confine the
subject of constitutional interpretation to the realm of “judicialism”, 32 the very essence of
adjudication basically imports the concept of judicial review through which the ordinary
law courts exercise their supervisory functions in law ordered societies.33
A legal concept of great antiquity, judicial review has drawn the attention of
numerous exponents as well as critics. It has been the subject of vibrant debates within
divergent domestic jurisdictions and has been the focus of many scholarly treatises.34 The
30
See Mark Tushnet, Constitutional Interpretation Outside the Courts, 37(3) J. INTERDISC. HIST.
415-422 (2007). See also Walter Murphy, Constitutional Interpretation as Constitutional Creation: The
1999-2000 Harry Eckstein Lecture, Centre for the Study of Democracy, University of California, 2000, p. 3
(listing “legislators”, “executive officials”, “police officers”, and “individual voters” as categories of
interpreters of constitutions).
31
Peter Russell, The Political Purposes of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, 61 CAN.
B. REV. 30, 51-52 (1983).
32
See Jackbeth K. Mapulanga-Hulston, Examining the Justiciability of Economic, Social and
Cultural Rights, 6(4) INT’L J. HUM. RTS. 29, 36-37 (2002).
33
See Mary Sarah Bilder, The Corporate Origins of Judicial Review, 116 Yale L.J. 502 (2006 );
Bilder, Mary Sarah, Why We Have Judicial Review, 116 YALE L. J. POCKET Part 215 (2007), available at
http://ssrn.com/abstract=981241. For a historical account of the development of the concept of judicial review
from ancient Athenian times to the present time, see ARNE MAVCIC, THE CONSTITUTIONAL REVIEW 18-22
(2001).
34
It has been empirically demonstrated that the concept of judicial review is now known and
recognized in every state of the modern world that has a court/judicial system. See generally CHARLES
PLATTO, TRIAL AND COURT PROCEDURES WORLDWIDE (1990) (analyzing, through the contributions of
diverse authors, some constitutive elements of judicial review – trial and court procedures – in Australia,
Hong Kong, India, Japan, South Korea, New Zealand, Singapore, Austria, Belgium, U.K., France, Italy, the
Netherlands, Portugal, Spain, Sweden, Switzerland, Argentina, Brazil, Chile, Ecuador, Uruguay, Canada,
Puerto Rico and the US).
11
historical origins, broader contexts and other fine details of this concept have been
adequately covered in a considerable number of works,35 and need not detain us here.
The philosophical and conceptual basis for judicial review lies in the notion that
the regular courts possess the inherent power to strike down a law, to overturn an
executive act, or order a public official to act in a certain manner if they consider such
law or act to be unconstitutional or to be contrary to law in a free and democratic
society.36 While judicial review has indeed been such a time-honored concept, its impact
has been felt more in the sphere of administrative law than in the field of human rights
until relatively recent.37 Today, in various nations and across many jurisdictions of the
world, judicial review is increasingly emerging as a cornerstone of human rights
promotion and protection and has added considerable impetus to human rights
discourses.38
35
See e.g., O. HOOD PHILLIPS, CONSTITUTIONAL AND ADMINISTRATIVE LAW (Sweet & Maxwell,
4th ed. 1967) (describing the classical origins and connotations of the concept in English Law); L ORD
WOOLF ET AL, DE SMITH, WOOLF AND JOWELL’S PRINCIPLES OF JUDICIAL REVIEW (1999) [hereinafter
WOOLF ET AL]; MAURO CAPPELLETTI, JUDICIAL REVIEW IN THE CONTEMPORARY WORLD 45-68 (analyzing
the centralized and decentralized forms of judicial review in modern times from the French, Italian, former
Soviet, U.S., English, and Austrian perspectives); J OHN HART ELY, DEMOCRACY AND DISTRUST (1980)
(giving insight into the U.S. perspective on judicial review as postulated by Chief Justice John Marshall in
Marbury v. Madison, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137 (1803)). For a critical study of the Canadian perspective, see
PATRICK MONAHAN, POLITICS AND THE CONSTITUTION: THE CHARTER, FEDERALISM AND THE SUPREME
COURT OF CANADA (1987). See generally TASLIM O. ELIAS, JUDICIAL PROCESS IN THE NEWER
COMMONWEALTH 179-193 (1990) (discussing the concept of judicial review in the context of the
Commonwealth and highlighting its rationale in the doctrines of Separation of Powers, Rule of Law and
Administrative Justice). See also LEE BRIDGES, JUDICIAL REVIEW IN PERSPECTIVE (2d ed., Cavendish
Publishing, 1995). For an analysis of the Israeli dimension, see Melville B. Nimmer, The Uses of Judicial
Review in Israel’s Quest for a Constitution, 70 COLUM. L. REV. 1217 (1970).
36
See WOOLF ET AL, id., at 3-4. See also DAVID ROBERTSON, A DICTIONARY OF HUMAN RIGHTS
125-126 (1997); Marmour, Constitutional Interpretation, supra note 24, at 11.
37
See generally WOOLF ET AL, supra note 35, at 183-194 (describing the effect of the absence of a
codified human rights system in the U.K. and stressing that even before the advent of the Human Rights
Act of 1998, judicial review related to human rights had been carried out under ordinary common law
rules). See also ANDRAS SAJO, LIMITING GOVERNMENT: AN INTRODUCTION TO CONSTITUTIONALISM 205218 (1999) (connecting the evolution of judicial review processes in U.S., French, British and German
constitutionalism and the restraints on state power from interfering with the rights of citizens).
38
See e.g., MARGARET DEMERIEUX, FUNDAMENTAL RIGHTS IN COMMONWEALTH CARIBBEAN
CONSTITUTIONS 485-499 (1992) (discussing the impact of judicial review in the process of fundamental
human rights protection in the Caribbean states); ROBERT J. SHARPE ET AL, THE CHARTER OF RIGHTS AND
12
Justifying the inevitable intercourse between human rights and judicial review,
Hutchinson and Monahan assert that:
A sensitivity for individual rights might be seen as particularly appropriate
and necessary in contemporary society. Individual life is dominated and
permeated by large and complex bureaucracies, principally the state and
the business corporation. The challenge to individual rights is no longer
the lynch mob crying for blood, but the coolly rational bureaucrat, armed
with spread sheets and cost-benefit studies. Regard for the Rule of
Law…[will] ensure that “social managers” will not trample individuals in
the march toward so-called organizational progress.39
In increasing measures, scholars and jurists across legal orientations and
ideological boundaries have continued to identify judicial review – within the context of
the interpretation of constitutionalized human rights – as a necessary tool for democratic
balance and social justice in the modern society.40
FREEDOMS 18-29 (1998) (analyzing the impact of judicial review in the process of fundamental human
rights protection in Canada); Richard Clayton & Vikram Sachdeva, The Role of Judicial Review in Curing
Breaches of Article 6, (2003) JUD. REV. 90-96 (examining the possible impact of judicial review on fair
trial rights within European jurisdictions).
39
ALLAN C. HUTCHINSON ET AL, THE RULE OF LAW: IDEAL OR IDEOLOGY 97 (1987) [hereinafter
IDEAL OR IDEOLOGY]. See also FRIEDRICH HAYEK, THE ROAD TO SERFDOM 115 (1946) (emphasis added).
See also RONALD DWORKIN, A MATTER OF PRINCIPLE 71 (Reprint ed., Harvard Univ. Press, 1986) (1985)
(asserting that judicial review assures that “the deepest, most fundamental conflicts between individual
[rights] and society [interests] will once, someplace, finally, become questions of justice”). See also
DEMERIEUX, id., at 486 (contending that contrary to “the postulate that in a democratic or majoritarian
political set up, judges who are unelected and unaccountable to the citizenry should not have carte blanche
to negative policy decisions of the representatives of the majority…the existence of a Bill of Rights imports
the existence of judicial review”).
40
See e.g., CAPPELLETTI, supra note 35, at 27 (asserting that “this fundamentally important worldwide movement was effectively begun by the American Constitution of 1789 and its courageous
interpretation by the Supreme Court [starting with Marbury v. Madison]”; THE RULE OF LAW: IDEAL OR
IDEOLOGY, id., at 110 (contemplating that “By forcing the political process to confront the question of
individual rights, public morality will become more reflective and self-critical”); Ernest J. Weinrib, The
Intelligibility of the Rule of Law, in THE RULE OF LAW: IDEAL OR IDEOLOGY, id., at 59; Paul Craig, Formal
and Substantive Conceptions of the Rule of Law: An Analytical Framework, PUB. L. 466, 470-473 (1997)
(contending that judicial review, as an extrapolation from the principle of Rule of Law, is a notion
grounded in legal positivism); David Dyzenhaus, Form and Substance in the Rule of Law: A Democratic
Justification for Judicial Review?, in JUDICIAL REVIEW AND THE CONSTITUTION 141 (Christopher Forsyth,
ed., 2000) (arguing that the substance of the Diceyan principle against arbitrariness engenders “judicial
supremacism” for its efficacy); MARK ELLIOTT, THE CONSTITUTIONAL FOUNDATIONS OF JUDICIAL REVIEW
197, 233 (2001) (discussing judicial review in the context of a rights-based approach to good governance in
the United Kingdom). For yet another view on the remedial dimension of the importance of judicial review
in matters of individual’s rights, see Paul Craig, Ultra Vires and the Foundations of Judicial Review, 57
CAMBRIDGE L. J. 63, 78-79 (1998).
13
Admittedly, in terms of practical experience and scholarship in constitutional
interpretation, the US judiciary represents one of the most remarkable systems with over
two centuries of ever-evolving constitutional dynamics. And no doubt, the arrowhead of
this tradition has been the US Supreme Court. Even though the US Constitution contains
no explicit provision on the function of judicial or constitutional review,41 the US
Supreme Court has, since the decision in Marbury v. Madison,42 positioned itself as the
undisputed final arbiter in matters involving the interpretation of the US Constitution,43
and in maintaining it as “a living Constitution.”44
41
Art. III of the US Constitution simply provides:
Section 1. The judicial power of the United States, shall be vested in one Supreme Court,
and in such inferior courts as the Congress may from time to time ordain and establish.
The judges, both of the supreme and inferior courts, shall hold their offices during good
behaviour, and shall, at stated times, receive for their services, a compensation, which
shall not be diminished during their continuance in office.
Section 2. The judicial power shall extend to all cases, in law and equity, arising under
this Constitution, the laws of the United States, and treaties made, or which shall be
made, under their authority;--to all cases affecting ambassadors, other public ministers
and consuls;--to all cases of admiralty and maritime jurisdiction;--to controversies to
which the United States shall be a party;--to controversies between two or more states;-between a state and citizens of another state;--between citizens of different states;-between citizens of the same state claiming lands under grants of different states, and
between a state, or the citizens thereof, and foreign states, citizens or subjects.
In all cases affecting ambassadors, other public ministers and consuls, and those in which
a state shall be party, the Supreme Court shall have original jurisdiction. In all the other
cases before mentioned, the Supreme Court shall have appellate jurisdiction, both as to
law and fact, with such exceptions, and under such regulations as the Congress shall
make.
The trial of all crimes, except in cases of impeachment, shall be by jury; and such trial
shall be held in the state where the said crimes shall have been committed; but when not
committed within any state, the trial shall be at such place or places as the Congress may
by law have directed.
Section 3. Treason against the United States, shall consist only in levying war against
them, or in adhering to their enemies, giving them aid and comfort. No person shall be
convicted of treason unless on the testimony of two witnesses to the same overt act, or on
confession in open court.
The Congress shall have power to declare the punishment of treason, but no attainder of
treason shall work corruption of blood, or forfeiture except during the life of the person
attainted.
42
5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137 (1803).
43
See Clark, An Introduction to Constitutional Interpretation, supra note 22, at 1; The United
States Supreme Court, “The Court and Constitutional Interpretation”, at
http://www.supremecourtus.gov/about/constitutional.pdf (last visited Jan. 14, 2011). See also Marshall L.
DeRosa, The Ninth Amendment and the Politics of Creative Jurisprudence: Disparaging the Fundamental
14
Little wonder that Alexis de Tocqueville asserted that “the representative system
of government has been adopted in several states of Europe, but I am unaware that any
nation of the globe has hitherto organized a judicial power in the same manner as the
Americans…A more imposing judicial power was never constituted by any people.”45
It must be mentioned that there is hardly any other aspect of US constitutional law
where the above view finds credence than in the interpretation of the provisions of the US
Bill of Rights. Notwithstanding the protracted controversy that continues to surround
many of the proactive decisions of the US Supreme Court,46 the court has, in a long line
of landmark cases demonstrated its capacity to remain proactive where laws clash with
aspirations of liberty, or where governmental action would result in hardship, injustice or
arbitrariness.47
Right of Popular Control 104 (1996) (describing the US Supreme Court as “the loose cannon on the deck of
American federalism”).
44
See Antonin Scalia, Constitutional Interpretation the Old Fashioned Way, Paper presented at the
Woodrow Wilson International Center for Scholars in Washington, D.C., on March 14, 2005, available at
http://www.cfif.org/htdocs/legal_issues/legal_updates/us_supreme_court/scalia-constitutional-speech.htm
(last visited Jan. 14, 2011).. The United States Supreme Court, “The Court and Constitutional
Interpretation”, id.
45
Quoted in The United States Supreme Court, “The Court and Constitutional Interpretation”, id.
46
See, e.g., JESSE H. CHOPPER ET AL, CONSTITUTIONAL LAW: CASES, COMMENTS, QUESTIONS
394- 447 (9th ed. 2001) (analyzing some of the trenchant criticisms against decisions like Roe v. Wade, and
numerous others connected to the “right to privacy”).
47
For various scholarly efforts analyzing the work of the US Supreme Court in these fields, see
WAYNE D. MOORE, CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHTS AND POWERS OF THE PEOPLE (1996); WALTER F. MURPHY
ET AL, AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONAL INTERPRETATION (3rd ed., 2003); GORDON SILVERSTEIN, IMBALANCE
OF POWERS: CONSTITUTIONAL INTERPRETATION AND THE MAKING OF AMERICAN FOREIGN POLICY (2006);
Walter F. Pratt, A New Vocabulary for a New Constitutional Law: United States v. Carolene Products, in
LEADING CASES OF THE TWENTIETH CENTURY 125 (Eoin O’Dell ed., 2000). See also Clark, An
Introduction to Constitutional Interpretation, supra note 22, at 7-8. Some of the cases where the U.S.
judiciary has made ‘positive’ mark as an ‘activist’ institution on social policy include United States v.
Carolene Products, 304 U.S. 144 (1938); Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U.S. 483 (1954); NAACP v.
Alabama, 357 U.S. 888 (1958); NAACP v. Button, 371 U.S. (1963); Miranda v. Arizona, 384 U.S. 436
(1966) (on procedural safeguards in criminal matters); Goldberg v. Kelly, 397 U.S. 254 (1970); San
Antonio Independent Sch. Dist. v. Rodriguez, 411 U.S. 1 (1973); United States v. SCRAP, 412 U.S. 669
(1973); and Milliken v. Bradley II, 433 U.S. 267 (1977). For scholarly discussions on the notable activist
periods of the U.S. Supreme Court, see KENNETH M. HOLLAND, JUDICIAL ACTIVISM IN COMPARATIVE
PERSPECTIVE 20-28 (1991). See also STEVEN D. SMITH, THE CONSTITUTION AND THE PRIDE OF REASON
(1998); AKHIL REED AMAR, THE BILL OF RIGHTS: CREATION AND RECONSTRUCTION (1998); THOMAS B.
MCAFFEE, INHERENT RIGHTS, THE WRITTEN CONSTITUTION, AND POPULAR SOVEREIGNTY (2000); Jesse H.
15
Rather than cataloguing the prolific achievements of the US Supreme Court in
general terms, however, what is immediately relevant to the present essay is the influence
it has wrought in other jurisdictions of the world in a specific and narrow aspect of
constitutional interpretation: the notion of unenumerated rights.
IV.
UNENUMERATED RIGHTS: A SURVEY OF JURISPRUDENCE AND
SCHOLARSHIP
In written constitutions generally, the corpus of human rights for which an individual
may seek judicial interpretation, protection and enforcement are usually couched in
ascertainable form.48 From a commonsensical perspective, therefore, whatever is not
explicitly contained in a written constitution should not belong in or be read into it. This
has been the viewpoint of judges and scholars of the positivism school of thought in
various ages and climes. Placed within the framework of constitutional rights, any right
not expressly conferred by a constitution cannot and should not warrant enforcement. In
Barnett’s analysis of this viewpoint, “judges should only do what they are qualified to do
and that is enforce ‘the rule laid down’ [since] they have no particular expertise to
identify fundamental rights the content of which is not provided to them by an
authoritative source.”49
The foregoing represents the point of sharp divergence among originalists and
non-originalists. To originalists, a constitution’s meaning must be that as understood by
Chopper, Consequences of Supreme Court Decisions Upholding Individual Constitutional Rights, 83 MICH.
L. REV. 1 (1984); Clark, An Introduction to Constitutional Interpretation, supra note 22, at 11-13.
48
See generally Marmour, supra note 24, at 24; James A Thomson, An Australian Bill of Rights:
Glorious Promises, Concealed Dangers, 19(4) MELB. U. L. REV. 1020 (1994); Timothy H. Jones, Legal
Protection for Fundamental Rights and Freedoms: European Lessons for Australia?, 22(1) FED. L. REV.
57 (1994).
49
Randy E. Barnett, “Who’s Afraid of Unenumerated Rights?”, Working Paper Series, Public
Law & Legal Theory Working Paper No. 06-02, 2002, p. 13 [hereinafter Barnett, Who’s Afraid?]. See also
ROBERT H. BORK, THE TEMPTING OF AMERICA: THE POLITICAL SEDUCTION OF THE LAW 264 (1991)
(contending that legal reasoning must “begin with a body of rules or principles or major premises that are
independent of the judge’s preferences”).
16
the public at the time of its making and that if the meaning is not so fixed, the law,
government, individual rights will be unpredictable, arbitrary and rendered susceptible to
the subjective views of the courts. Conversely, non-originalists contend that a
constitution’s meaning must manifest changing societal values and demands, and that if
its meaning does not so evolve, society will be subjected to archaic values that cannot
respond to current social challenges.50
Since the discussion of constitutional interpretation in this essay is located within
the context of unenumerated human rights, an effort is made at this juncture to examine
how different judiciaries have responded to this notion.
A.
United States
As already mentioned, because of the paucity of the provisions of the US
Constitution, and of course, its Bill of Rights, the necessity had arisen over the ages for
the courts, nay the US Supreme Court, to interpret the constitution in ways that would
make it respond to radical changes in social values and dynamics.
Over the course of the last two hundred years, the fount of this judicial
engagement has been the provisions of the Ninth and Tenth Amendments of the US
Constitution. It will be worthwhile to reproduce them at this juncture.
The Ninth Amendment provides:
The enumeration in the Constitution, of certain rights, shall not be
construed to deny or disparage others retained by the people.
The Tenth Amendment in turn provides:
50
See Richard Kay, Adherence to the Original Intentions in Constitutional Adjudication: Three
Objections and Responses, NORTHWESTERN U. L. REV. 251-253 (1988); ANTONIN SCALIA, A MATTER OF
INTERPRETATION: FEDERAL COURTS AND THE LAW (1997); Randy E. Barnett, An Originalism for NonOriginalists, 45(4) LOYOLA L. REV. 620, 633-649 (1999).
17
The powers not delegated to the United States by the Constitution, nor
prohibited by it to the states, are reserved to the states respectively, or to
the people.
To these is naturally added the Privileges and Immunities Clause of the
Fourteenth Amendment, namely,
No state shall make or enforce any law which shall abridge the privileges
or immunities of citizens of the United States….
While there had been early skepticism and confusion about the notion of
unenumerated rights in US constitutionalism,51 it was the embrace of Blackstone’s
interpretation of sovereignty as well as the Austinian idea of positivism leading American
statesmen and commentators that had fuelled the suppression and antagonism to
elaborating the corpus of unenumerated rights.52 Wendell Phillips had located this
positivist antagonism to unenumerated rights on the premises of majoritarian sovereignty.
In his words:
There can be no more self-evident proposition, than that, in every
Government, the majority must rule, and their will be uniformly obeyed.
Now, if the majority enact a wicked law, and the Judge refuses to enforce
it, which is to yield, the Judge or the majority? Of course, the first. On any
other supposition, Government is impossible.53
St. George Tucker, an eminent Virginian scholar and jurist, had sought to validate
the linkage between unenumerated governmental powers and unenumerated rights in
those provisions as follows:
51
See generally BLACKSTONE’S COMMENTARIES: WITH NOTES OF REFERENCE TO THE
CONSTITUTION AND LAWS OF THE FEDERAL GOVERNMENT OF THE UNITED STATES; AND OF THE
COMMONWEALTH OF VIRGINIA app. 1, at 307-308 (St. George Tucker ed., Augustus M. Kelley, 1969)
(1803) [hereinafter TUCKER, BLACKSTONE’S COMMENTARIES]; Barnett, Who’s Afraid?, supra note 49, at
2-3; Thomas McAffee, Federalism and the Protection of Rights: The Modern Ninth Amendment’s
Spreading Confusion, BYU L. REV. 351 (1996).
52
Barnett, id., at 9-11. But see JOHN TAYLOR, CONSTRUCTION CONSTRUED, AND CONSTITUTIONS
VINDICATED 25 (1820) (condemning the notion of “sovereignty” as an unknown “word [that has] crept into
[US] political dialect”].
53
WENDELL PHILLIPS, REVIEW OF LYSANDER SPOONER’S ESSAY ON THE UNCONSTITUTIONALITY
OF SLAVERY 10 (1847) (reprint edition 1969).
18
All powers of the federal government being either expressly enumerated,
or necessary and proper to the execution of some enumerated power; and
it being one of the rules of construction which sound reason has adopted;
that as exception strengthens the force of a law in cases not excepted, so
enumeration weakens it, in cases not enumerated; it follows, as a regular
consequence, that every power which concerns the right of the citizen
must be construed strictly, where it may operate to infringe or impair his
liberty; and liberally, and for his benefit, where it may operate to his
security and happiness, the avowed object of the constitution.54
Compounding the hazy profile of unenumerated rights was the judicial
ambivalence and uncertainty of US judges of that era. This scenario played out in Calder
v. Bull,55 where Justice Chase had affirmed the possibility of invalidating laws and
powers that violate rights not enumerated in the US Bill of Rights. 56 Even though Justice
Iredell had concurred with Chase in that decision, he had, a decade earlier, been a
committed protagonist of unenumerated rights. In defending the failure of the
Constitution of North Carolina to enumerate rights, Iredell had vehemently argued that:
It would not only be useless, but dangerous, to enumerate a number of
rights which are not intended to be given up; because it would be
implying, in the strongest manner, that every right not included in the
exception might be impaired by the government without usurpation; and it
would be impossible to enumerate every one. Let any one make what
collection or enumeration of rights he pleases, I will immediately mention
twenty or thirty more rights not contained in it.57
In a number of judicial decisions, the US Supreme Court had alluded to the
substantive implications of the Ninth and Tenth Amendments, albeit without settling the
philosophical and conceptual questions arising from them.58 The uncertainty came to a
54
TUCKER, BLACKSTONE’S COMMENTARIES, supra note 51, id.
3 U.S. 386 (1798).
56
Id., 877-878.
57
THE DEBATES IN THE SEVERAL STATE CONSTITUTIONS ON THE ADOPTION OF THE FEDERAL
CONSTITUTION 167 (Jonathan Elliot ed., 2d. ed. 1836) (James Iredell, North Carolina Ratifying Convention,
Tuesday, July 29, 1788), quoted in Barnett, Who’s Africa?, supra note 49, at 5.
58
See, for example, Loan Ass’n v. Topeka, 87 U.S. (20 Wall.) 655, 662 -63 (1875); Ashwander v.
TVA, 297 U.S. 288, 300 - 11 (1936); Tennessee Electric Power Co. v. TVA, 306 U.S. 118, 143 -44 (1939);
United Public Workers v. Mitchell, 330 U.S. 75, 94 -95 (1947).
55
19
head in Griswold v. Connecticut,59 a celebrated decision on the right to privacy which is
not listed in the US Bill of Rights, where Justice Arthur Goldberg had lucidly established
the basis of unenumerated rights in the following words:
The language and history of the Ninth Amendment reveal that the Framers
of the Constitution believed that there are additional fundamental rights,
protected from governmental infringement, which exist alongside those
fundamental rights specifically mentioned in the first eight constitutional
amendments...To hold that a right so basic and fundamental and so deeprooted in our society as the right of privacy in marriage may be infringed
because that right is not guaranteed in so many words by the first eight
amendments to the Constitution is to ignore the Ninth Amendment and to
give it no effect whatsoever. Moreover, a judicial construction that this
fundamental right is not protected by the Constitution because it is not
mentioned in explicit terms by one of the first eight amendments or
elsewhere in the Constitution would violate the Ninth Amendment...Nor
do I mean to state that the Ninth Amendment constitutes an independent
source of rights protected from infringement by either the States or the
Federal Government. Rather, the Ninth Amendment shows a belief of the
Constitution’s authors that fundamental rights exist that are not expressly
enumerated in the first eight amendments and an intent that the list of
rights included there not be deemed exhaustive.60
The Connecticut statute prohibiting the use of contraceptives was consequently
voided as an infringement of the right of marital privacy. The reasoning in Griswold has
found adumbration in a bevy of other cases where the right to privacy, not mentioned
anywhere in the US Constitution has been recognized and enforced.61
What, then, is the whole essence of ‘unenumerated rights’ in the provisions of the
topical Amendments to the US Constitution? Lund proffers a navigational aid in this
foggy terrain:
[T]he…Amendments together serve as an emphatic reminder that the
Constitution was designed so as to protect a vast number of unenumerated
59
381 U.S. 479 (1965).
Id. at 488, 491, 492.
61
See, e.g., Katz v. United States, 389 U.S. 347 (1967) (right to protection from unreasonable
searches and seizures); Loving v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1 (1967) (right to marry); Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113
(1973) (right of abortion); Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003) (right to sexual privacy).
60
20
rights from infringement by the federal government, namely all those
rights that the federal government is not authorized to abridge in the
exercise of its enumerated powers. Some of them may be natural rights,
some are positive rights established by state law, and some are political
rights exercised in the course of establishing state law.62
Contrary to the initial reluctance towards unenumerated rights, therefore, US
jurists are showing increasing interest in them, extending the scope of rights intrinsically
covered. Jon Roland, Founder and President of the Constitution Society, had in his
seminal essay posited that the body of unenumerated rights under US constitutionalism
covers thirteen categories of rights including right to “recordation of public acts and
disclosure of records”; to complete and accurate reports of revenues and expenditures;
and the right to travel.63 Others have strongly argued that these rights also cover self
defense and gun ownership.64 The US judiciary has also established the existence of a
right to welfare assistance for the indigent;65 offered succor to the illegitimate child;66 and
protection for the mentally ill.67
While the notion of unenumerated rights has received considerable attention in
the US, its philosophical and moral appeal has also engendered somewhat passionate
responses, for and against, in other jurisdictions. Although not usually discussed or
applied as direct adoption of the US notion of unenumerated rights, the idea manifests in
62
Nelson Lund, A Constitutional Right to Self Defense?, George Mason University Law and
Economics Research Paper Series 06-29, p. 6.
63
Jon Roland, “Presumption of Nonauthority and Unenumerated Rights”, at
http://www.constitution.org/9ll/schol/pnur.htm#sdendnote4anc (last visited Jan. 14, 2011).
64
See Robert E. Shalhope, The Armed Citizen in the Early Republic, 49 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS.
125, 128 (1986); Nicholas J. Johnson, Beyond The Second Amendment: An Individual Right to Arms
Viewed Through the Ninth Amendment, 24 RUTGERS L.J. 1, 64-70 (1992); Nelson Lund & John O.
McGinnis, Lawrence v. Texas and Judicial Hubris, 102 MICH. L. REV. 1555, 1590-93 (2004).
65
Shapiro v. Thompson, 394 U.S. 618 (1969).
66
Levy v. Louisiana, 391 U.S. 68 (1968).
67
City of Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Centers, 473 U.S. 432 (1985). For a recent scholarly
compilation of topical cases arising from the corpus unenumerated rights in the US, see C HARLES O.
PRINCE, PURPOSE OF THE NINTH AMENDMENT TO THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES: PROTECTING
UNENUMERATED RIGHTS (2005).
21
the course of interpreting the constitutions of diverse Anglophone states.68 While there
might be more than one reason for this scenario, it however appears that the following
statement of Canadian Supreme Court Justice Claire L’Heureux-Dubé captures the
picture in convincing light:
As the bonds of colonialism loosened, the prominence of American
jurisprudence grew throughout the world. This is particularly true in the
field of constitutionalism and human rights. The very concept of judicial
review of legislation in accordance with guaranteed rights originated in the
U.S. Supreme Court, in the classic case of Marbury v. Madison.69
The scenario of unenumerated rights therefore manifests in two ways: in countries
with constitutions “written in language which is brief, sometimes obscure and usually
ambiguous.”70 Australia and Canada, with their very old constitutions (1901 and 1867,
respectively), fall in this rank. The other mode is in countries with certain constitutional
guarantees that are essentially human rights provisions but which are excluded from
enforceability. India, Nigeria, and numerous African states of the neo-Nigerian
constitutional model belong in this category.71 It will be worthwhile to examine these
manifestations in some detail.
B.
Australia
See generally Michael D. Kirby, International Law – The Impact on National Constitutions,
Grotius Lecture, April 2005 (on file with author), pp. 8-14 (attempting to explain the historical context of
constitutionalism and constitutional interpretation in English-speaking states).
69
Claire L’Heureux-Dubé, The Importance of Dialogue: Globalization and the International
Impact of the Rehnquist Court, 34 TULSA L. J. 15, 18 (1998).
70
Michael Kirby, Constitutional Interpretation and Original Intent: A Form of Ancestor Worship,
24 MELB. U. L. REV. 1-2 (2000).
71
I have explained the neo-Nigerian constitutional paradigm elsewhere. See ’Dejo Olowu, Human
Rights and the Avoidance of Domestic Implementation: The Phenomenon of Non-Justiciable Constitutional
Guarantees, 69(1) SASK. L. REV. 39, 57 and accompanying note 74.
68
22
It is now beyond polemics that there exists a comparative linkage between the
Australian and US Constitutions, at least in terms of their interpretative dynamics.72 An
eminent Australian scholar, Craven, had actually argued that
The originalism debate in the United States has largely been fought over
the interpretation of the Bill of Rights, with its broad, sweeping guarantees
of fundamental human rights. It is in this highly emotive context, the
stalking-ground of rights to abortion and to freedom from racial
discrimination, that the performance of the Supreme Court has been
vilified or defended according to the stance of commentators upon the
question of original intent. The Australian Constitution does not include a
bill of rights, and so the High Court has not been called upon to deploy its
interpretative armory in so controversial a field.73
However, Craven’s contention would appear outdated. Even though Australian
Constitution does not have a Bill of Rights, the Australian judiciary, represented by the
High Court, has been actively engaged in rights-based constitutional interpretation work.
The anchor of the Australian High Court’s forays has been the robust application of the
principle of legality, a well-established concept in English common law. Lord Hoffman
explained the rationale and essence of the principle vis-à-vis the protection of
unenumerated rights this way:
The principle of legality means that Parliament must squarely confront
what it is doing and accept the political costs. Fundamental rights cannot
be overridden by general or ambiguous words. This is because there is too
great a risk that the full implications of their unqualified meaning may
have passed unnoticed in the democratic process. In the absence of
express language or necessary implication to the contrary, the courts
therefore presume that even the most general words were intended to be
subject to the basic rights of the individual. In this way the courts of the
United Kingdom, though acknowledging the sovereignty of Parliament,
apply principles of constitutionality little different from those which exist
72
Id. Another seminal work in this regard is Rebecca Lefler, A Comparison of Comparison: The
Use of Foreign Case Law as Persuasive Authority by the United States Supreme Court, the Supreme Court
of Canada, and the High Court of Australia, 11 S. CAL. INTERDISC. L.J. 165 (2001).
73
Greg Craven, Original Intent and the Australian Constitution – Coming Soon to a Court Near
You ?, 1 PUB. L. REV. 166, 169 (1990).
23
in countries where the power of the legislature is expressly limited by a
constitutional document.74
This principle has been adopted and applied with approval by Chief Justice
Gleeson of Australia;75 Chief Justice Elias of New Zealand;76 Justice Kirby;77 and Justice
Tipping.78 The principle has steadily evolved into the bedrock of constitutional
interpretation in Australia and New Zealand.79
In a country without a Bill of Rights, the principle of legality has become a tool of
establishing separation of powers, rule of law and the protection of human rights in
Australia. It has also helped in formulating ascertainable presumptions against any
exercise of governmental powers. Among some of the established presumptions based on
this principle are that it will never be the intention of the Parliament:
(a) to invade fundamental rights, freedoms and immunities;80
(b) to restrict access to the courts;81
(c) to exclude the right to claims of self-incrimination;82
(d) to deny procedural fairness to persons affected by the exercise of public
power;83
R v. Sec’y of State for Home Dep’t, Ex parte Simms (2002) 2 A.C. 115, 131.
See MURRAY GLEESON, THE RULE OF LAW AND THE CONSTITUTION 2, 5 (The Boyler Lectures,
ABC Books, 2000); Al-Kateb v. Godwin (2004) 208 A.L.R. 124 at para. 19; Electrolux Home Products Pty
Ltd. v. Australian Workers Union (2003) 209 A.L.R. 116 at para. 21, 23.
76
See R v. Pora [2001] 2 N.Z.L.R. 37, para. 53.
77
See Daniels Corp’n v. ACCC [2002] 213 C.L.R. 543, 582.
78
See R v. Pora [2001] 2 N.Z.L.R. 37 at para. 53.
79
See Dan Meagher, Guided By Voices? - Constitutional Interpretation on the Gleeson Court, 7
DEAKIN L. REV. 261 (2002).
80
See Potter v. Minahan (1908) 7 C.L.R. 277, 304; R v. Bolton; Ex parte Beane (1987) 162 C.L.R.
514, 523, 532; Bropho v. Western Australia (1990) 171 C.L.R. 1; Coco v. The Queen (1994) 179 C.L.R.
427, 437; Al-Kateb, supra note 75, at paras. 19, 150; Minister v. Al Masri (2003) 197 A.L.R. 241, paras.
82-85.
81
Magrath v. Goldsborough Mort & Co Ltd (1932) 47 C.L.R. 121, 134.
82
Pyneboard Pty Ltd. v. Trade Practices Comm’n (1983) 152 C.L.R. 328; Rich v. ASIC (2004) 78
A.L.J.R. 1354.
83
Comm’r of Police v. Tanos (1958) 98 C.L.R. 363, 395-396.
74
75
24
(e) to interfere with vested property rights,84 or to alienate property without
compensation;85 or
(f) to interfere with equality of religion.86
Following the growing acceptance of this principle, therefore, in Australian
Broad. Corp. v. Lenah Game Meats (Lenah Meats),87 for example, Justice Callinan stated
that he disagreed with the unanimous decision in Lange v. Australian Broad. Comm’n,88
and proceeded to confirm the existence of an implied constitutional freedom of political
communication in Australia. It is noteworthy that the Australian High Court has already
extracted some other unenumerated rights from the separation of judicial power effected
by the Constitution of the Australian Commonwealth.89
C.
Ireland
Even though the Republic of Ireland has a written constitution containing a bill of
rights, it could not avoid judicial engagement with the subject of unenumerated rights in
the course of interpretative activities. The Irish judiciary had introduced the notion of
unenumerated rights into Irish constitutional jurisprudence when the court was called
upon in 1965 to decide on a claim to the right to bodily integrity under Article 40(3)(1) of
84
Clissold v. Perry (1904) 1 C.L.R. 363, 373; Clunies Ross v. The C’wealth (1984) 155 C.L.R.
193, 199-200.
85
C’wealth v. Haseldell Ltd. (1918) 25 C.L.R. 552, 563; Durham Holdings (2001) 205 C.L.R.
399, paras. 28-31.
86
Canterbury Mun. Council v. Muslim Alawy Soc’y Ltd. (1985) 1 N.S.W.L.R. 525, 544 per
McHugh, JA.
87
Lenah Meats (2002) 185 A.L.R. 1, 97.
88
(1997) 189 C.L.R. 520.
89
For scholarly discussions on rights emanating from judicial interpretation of the separation of
powers in the Australian Constitution, see George Winterton, The Separation of Judicial Power as an
Implied Bill of Rights, in FUTURE DIRECTIONS IN AUSTRALIAN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW 185 (Geoffrey
Lindell, ed., 1994); GEORGE WILLIAMS, HUMAN RIGHTS UNDER THE AUSTRALIAN CONSTITUTION, ch. 9
(1999).
25
the Irish Constitution, 1937 (Bunreacht na hÉireann), in the case of Ryan v. Att’y Gen.90
It will be apt to reproduce the critical content of the said Article 40.
Article 40 Personal Rights
….
(3.1) The State guarantees in its laws to respect, and, as far as practicable,
by its laws to defend and vindicate the personal rights of the citizen.
(3.2) The State shall, in particular, by its laws protect as best it may from
unjust attack and, in the case of injustice done, vindicate the life, person,
good name, and property rights of every citizen.
Rather than define this novel right to bodily integrity, Justice Kenny proclaimed
that the origins of unenumerated rights were to be found in the “Christian and Democratic
nature of the [Irish] State.”91 Even though on appeal the Supreme Court had considered
Justice Kenny’s view as too narrow,92 the apex court had demonstrated in later cases that
the “personal rights” of life, good name and property enumerated in the Irish Constitution
of 1937 were inexhaustive.93
Both Justice Kenny, who introduced the concept of unenumerated rights into Irish
constitutionalism as well as the Supreme Court that glossed over his natural law
justification for them have been subjected to robust criticism.94 Hogan decries the notion
90
(1965) I.R. 294.
Id., at 311.
92
Id., at 312.
93
See, for example, T.D. v. Minister for Education, Ireland & Ors [2001] 4 I. R. 259; D.P.P. v.
MS and the Att’y Gen. [2003] I. R. 606, per Keane, C.J., at 619. For a scholarly assessment of the posture
of the Irish Supreme Court on unenumerated rights in these cases, see Orlaith Molloy, Unenumerated
Constitutional Rights: The Current Problematic Position, 3 GALWAY STUD. L. REV. 208, 219-220 (2007);
Nicola Daly, Unenumerated Rights Reconsidered, 3 GALWAY STUD. L. REV. 224, 225 (2007).
94
See, e.g., Molloy, id., 211 (criticizing the Irish Supreme Court for its “heavy emphasis on
Catholic teaching and Christianity in the High Court verdict”); Lesch Bodnik, Bringing Ireland Up To Par:
Incorporating the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms,
26 FORDHAM INT’L L. J. 396, 425 (2002-2003) (criticizing the Supreme Court for the decision in McGee);
Gerard N. Casey, Are there Unenumerated Rights in the Irish Constitution?, 23 IRISH L. TIMES 123 (2005)
(criticizing the analogical reasoning drawn from US Constitution to the Irish Constitution as unwarranted
since the latter is bereft of any provision to the effect of the US Ninth Amendment).
91
26
of unenumerated rights as “practically tantamount to an open invitation to the judiciary to
become later day philosopher kings via the guise of Constitutional interpretation.”95
Nevertheless, more than four decades after its inception in Ireland, the sustained
application of the concept has vindicated Doolan’s submission that its discovery was
“one of the most innovative features of [Irish] Constitutional law.”96 Ample judicial
decisions and scholarly pronouncements lend credence to this assertion.
In Macauley v. Minister of Posts and Telegraph,97 the plaintiff had argued that the
fact that the fiat of the Attorney-General was necessary before proceedings could be
initiated by a citizen against a Minister, whereas a Minister could institute proceedings
against a citizen without obtaining such a fiat, constituted an impermissible inequality as
between a Minister and a citizen. The plaintiff failed in his equality argument but
succeeded on the basis that his unenumerated constitutional right of access to the courts
had been infringed.
Similarly, the Irish judiciary had in 1974 extended the scope of unenumerated
rights to cover the protection of the unborn child. In McGee v. Att’y General,98 Justice
Walsh had applied the unenumerated right of the unborn child to restrict another
unenumerated right – to marital privacy. In his words:
Any action on the part of either the husband and wife or of the state to
limit family sizes by endangering or destroying human life must
necessarily not only be an offence against the common good but also
against the guaranteed personal rights of the human life in question.99
G.W. Hogan, Unenumerated Personal Rights: Ryan’s Case Re-Evaluated, 23 IRISH JURIST 95,
110. See also Michelle Daly, The Separation of Powers: A Means to An End or An End in Itself?, 3
GALWAY STUD. L. REV. 239, 241-243 (2007) (arguing that the tendency towards unenumerated rights was
an anathema to separation of powers).
96
BRIAN DOOLAN, CONSTITUTIONAL LAW & CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHTS IN IRELAND 152 (1994).
97
(1966) I.R. 345.
98
[1974] I.R. 284.
99
Id., at 312.
95
27
Whether by statute or by policy, there is no longer any iota of doubt that the
unborn child is guaranteed full protection under the Irish Constitution. What more?
Beyond the Ryan decision, several rights as diverse as the right to communicate;100 and
the right to earn a living,101 have been located within the realm of “personal rights” under
Article 40(3) of the Irish Constitution.
It is also important to note that even though Irish Constitution does not recognize
socio-economic rights in justiciable form, the Directive Principles of Social Policy
contained in Article 45 of the Constitution have presented the courts with opportunity to
define the content and scope of unenumerated rights. In Murtagh Properties v. Cleary,102
the right to earn a living was premised on the content of Article 45.103 An Irish scholar
Att’y General v. Paperlink [1984] I. L. R. M. 373.
Cafolla v. O’Malley [1985] I. R. 486.
102
[1972] I. R. 330.
103
Art. 45, IR. CONSTITUTION, provides:
[Chapter XIII] Directive principles of social policy
Article 45 [Social Policy]
(0) The principles of social policy set forth in this article are intended for the general
guidance of Parliament. The application of those principles in the making of laws shall be
the care of Parliament exclusively, and shall not be cognisable by any Court under any of
the provisions of this Constitution.
(1) The State shall strive to promote the welfare of the whole people by securing and
protecting as effectively as it may a social order in which justice and charity shall inform
all the institutions of the national life.
(2) The State shall, in particular, direct its policy towards securing:
(i) That the citizens (all of whom, men and women equally, have the right to an adequate
means of livelihood) may through their occupations find the means of making reasonable
provision for their domestic needs.
(ii) That the ownership and control of the material resources of the community may be so
distributed amongst private individuals and the various classes as best to serve the
common good.
(iii) That, especially, the operation of free competition shall not be allowed so to develop
as to result in the concentration of the ownership or control of essential commodities in a
few individuals to the common detriment.
(iv) That in what pertains to the control of credit the constant and predominant aim shall
be the welfare of the people as a whole.
(v) That there may be established on the land in economic security as many families as in
the circumstances shall be practicable.
(3.1) The State shall favor and, where necessary, supplement private initiative in industry
and commerce.
100
101
28
has strongly contended that Article 45 holds the ace in resolving the polarization among
those in favor or against unenumerated rights in Ireland.104
In the other manifestation of judicial recognition of unenumerated rights, written
constitutions do exist, with elaborate human rights provisions (bill of rights), albeit
tainted with a genre of provisions usually tagged ‘Directive Principles’, among which the
Indian version stands out in the developing world.105 And since these constitutional
provisions now variously known across Africa as Fundamental Objectives or Directive
Principles were not original to Africa, I must delve into their earliest frameworks for
proper understanding of the subject, in this instance, the Indian Constitution.
D.
India
Part III of the Indian Constitution of 1950106 sets out “Fundamental Rights”
encompass the right to equality;107 the rights to freedom of speech, expression, assembly,
(3.2) The State shall endeavor to secure that private enterprise shall be so conducted as to
ensure reasonable efficiency in the production and distribution of goods and as to protect
the public against unjust exploitation.
(4.1) The State pledges itself to safeguard with especial care the economic interests of the
weaker sections of the community, and, where necessary, to contribute to the support of
the infirm, the widow, the orphan, and the aged.
(4.2) The State shall endeavor to ensure that the strength and health of workers, men and
women, and the tender age of children shall not be abused and that citizens shall not be
forced by economic necessity to enter avocations unsuited to their sex, age or strength.
104
See Donal Small, Ryan v. AG, A Bottomless Pit of Rights? – A Proposal for Reform, 2 GALWAY
STUD. L. REV. 40, 48-50 (2003).
105
Even though such provisions had been included in I R. CONST., 1937 (Directive Principles of
Social Policy, art. 45); MYAN. CONST., 1947 (Directive Principles of State Policy, arts. 32-44); INDONESIAN
CONST., 1951; NEPAL CONST., 1962 (Directive Principles and Policies of the State, pt. IV, arts 24-26); and
SRI LANKA CONST., 1972 (Directive Principles of State Policy and Fundamental Duties, ch. VI, arts. 2729), it was the Indian Constitution of 1950 that provided the model for their first African transplant: the
Nigerian Constitution of 1979. See generally Ahmed D. Yahaya, The Party System and the Nigerian Polity,
in ISSUES IN THE NIGERIAN DRAFT CONSTITUTION 81(Suleiman Kumo et al, eds., 1977) [hereinafter K UMO
ET AL] (showing that the Indian Constitution entirely appealed to Nigeria because “the spirit of the
Constitution entrenched the notion of India’s dignity and desire to assert its independence”).
106
INDIA CONST., adopted Nov. 26, 1949 (entered into force Jan. 26, 1950), amended by
Constitution (Sixty-sixth) Amendment Act, 1990, June 7, 1990, reprinted in NANDI KHANNA,
CONSTITUTIONAL LAW AND HISTORY OF GOVERNMENT OF INDIA ACT, 1935 AND THE CONSTITUTION OF
INDIA 931-1130 (1992).
107
Arts. 14-18.
29
association, movement and choice of work;108 criminal procedural rights;109 the right to
life and personal liberty; 110 the right against exploitation;111 the right to freedom of
religion;112 minority rights;113 and the right to constitutional remedies.114
In Part IV of the Constitution, there is a cluster of “Directive Principles of State
Policy” dealing with such issues as adequate means of livelihood; fair distribution of
material resources; equal pay for equal work; health and strength of all citizens; child
development;115 equal justice and free legal aid;116 functional village arrangement;117
right to work, to education and to public assistance in certain cases;118 provision of just
and humane conditions of work and maternity relief;119 living wage and fair conditions of
work for workers;120 participation of workers in industrial management;121 uniform civil
code for citizens;122 provision of free and compulsory education for children;123
promotion of educational and economic interests of weaker sections of society; 124 duty of
the State to raise the level of nutrition and the standard of living; 125 organization of
agriculture and animal husbandry;126 environmental protection and improvement;127
108
Art. 19(a)-(g).
Arts. 20 and 22.
110
Art. 21.
111
Arts. 23-24.
112
Arts. 25-28.
113
Arts. 29-30.
114
Arts. 32-35.
115
Art. 39.
116
Art. 39A.
117
Art. 40.
118
Art. 41.
119
Art. 42.
120
Art. 43.
121
Art. 43A.
122
Art. 44.
123
Art. 45.
124
Art. 46.
125
Art. 47.
126
Art. 48.
127
Art. 48A.
109
30
protection of monuments, places and objects of national importance; 128 separation of
judiciary from executive;129 and the promotion of international peace and security.130
The summary of the provisions of Part IV can be found in Article 38 that says:
(1) The State shall strive to promote the welfare of the people by securing
and protecting as effectively as it may a social order in which justice,
social, economic and political, shall inform all the institutions of national
life.
(2) The State shall, in particular, strive to minimize the inequalities in
income, and endeavor to eliminate inequalities in status, facilities and
opportunities, not only amongst individuals but also amongst groups of
people residing in different areas or engaged in different vocations.
Article 37 however expresses the non-justiciable status of those provisions as
follows: “The provisions contained in this Part shall not be enforceable by any court, but
the principles therein laid down are nevertheless fundamental in the governance of the
country and it shall be the duty of the State to apply these principles in making laws.”
The reduction of those provisions into non-justiciable claims had been the product
of the protracted political intrigues that beleaguered India during its transition period. As
constitutional historian Glanville Austin notes:
Although the Fundamental Rights and Directive Principles appear in the
Constitution as distinct entities, it was the [Constituent] Assembly that
separated them; the leaders of the Independence Movement had drawn no
distinction between the positive and negative obligations of the State. Both
types of rights had developed as a common demand, products of the
national and social revolutions, of their almost inseparable intertwining,
and of the character of Indian politics itself.131
Austin is not alone in the assertion that those provisions were originally meant to
be justiciable. As Indian human rights scholar Narively writes, “[t]he prevailing
128
Art. 49.
Art. 50.
130
Art. 51.
131
GLANVILLE AUSTIN, THE INDIAN CONSTITUTION: CORNERSTONE OF A NATION 52 (Oxford
129
1999).
31
sentiment in the [Indian national] Sub-Committee [on Fundamental Rights and to the
Constituent Assembly] was in favor of formulating all rights, including those that later on
became the directive principles of state policy, with legal enforceability.”132
Another scholar of the Indian Constitution had explained the essence of the
Directive Principles as follows:
The principal object in enacting the directive principles was to set
standards of achievement before the legislature and the executive, the
local and other authorities, by which their success or failure could be
judged. It was also hoped that those failing to implement the directives
might receive a rude awakening at the polls.133
Austin’s later statement lends unflinching credence to this assertion, and adds an
insight into the philosophical basis of those provisions:
The Directive Principles were a declaration of economic independence, a
declaration that the privilege of the colonial era had ended, that the Indian
people (through the democratic institutions of the Constitution) had
assumed economic as well as political control of the country, and that
Indian capitalists should not inherit the empire of British colonialists.134
The judicial interpretation of those directive principles at the earlier stages of the
Indian constitutional experience demonstrated how the ossified letters of legal documents
could assume vibrant content. While the Supreme Court of India had in 1951 held, inter
alia, that “the directive principles have to conform to and run subsidiary to the chapter on
132
VICTOR Z. NARIVELY, CONFLICT: RIGHT TO PROPERTY AND DIRECTIVE PRINCIPLES OF THE
INDIAN CONSTITUTION 39 (1988).
133
H.M. SEERVAI, CONSTITUTIONAL LAW OF INDIA 759 (1967). See also NARIVELY, id., at 43-46
(demonstrating through vivid account of the views of various participants in the constitution drafting
process that the constitutional provisions on directive principles were couched in flexible language to
achieve “the goal of economic democracy”).
134
AUSTIN, supra note 131, at 61. The evolutionary processes of the Indian Constitution and the
Directive Principles have been the subject of ample research and need not detain us any further. See e.g.,
PATTABHI SITARAMAYYA, THE HISTORY OF THE INDIAN NATIONAL CONGRESS 463 (1946); AUSTIN, supra
note 131, at 50-113; Leela Simon et al, Fundamental Rights: The Constitutional Context of Human Rights,
in HUMAN RIGHTS IN INDIA 41-71 (Chiranjivi J. Nirmal, ed., 2000); Bertus de Villiers, Directive Principles
of State Policy and Fundamental Rights: The Indian Experience, 8(1) S. AFR. J. HUM. RTS. 29 (1992);
Maureen Callahan, Cultural Relativism and the Interpretation of Constitutional Texts, 30 WILLAMETTE L.
REV. 609 (1994).
32
fundamental rights”,135 in later years, particularly since the Indian emergency years
(1975-1977), Indian courts were to adopt a new, radical and proactive approach to the
interpretation of the scope and content of those directive principles.136
Today, Indian courts have established a veritable juridical pedestal in the
Directive Principles to address the plight of India’s underprivileged masses, to challenge
poverty and deprivation, and to question governmental acts that are capable of fettering
the very life, capabilities and aspirations of ordinary Indians.137
Posing the rhetorical question of whether the Directive Principles in the Indian
Constitution have “helped to bring Indian society closer to the Constitution’s goal of
social, economic, and political justice for all”, Austin concludes thus: “Briefly, the
answer is yes.”138 Similarly, in his assessment of the Indian judiciary’s efforts at giving
life to the otherwise non-justiciable provisions on Directive Principles in the Indian
135
State of Madras v. Champakam Dorairajan (1951) S.C.R. 226, 525.
See generally Sheetal B. Shah, Illuminating the Possible in the Developing World:
Guaranteeing the Right to Health in India, 32 VAND. J. INT’L L. 435, 462 (1999) (showing the impact of
public interest litigation and how the Supreme Court of India has consistently interpreted the enforceable
provisions of the Constitution to give meaning and force to directive principles). See also S. Muralidhar,
Justiciability – The Indian Experience, in INTERNATIONAL HUMAN RIGHTS INTERNSHIP PROGRAM (IHRIP),
CIRCLE OF RIGHTS ECONOMIC, SOCIAL AND CULTURAL RIGHTS ACTIVISM: A TRAINING RESOURCE 435
(IHRIP, 2000) (identifying the human rights consequences of the emergency period in India between 1975
and 1977 as the catalyst for the proactive stance of the Indian judiciary on directive principles).
137
See Villiers, Directive Principles, supra note 134, at 46-48. The tremendous impact of the
Indian Constitution in the concerted efforts towards good governance and nation-building since 1950,
including particularly the emergency years 1975-1977 under Indira Ghandi’s ill-fated regime has been
carefully analyzed and documented in AUSTIN, supra note 131, at 293-390 (1999). Ostensibly in its
increasing effort to curtail the effect of the constitutional non-justiciability of Directive Principles, the
Indian legislature has continually enacted a broad range of statutes that prioritize social issues. Notable
among which are the Plantation Labor Act, 1951; the Mines Act, 1952; the Employees Provident Fund Act,
1952; the Maternity Benefits Act, 1961; the Apprentices Act, 1961; the Contract Labor (Regulation and
Abolition) Act, 1970; the Bonded Labor System (Abolition) Act, 1976; the Urban Land (Ceiling and
Regulations) Act, 1976; the Child Labor (Prohibition and Regulation) Act, 1986 and the Legal Service
Authority Act, 1995. It is significant to note that all these statutes resulted from the energetic activism put
into the Directive Principles. See generally Lakshmidhar Mishra, Laws for the Labour, in SOCIAL ACTION
THROUGH LAW 107 (P. K. Ghandi, ed., 1985) (commending the manner of legislative intervention in the
face of rising economic adversities in India)
138
AUSTIN, supra note 131, at 114. In the next chapter, I shall be considering in analytical detail
the groundbreaking jurisprudential developments from Indian courts on this subject and their implications
for galvanizing a rights-based approach to human development in Africa.
136
33
Constitution, Rao says: “From…a restrictive and narrow definition of human rights, the
Supreme Court has expanded the scope of enforceable rights such as the right to life and
liberty.”139
It is particularly striking to note that the pivot of the Indian judicial approach to
the expansive and proactive interpretation of fundamental rights have been the Directive
Principles, which, technically speaking, are non-justiciable. The Supreme Court has
resoundingly reaffirmed the status of the Directive Principles as being the non-negotiable
corollary of fundamental human rights.140 This reconceptualization has meant a sustained
commitment to the integrative approach to all human rights in Indian courts. A long line
of cases demonstrates this assertion.
In the groundbreaking case of Maneka Ghandi v. Union of India,141 the applicant’s
passport had been seized by the authorities pursuant to the Emergency Orders of that
period, and thus, she had been denied the opportunity to travel abroad. Observing that
any procedure affecting any human rights must not be “arbitrary, fanciful or
oppressive”,142 the Indian Supreme Court seized the opportunity of Ghandi to affirm that
139
S. N. Nageswara Rao, Human Rights Initiatives, in HUMAN RIGHTS IN INDIA, supra note 134,
52, 64. Art. 21 of the Indian Constitution provides: “No person shall be deprived of his life or personal
liberty except according to procedure established by law.” For an insight into how the National Human
Rights Commission of India, in partnership with the civil society, has been of tremendous assistance in
monitoring the implementation of the Supreme Court’s decisions on human rights, see Subbash C. Jain,
The Commonwealth and Human Rights: An Indian Perspective, 25 C’WEALTH L. BULLETIN 117, 128-132
(1999).
140
In Minerva Mills Ltd. v. Union of India, A.I.R. 1980 S.C. 1789, the Supreme Court, declared
that “[t]hose [fundamental human] rights are not an end in themselves but are the means to an end. The end
is specified in Part IV [Directive Principles]”, id., at 1806-1807, per Chief Justice Chandrachud. See also
Bharati v. State of Kerala, A.I.R. 1973 S.C. 1461, where the Supreme Court, per Justices Hedge and
Mukherjea proclaimed that “the fundamental rights and directive principles constitute the conscience of the
Constitution…There is no antithesis between the fundamental rights and directive principles…one
supplements the other”, id., at 1641(emphasis in the original).
141
Ghandi, A.I.R. 1978 S.C. 597.
142
Id., at 674.
34
the right to life entrenched in Article 21 of the Indian Constitution also covers the right to
travel abroad.
This case was to mark a historic defining moment for the Indian judiciary as well
as human rights protection in years to follow.143 While Ghandi had arisen as an action in
defense of the right to personal liberty, its broader effects have been felt in the areas of
criminal justice, judicial review, contracts, ecology, fundamental rights as well as other
“implied fundamental rights” including education, legal aid, pollution-free environment,
livelihood and human dignity.144 The proactive approach of the Indian judiciary to many
questions involving social justice, individual liberty, human development, labor rights
and poverty alleviation has been the offshoot of the judiciary’s commitment to a creative
interpretative process that considers a fundamental human right to “mean merely animal
existence [when it is bereft of] human dignity.”145
143
See Antulay v. Naik, A.I.R. 1992 S.C. 1701, 1717, where the Supreme Court described the
transformative influence of the provision of Art. 21 in Indian constitutionalism as follows: “Article 21 got
unshackled from the restrictive meaning placed upon it...It came to acquire a force and vitality hitherto
unimagined. A burst of creative decisions of this Court fast on the heels of Maneka Ghandi gave a new
meaning to the Article and expanded its content and connotation.” See also V. Vijayakumar, The Working
of the National Human Rights Commission, in HUMAN RIGHTS IN INDIA, supra note 134, 211, 213
(describing the Ghandi decision as “the turning point for judicial activism in upholding the rights and
liberties of individuals under the Indian Constitution”).
144
M. P. Jain, The Supreme Court and Fundamental Rights, in FIFTY YEARS OF THE SUPREME
COURT OF INDIA: ITS GRASP AND REACH 1, 43, 51-52 (S.K. Verma et al, eds., 2000). See, for example,
Vellore Citizens’ Welfare Forum v. Union of India, A.I.R. 1996 S.C. 3399, where the Supreme Court laid
down the fundamental rule that precautionary measures must be taken by the state and other authorities in
the anticipation and prevention of causes of environmental degradation; Vishaka v. State of Rajasthan,
A.I.R. 1997 S.C. 3011, where the Supreme Court held the workplace sexual harassment of a woman to be a
violation of her rights to equality, life and liberty under arts. 14, 15, and 21; Krishnan v. State of Andhra
Pradesh, A.I.R. 1993 S.C. 2178, where the Supreme Court acknowledged that the provision of education
depends on the economic capacity of the state, it held that the commercialization of education cannot be
permitted. The court further established that under art. 21, the right to education until the age of 14 is a
fundamental right; Shetty v. The Int’l Airport Auth. India, A.I.R. 1979 S.C. 259, where the Supreme Court
established the rule that although the discretion of awarding contracts for state projects vests in the
government, such discretion must be rational, relevant and non-discriminatory”, id., at 157; and, Hoskot v.
State of Maharashtra, A.I.R. 1978 S.C. 1548, where the Supreme Court declared that the right to legal aid
and speedy trial is an integral part of art. 21.
145
Jain, id., at 30.
35
Thus, in Olga Tellis v. Bombay Mun. Corp.,146 the petitioners who were slum
dwellers had petitioned against their forcible eviction by the defendant corporation,
alleging a violation of their right to life under Article 21. The Supreme Court held that the
right to life conferred by Article 21 of the Indian Constitution extends to the right to
livelihood, and that in this particular instance, the eviction of the slum dwellers will
deprive them of livelihood, and invariably, life. Even though the applicants had failed to
demand that the corporation allows the slum dwellers to show why they should not be
evicted, the court ordered that further evictions must cease until the end of the prevailing
monsoon season, to mitigate their hardship.147 The court explained the basis of its
decision as follows:
The sweep of the right to life conferred by Article 21 is wide and far
reaching. It does not mean merely that life cannot be extinguished or taken
away as, for example, by the imposition and execution of the death
sentence, except according to procedure established by law…An equally
important facet of that right is the right to livelihood because, no person
can live without the means of living, that is, the means of livelihood. If the
right to livelihood is not treated as a part of the constitutional right to life,
the easiest way of depriving a person of his right to life would be to
deprive him of his means of livelihood to the point of abrogation. Such
deprivation would not only denude the life of its effective content and
meaningfulness but it would make life impossible to live. And yet, such
deprivation would not have to be in accordance with the procedure
established by law, if the right to livelihood is not regarded as a part of the
right to life. That, which alone makes it possible to live, leave aside what
makes life livable, must be deemed to be an integral component of the
right to life.148
146
Tellis, A.I.R. 1986 S.C. 180.
Monsoon refers to the volatile climatic torrents that sweep sporadically and unpredictably
across India and the South Asian region annually, creating adverse weather conditions. See THE AMERICAN
HERITAGE DICTIONARY 549 (4th ed. 2001).
148
Id., at para. 79F-H, 80A-B (emphasis added). This reasoning was applied in the more recent
case of Anthony v. Bihar Gold Mines Ltd., A.I.R. 1999 S.C. 1416, where a government worker had his
employment and salary suspended while disciplinary action was being considered. The court held that he
must be paid “subsistence allowance” notwithstanding the interdiction. In the court’s words: “Non-payment
of subsistence allowance is an inhuman act which has an unpropitious effect on the life of an employee”,
id., at 1423. See also Coralie v. Union Territory of Delhi, A.I.R. 1981 S.C. 746, 753, where the same court
declared: “We think that the right to life includes the right to live with human dignity and all that goes
147
36
The Indian judiciary has consistently shown in many other instances that it will
not abandon the helpless to the vicissitudes of life. In Samity v. State of West Bengal,149
involving a petitioner who had suffered serious cerebral injuries occasioned by a train
accident, the Supreme Court held that under Article 21, he had a right to “timely medical
treatment.”150
The effect of the proactive stance of the Indian judiciary has also been felt in the
fields of industrial, labor and trade practices.151 In a slew of cases, for instance, the
Supreme Court has held that the “equal pay for equal work” principle in Article 39(d) of
the Indian Constitution is within the expanded scope of Articles 14 and 21.152
Also, in Randhirin Shri Literam Sugar Co. Ltd. v. Union of India, 153 citing the
directive principles, the Supreme Court held that the price control on foodstuffs was in
the public interest.154
along with it, namely, the bare necessaries of life such as adequate nutrition, clothing and shelter over the
head and facilities for reading, writing and expressing oneself in diverse forms, freely moving about and
mixing and commingling with fellow human beings.”
149
A.I.R. 1996 S.C. 2415.
150
Id., at 2429. See also Panikulangara v. India, A.I.R. 1987 S.C. 990 (laying the precedent for the
judicial principle that access to medical treatment is an integral part of the right to life under art. 21);
Kataria v. Union of India, A.I.R. 1989 S.C. 2039 (upholding the claim of the victim to right to assistance by
a medical doctor). For an extensive analysis of concerted efforts of various cadres of the Indian judiciary to
incorporate the right to health into the fundamental right to life, see Shah, supra note 136, at 475-484.
151
See generally M. Rama Jois, The Supreme Court on Service Law Governing Employees of
State, in FIFTY YEARS OF THE SUPREME COURT OF INDIA, supra note 144, at 127-155 (discussing the
activist role of the Indian Supreme Court in defending the rights of working people in India). See also
Bertus de Villiers, The Socio-Economic Consequences of Directive Principles of State Policy: Limitations
on Fundamental Rights, 8(2) S. AFR. J. HUM. RTS. 188-199 (1992) (analyzing the Indian case law on
minimum wages, workers’ participation, equal pay, and price fixing, as developed through the activism of
the Indian judiciary). See, for example, Bandhua Mukti Morcha v. Union of India, A.I.R. 1984 S.C. 802,
where the Supreme Court read art. 21 in conjunction with the directive principles in arts. 39(e), (f), 41 and
42, to hold that bonded labor was unconstitutional, constituting a “gross and revolting violation of
constitutional values”, per Justice Bhagwati, at 811. For an analysis of other judicial decisions on these
issues, see Rao, supra note 139, at 66-67.
152
See e.g., Singh v. Union of India, A.I.R. 1982 S.C. 879; Singh v. J and K, A.I.R. 1986 S.C.
584; Fed’n of Stenographers v. Union of India, A.I.R. 1988 S.C. 1291.
153
(1990) I S.C.R. 909.
37
The manner of consistency and clarity with which the Indian Supreme Court has
been administering social justice through its efficacious protection of the ‘implied’ rights
in the Indian Constitution has led a scholar to proclaim that “after Maneka Ghandi’s case
the Court began to apply the fair and reasonable requirements of law not only to
deprivation of life but also to the well-ordered concept of human dignity and life.”155
By virtue of shared British colonial heritage and common law traditions, the
Indian approach to human rights certainly portends strategic implications for other
countries of the developing world, especially those in Anglophone Africa.
E.
Nigeria
The Indian constitutional design of directive principles had gained the attention of
constitutional drafters in Indonesia in 1951, Nepal in 1962, and Sri Lanka in 1972.156 For
Africa, Nigeria led the way in 1979 with its Second Republican Constitution.157 That
Constitution provided a litany of principles that would guide the administration of the
154
See Khandsari v. State of Uttar Pradesh, (1981) S.C. 873, for an earlier decision on identical
point. See also Shantistar Builders v. Totane, A.I.R. 1990 S.C. 630, 633, where the Supreme Court held that
the right to life included the right to “food, clothing, shelter and a decent environment.”
155
T. R. Andhyarujina, The Evolution of Due Process of Law by the Supreme Court, in SUPREME
BUT NOT INFALLIBLE: ESSAYS IN HONOUR OF THE SUPREME COURT OF INDIA 193, 204 (B. N. Kirpal et al
eds. 2000). For an assessment of the proactive drive of the Indian Supreme Court between 1950 and 2000,
see Vijayashri Sripati, Towards Fifty Years of Constitutionalism and Fundamental Rights in India: Looking
Back to see Ahead, 14 AM. U. INT’L L. REV. 413, 439-452 (1998).
156
For readings on the background to the adoption of Directive Principles in other jurisdictions,
see the following: JOSEPH A. L. COORAY, CONSTITUTIONAL AND ADMINISTRATIVE LAW OF SRI LANKA
(CEYLON) (1973); TIM MURPHY ET AL, IRELAND'S EVOLVING CONSTITUTION 1937-1997: COLLECTED
ESSAYS (1999); Richard Stith, Unconstitutional Constitutional Amendments: The Extraordinary Power of
Nepal’s Supreme Court, 11 AM. U. J. INT’L L & POL’Y 47 (1996); Pinai Nanakorn, Re-Making of the
Constitution in Thailand, 6(1) SING. J. INT’L & COMP. L. 90, 105-106 (2002); Andrew Ellis, The
Indonesian Constitutional Transition: Conservativism or Fundamental Change?, 6(1) SING. J. INT’L &
COMP. L. 116 (2002).
157
Fundamental Objectives and Directive Principles of State Policy, ch. II (§§ 13-22), Constitution
of the Federal Republic of Nigeria (CFRN), promulgated into law by the CFRN Decree No. 104 of 1979
(entered into force Oct. 1, 1979). For a historical commentary on the CFRN 1979, see J ADESOLA AKANDE,
INTRODUCTION TO THE NIGERIAN CONSTITUTION, at i-xiv (1982).
38
Nigerian polity towards the general good (sections 13-22).158 Those objectives and
principles were essentially a set of guidelines designed to secure the ‘national’ targets of
social well-being, social justice, political stability, and economic growth in accordance
with the espoused vision of the Preamble to the Constitution.159
During the drafting stages of the CFRN 1979, Emovon, a Nigerian scholar, had
justified the inclusion of these objectives as follows:
Fundamental Objectives refer to a set of social ideals which are semijusticiable and designed as targets towards which the country must aim.
They define a goal for the Nation without which this country would drift
as it appeared to have done in the past. In a country as vast and
heterogeneous as Nigeria where we still have primacy of local interests
and where the people have…different historical, cultural and religious
backgrounds, it has become necessary to spell out in detail the basic
principles of the State for the guidance of Government.160
While those Fundamental Objectives could have passed as one of the most
innovative dimensions in the history of constitution making in Nigeria, they are prone to
158
§ 13 provides for the overarching duty of all organs and officials of government to apply the
provisions of ch. II; § 14 proclaims sovereignty as being vested in the people of Nigeria; § 15 entrenches
the promotion of national loyalty as the cardinal political objective of Nigeria; § 16 entrenches the
establishment of a “mixed economic system” as the fundamental objective, which was essentially an
official proclamation of the existing free market ideology of the regime; § 17 emphasizes a system of
welfare assistance; § 18 declared the commitment of government to education and literacy among
Nigerians; § 19 asserts Nigeria’s Afro-centric foreign policy; § 20 directs the State to promote and preserve
Nigerian cultures and values; § 21 mandates the Press and media to uphold the fundamental objectives and
accountability while § 22 declares the ethics of the Nigerian State as “Discipline, Self-reliance and
Patriotism.” Those same provisions were re-enacted verbatim as ch. II (§§ 13-24) in the 1999 version of
the CFRN promulgated into law by Constitution of the Federal Republic of Nigeria (Promulgation) Decree
No. 24, May 5, 1999 (entered into force May 29, 1999). For a robust critique of this constitutional model,
see ’Dejo Olowu, Fundamental Objectives and Directive Principles of State Policy in Nigeria, in ISSUES IN
CONSTITUTIONAL LAW AND PRACTICE IN NIGERIA 290 (Justus A. Sokefun, ed., 2002) [hereinafter
SOKEFUN].
159
Para. 3 of the Preamble to the 1979 Constitution provided the basis of the Constitution as “TO
PROVIDE…good government and welfare of all persons in our country on the principles of Freedom,
Equality and Justice, and for the purpose of consolidating the Unity of our people.”
160
Emmanuel U. Emovon, Fundamental Objectives and Directive Principles and Public
Accountability, in KUMO ET AL, supra note 105, 29.
39
becoming worthless platitudes because of their emasculated constitutional status.161 An
overriding provision of the same Constitution nullifies their legal value:
6(1) The judicial powers of the Federation shall be vested in the courts to
which this section relates, being courts established for the Federation.
…
(6) The judicial powers vested in accordance with the foregoing provisions
of this section
…
(c) shall not, except as otherwise provided by this Constitution, extend to
any issue or question as to whether any act or omission by any authority or
person or as to whether any law or any judicial decision is in conformity
with the Fundamental Objectives and Directive Principles of State Policy
set out in Chapter II of this Constitution….162
It naturally follows, from the above ouster clause, that all the promises of the
Objectives and Principles in Chapter II of the CFRN serve no better purpose than British
coronation oath: mere moral appeal. The decisions of Nigerian courts, as far as the status
of those provisions is concerned, were unequivocal in confining those provisions to the
realm of principles that may only appeal to the morality of any government in power.163
161
See AKANDE, supra note 157, at vi. See also AGUDA, supra note 21, at 77-78 (describing those
provisions as “a white elephant…attempt to introduce into the constitution some ideals and concepts in the
nature…of a by-gone era”).
162
CFRN, 1979, § 6(6) (c). This same section was re-enacted verbatim as § 6(6) (c) in the CFRN,
1999.
163
I examine a number of relevant decisions in the next segment. Comparative experience in India
and Ireland shows that although Directive Principles lack the force of positive law, they have nonetheless
crystallized into political imperatives from which no “responsible government” will openly derail. See
NARIVELY, supra note 132, at 174-175. See also AUSTIN, supra note 131, at 74-75 (pointing out that since
the Directive Principles are seen as “the aims of the Indian social revolution”, every successive parliament
has adhered to those principles in the enactment of statutes). As desirable as it would have been for the
Directive Principles to become central political issues in Nigeria, the Nigerian political party system and
post-election machinery for the implementation of campaign promises have remained problematic since
independence. The notion of democratic auditing is yet to find its way into either intellectual debate or the
Nigerian political arena. Nigerian electoral politics revolves more around cleavages and parochial interests
rather than on political accountability. For readings on Nigerian politics and its long history of failure to
yield tangible and sustainable democratic dividends, see A. Fadahunsi, The Constitution, Parties and
Ideology: Prospects for National Unity and Welfare, in KUMO ET AL, supra note 105, 103-108; Pita Ogaba
Agbese, The State versus Human Rights Advocates in Africa: The Case of Nigeria, in AFRICA, HUMAN
RIGHTS AND THE GLOBAL SYSTEM 147, 159-167 (Eileen McCarthy-Arnolds, David R. Penna et al, eds.,
1994); Dele Olowu, Centralization, Self-Governance and Development in Nigeria, in THE FAILURE OF THE
CENTRALIZED STATE: INSTITUTIONS AND SELF-GOVERNANCE IN AFRICA 193, 204-218 (James S. Wunsch et
al, eds., 1995).
40
The idea of non-justiciable constitutional provisions had indeed become Nigeria’s
legacy for constitutionalism in Africa. After the debut in 1979, political power brokers in
other African countries had found a leeway out of rights-based accountability to their
peoples. Thus, at independence, Zimbabwe (1980)164 and Namibia (1990)165 must have
looked up to the Nigerian constitutional model of 1979 in drafting their versions of
fundamental objectives that mirror the Nigerian model almost verbatim.166 The
constitutional model of Directive Principles was to fascinate many other African
countries in the years that followed. Many African Constitutions are now replete with
provisions identical to the neo-Nigerian paradigm. These are: Botswana, 1992;167 Eritrea,
1997;168 the Gambia, 1994;169 Ghana, 1992;170 Lesotho, 1993;171 Liberia, 1984;172
164
ZIMB. CONST., Apr. 18, 1980, amended by Constitution of Zimbabwe (Amendment) Act No.
14, 1996, reprinted in CHRISTOF HEYNS, HUMAN RIGHTS LAW IN AFRICA 318 (1999). For a scholarly
analysis of salient human rights provisions in the Zimbabwean Constitution, see Pearson Nherere, How
Can a Bill of Rights best be Protected against Undesirable Erosion and Amendment?, 7 LEGAL F. 40
(1995).
165
Principles of State Policy, (art. 95), NAMIB. CONST., Mar. 21, 1990, Fundamental Principles,
Ch. III (arts. 12-14), reprinted in CHRISTOF HEYNS, HUMAN RIGHTS LAW IN AFRICA 261 (1996)
[hereinafter HEYNS, 1996].
166
See generally Kenneth Grundy, The Impact of Regionalism on Contemporary African Politics,
in AFRICAN INDEPENDENCE: THE FIRST TWENTY-FIVE YEARS 97 (Gwendolen M. Carter et al, eds., 1985)
(highlighting Nigeria’s frontline role in the decolonization struggles of States in the Southern African subregion). See also Gabriel O. Olusanya, Reflections on the First Twenty-Five Years of the Organization of
African Unity, 14 (1) NIG. J. INT’L AFF. 67-72 (1988) (commending Nigeria’s yeoman role in the
decolonization and anti-apartheid agenda of the OAU).
167
BOTS. CONST., Sept. 30, 1966, amended by Constitutional (Amendment) Act No. 27, Oct. 9,
1992, reprinted in HEYNS, 1996, supra note 165, 35.
168
National Objectives and Directive Principles, ch. II (arts. 6-12), ERI. CONST., May 23, 1997,
reprinted in CHRISTOF HEYNS, HUMAN RIGHTS LAW IN AFRICA 292 (1998).
169
GAM. CONST., Apr. 24, 1970, suspended July 1994, rewritten and approved Aug. 8, 1996,
reestablished Jan. 1997, reprinted in HEYNS, 1996, supra note 165, 135.
170
The Directive Principles of State Policy, ch. VI (arts. 34-41), GHANA CONST., Apr. 28, 1992,
reprinted in HEYNS, 1996, supra note 165, 146. Note that the constitution recognizes the right to work
under satisfactory conditions (art. 24); the right to “equal educational opportunities” (art. 25); and the right
to social security (art. 36) as justiciable rights. For a scholarly analysis of salient human rights provisions in
the Ghanaian Constitution, see Nana K. A. Busia, Competing Visions of Liberal Democracy, in HUMAN
RIGHTS UNDER AFRICAN CONSTITUTIONS: REALIZING THE PROMISE FOR OURSELVES 52 (Abdullahi Ahmed
An-Na’im, ed., 2003).
171
Principles of State Policy, ch. III (arts. 25-36), LESOTHO CONST., Mar. 25, 1993, reprinted in
HEYNS, 1996, supra note 165, 186.
172
General Principles of National Policy, ch. II (arts. 1-10), LIBER. CONST., Jan. 27, 1984,
reprinted in HEYNS, 1996, supra note 165, 201.
41
Malawi, 1995;173 Sierra Leone, 1991;174 Tanzania, 1984;175 Uganda, 1995;176 and
Zambia, 1991.177 Common to all those constitutional provisions is their non-justiciability
because of language similar to that found in section 6(6)(c) of the Nigerian model.178
V.
CONTEXTUAL AFRICAN CHALLENGES AND THE PROMISE OF
UNENFORCEABLE ENUMERATED RIGHTS
It is important to note that the provisions usually couched as Directive Principles
are often the exact spirit and letters of economic, social and cultural rights (ESCR)
norms, as elaborated in the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural
Rights (ICESCR), 1966.179 One is perturbed that many African States Parties that are
obliged under Article 2(1) of the ICESCR “to take steps…by all appropriate means,
including particularly the adoption of legislative measures” to secure ICESCR provisions
173
Fundamental Principles, ch. III (arts. 12-14), MALAWI CONST., May 16, 1994, reprinted in
HEYNS, 1996, supra note 165, 216.
174
Fundamental Principles of State Policy, ch. II (arts. 4-14), SIERRA LEONE CONST., Oct. 1, 1991,
reprinted in HEYNS, 1996, supra note 165, 319.
175
Important Objectives and the Basic Structures of the Direction of Government Affairs, s. 2
(arts. 1-11), TANZ. CONST., 1977, amended by Fifth Amendment of the State Constitution (Act No. 15),
1984 (entered into force on Mar. 15, 1988), reprinted in HEYNS, 1996, supra note 165, 355. Note that art.
22 recognizes the right to work in positive language. For a scholarly analysis of salient human rights
provisions in the Tanzanian Constitution, see Chris Maina Peter, Respect for Fundamental Rights and
Freedoms: A New Bill of Rights for Tanzania, 67(4) REV. INT’L L. DIPL. & POL. 255 (1989).
176
National Objectives and Directive Principles of State Policy, arts. I-XXIX, UGANDA CONST.,
adopted Sept. 22, 1995, reprinted in HEYNS, 1996, supra note 165, 371. For a scholarly analysis of salient
human rights provisions in the Ugandan Constitution, see Joe Oloka-Onyango, Constitutional Transition in
Museveni’s Uganda: New Horizons or Another False Start?, 39 J. AFR. L. 156 (1995).
177
Fundamental Objectives (art. 16), ZAMBIA CONST., Act No. 1, Aug. 30, 1991, amended by
Constitution (Amendment) Act No. 18, May 28, 1996, reprinted in HEYNS, 1996, supra note 165, 303. For
a scholarly discussion of salient human rights provisions in the Zambian Constitution, see Alfred W.
Chanda, Zambia’s Fledgling Democracy: Prospects for the Future, 25-28 ZAMBIA L. J. 125 (1993-1996).
178
See, for example, § 34(1), GHANA CONST. (“The Directive Principles of State Policy contained
in this Chapter shall guide [not bind] all citizens, Parliament, the President, the Judiciary, the Council of
State, the Cabinet, political parties and other bodies and persons in applying or interpreting this
Constitution or any other law and in taking and implementing any policy decisions, for the establishment of
a just and free society”) (emphasis added); § 25, LESOTHO CONST. (“These principles shall not be
enforceable by any court but…shall guide the authorities and agencies of Lesotho”) (emphasis added); §
14, MALAWI CONST. (“The principles of national policy contained in this Chapter shall be directory in
nature”) (emphasis added); § 14, S IERRA LEONE CONST. (“the provisions contained in this Chapter shall
not confer legal rights and shall not be enforceable in any court of law”); art. I, U GANDA CONST.; and §
111, ZAMBIA CONST.
179
International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (ICESCR), G.A. Res. 2200A
(XXI), U.N. Doc. A/6316 (1966), 993 U.N.T.S. 3 (entered into force on Jan. 03, 1976).
42
have generally shunned the inclusion of economic, social and cultural rights in the most
fundamental of their domestic laws.
Since 1979 when the Fundamental Objectives and Directive Principles of State
Policy debuted in Nigerian constitutionalism, the entrenched non-justiciability clause has
remained a veritable rampart against their appreciation in Nigerian courts. The nonjusticiability of these provisions has received judicial pronouncement in a series of cases,
chief among which was Okogie v. Att’y Gen., Lagos State.180 Here, the plaintiff had sued
as the trustee of Roman Catholic Schools challenging the abolition of private primary
schools on the ground that it was contrary, inter alia, to freedom of expression
guaranteed in the CFRN 1979. The government had argued that the operation of private
schools was inconsistent with the obligation of the State to give “equal and adequate
educational opportunities” under Section 18(1), CFRN. The court also held that while the
phrase “equal and adequate educational opportunities” did not necessarily restrict the
right of private institutions or other persons to provide similar or different educational
facilities at their own expense, taste and preferences, the Directive Principles must have
to conform to and run subsidiary to the fundamental human rights provisions.181
The reasoning in that decision found wholesale affirmation in Adewole v.
Jakande, Governor of Lagos State.182 It had become evident that the ESCR elements in
the Directive Principles were to remain cosmetic constitutional provisions in Nigeria.
Indeed, the first time those provisions were ever referred to as “rights” was in the
1991 decision of the Nigerian Court of Appeal in Uzuokwu v. Ezeonu II183 where the
180
(1981) 1 N.C.L.R. 218.
§ 18(1) CFRN 1979 provided that: “Government shall direct its policy towards ensuring that
there are equal and adequate educational opportunities at all levels.” §18(1) CFRN 1999 retains the
provision in its exact wording.
182
(1981) 1 N.C.L.R. 152.
181
43
court held, inter alia, that “[t]here are other rights which may pertain to a person which
are neither fundamental nor justiciable in the court. These may include rights given by
the Constitution as under the Fundamental Objectives and Directive Principles of State
Policy under Chapter II of the Constitution.” 184
For a very long period, therefore, as far as ESCR were concerned, Nigerian courts
had declined to assume jurisdiction. It is worthy to note, however, that since the era of the
repressive military regimes that ruled Nigeria between 1984 and 1999, efforts had been
made by human rights NGOs and activists to explore the application of the African
Charter in national courts in view of its domestication.185 Thus, in a long line of cases,
Nigerian courts have been called upon to adjudicate on the domestic legal status of the
African Charter. In Ogugu v. State, 186 the Supreme Court of Nigeria held that all rights
provisions in the African Charter are applicable and enforceable in Nigeria through the
ordinary rules of court in the same manner as those fundamental rights set out in Chapter
IV of the Constitution. This position has been affirmed by the later decision of the apex
court in Abacha v. Fawehinmi.187
Notwithstanding the fact that the scanty Nigerian jurisprudence on the African
Charter has exclusively been on civil and political rights, it is plausible to argue that a
priori, the ESCR provisions in the African Charter are domestically enforceable although
further development of jurisprudence in this direction will still be required to make this
183
(1991) 6 N.W.L.R. (pt. 200) 708.
Id., at 761-762 (emphasis added).
185
By virtue of the African Charter on Human and Peoples’ Rights (Enforcement and Ratification)
Act, Ch. 10, LFN 1990, the African Charter was incorporated into the municipal laws of Nigeria. In
Oshevire v. British Caledonian Airways (1990) 7 N.W.L.R. (pt. 163) 507, the Court of Appeal held that
international treaties incorporated into municipal laws are superior to other municipal laws.
186
(1994) 9 N.W.L.R. (pt. 366) 1.
187
(2000) Fed’n Wkly. L. Rep. (pt. 4) 533. Cf. Fawehinmi v. Abacha (1996) 9 N.W.L.R. (pt. 475)
710, where the Court of Appeal had opined that the African Charter was superior to any other municipal
law in Nigeria.
184
44
thinking resonant.188 In this regard, I conjecture a re-awakening of the Nigerian judiciary
to its responsibility in nation-building in light of the Supreme Court’s decision in Att’y
Gen., Ondo State v. Att’y Gen., Fed’n.189 The Ondo State Government had brought an
action challenging the constitutional validity of the Corrupt Practices and Other Related
Offences Act, 2000 as well as the Independent Corrupt Practices and Other Related
Offences Commission (ICPC) set up under it to initiate criminal proceedings in any court
in Nigeria.190
In what may be considered a new judicial perception about the status of the
Fundamental Objectives in Nigeria, the Supreme Court added that:
As to the non-justiciability of the Fundamental Objectives and Directive
Principles of State Policy, section 6(6)(c)…says so. While they remain
mere declarations, they cannot be enforced by legal process but would be
seen as a failure of duty and responsibility of State organs if they acted in
clear disregard of them…the Directive Principles can be made justiciable
by legislation.191
From the tone of the Ondo State decision, it would appear that the Nigerian
Supreme Court might become favorably disposed to ESCR adjudication in the future,
particularly where there are appropriate statutes to fortify rights-based claims.
It would appear that the new ‘democratic’ dispensation has added impetus to ESCR activism in
Nigeria going by the number of pending cases. In Eze Amadi v. Att’y Gen., Fed’n, Suit No. ID/231/99,
plaintiffs are seeking to enforce the right to accessible and qualitative education as guaranteed under the
African Charter. Similarly, in Ilemobayo v. Nigerian Nat’l Petroleum Corp., Suit No. FHC/L/593/97, a
Lagos Federal High Court is being asked to hold that the right to work under favorable environment under
the African Charter is enforceable despite section 6(6)(c) of the Constitution. It is certain that the outcomes
of these cases would go a long way in boosting ESCR jurisprudence in Nigeria.
189
(2002) 9 Sup. Ct. Monthly 1.
190
In holding that the statute and the commission set up under it were constitutional and valid, the
apex court referred extensively to the Fundamental Principles in Chapter II of the CFRN 1999. According
to the court: [I]t is incidental or supplementary for the National Assembly to enact the law that will enable
the ICPC to enforce the observance of the Fundamental Objectives and Directive Principles of State
Policy…The ICPC was established to enforce the observance of the Directive Principle set out in Section
15 subsection (5) of Chapter II. See id., at 38-39, 79. § 15(5) CFRN 1999 provides that “[t]he State shall
abolish all corrupt practices and abuse of power.”
191
Id., at 96-97. The Ondo State decision has been described by an African human rights activist
as supporting “a wider interpretation of the reach of the Fundamental Objectives and Directive Principles of
State Policy.” See E-mail from Chidi Odinkalu, Constitutions (Nov. 21, 2002, 15:05:59 GMT) (on file with
author).
188
45
While one might be prone to ascribe the parlous state of ESCR adjudication in
Nigeria to substantive issues of legal framework, perhaps the most formidable
impediment to the effective protection of such rights remains the common law procedural
doctrine of locus standi and how the courts have interpreted it in relation to
constitutionalism. Nigerian courts still interpret the rule on the right to sue very strictly,
that is, only the person who shows the court that he or she has personal interest in the
subject matter of the litigation or that the violation complained of affects him or her
directly and personally, has the ‘standing’ to institute an action. This has always been
particularly difficult to establish in public interest litigation cases as few of such actions
ever scale the hurdle.192
The leading decision on the question of locus standi in Nigeria is Adesanya v.
President of the Federal Republic of Nigeria193 where the appellant had commenced an
action challenging the appointment of the Chairman of the Federal Electoral Commission
on the ground that it would violate some constitutional provisions. After a protracted
process of appeals, the Supreme Court of Nigeria held that the appellant lacked the locus
standi to institute the action. In laying the foundation of what was to become Nigeria’s
‘strict constructionist approach’ to locus standi, the apex court had preoccupied itself
with the imprecise task of keeping “vexatious litigants or frivolous claims” at bay. 194
Regrettably, despite rigorous attempts by Nigerian lawyers to whittle down the
192
For general discussions on the operation of the doctrine of locus standi in Nigerian courts, see
MIKE A.A. OZEKHOME, THE NIGERIAN LAW ON LOCUS STANDI 82-90 (1988); E.A. Taiwo, Locus Standi in
Nigeria, in SOKEFUN, supra note 158, 242-153.
193
Adesanya, (1981) 2 NC.L.R. 358.
194
Id., at 373, per Fatayi-Williams, Chief Justice of Nigeria.
46
conservative rule of locus standi, Adesanya has continued to reverberate on the Nigerian
legal terrain since 1981.195
It is my contention that based upon the dynamic trends on the doctrine in England
as well as in many common law jurisdictions, the test of ‘interest’ in Nigerian courts
should be based on liberal rules of genuine concern and legitimate expectation.196 This
argument has received isolated judicial approval in Ezezoobo v. The Provisional Ruling
Council197 where the Federal High Court held that in public law, locus standi should not
deprive citizens’ access to court for remedies.
Once this proposition gains acceptation in the higher courts and becomes settled,
the question of the extent of state obligations would follow, but for now, the ESCR
struggle must advance towards achieving basic recognition for these rights and their
beneficiaries in Nigerian courts.198
195
See, for example, Irene Thomas v. Olufosoye, (1986) 2 Sup. Ct. 325; Adefulu v. Oyesile,
(1989) 5 N.W.L.R. (pt. 122) 377; Okoye v. Lagos State Gov’t, (1990) 3 N.W.L.R. (pt. 136) 115; Obaba v.
Military Governor of Kwara State, (1994) 4 N.W.L.R. (pt. 336) 15; Ezeafulukwe v. John Holt Ltd., (1996)
2 N.W.L.R. (pt. 432) 511; HURILAWS v. Gov’t of Zamfara State of Nigeria, Unreported Suit No.
ZMS/GS/17/2000, Judgment of the High Court of Zamfara State, May 4, 2001 (on file with author). But see
Fawehinmi v. Akilu, (1987) 4 N.W.L.R. (pt. 67) 797, where the Supreme Court, in an unusual manner, held
that the appellant had locus standi to commence private criminal proceedings against two suspected
military officers in the light of the State’s reluctance and unwillingness to prosecute them for the murder of
a frontline Nigerian journalist). Note, however, that the decision was rendered practically useless as the
military government retroactively amended the criminal procedure law that guaranteed the right of private
prosecution.
196
This is an alchemy of the reasoning that prevailed in cases like Inland Revenue Comm’rs v.
Nat’l Fed’n of Self-Employed and Small Businesses Ltd., [1982] A.C. 617 (British House of Lord); Kajing
Tubek v. Ekran BAD (1995) Saman Remula 55-27-66 (Supreme Court of Pakistan).
197
Unreported Suit No. FHC/CS/640/95 (on file with author).
198
For other decisions relating to locus standi in public law matters in Nigeria, see Akinpelu v.
Att’y Gen., Oyo State, (1984) 5 NC.L.R. 557, and Ejeh v. Att’y Gen., Imo State, (1985) 6 N.C.L.R. 390, in
both of which the court held that where the cause of action involves the validity or constitutionality of any
enactment, the litigant is relieved of the requirement of locus standi. See also Kokoro-Owo v. Lagos State
Gov’t, (1998) Hum. Rts. L. Rep. Afr. 322, and Olatoye v. Governor of Lagos State, Unreported Suit No.
FHC/CS/144/99 (on file with author), where the High Court of Lagos State and the Federal High Court,
respectively, held that the established practice of forced evictions from homes was inhuman. Contra
Thomas v. Olufosoye, supra note 195, at 352-353, where the Supreme Court declared, per Obaseki, JSC,
that: “As the law stands, there is no room for the adoption of the modern views on locus standi being
followed by England and Australia. The adoption of those views in England has found support in the
statute law of England.” This might very well be an unmistakable omen of the apex court’s unwillingness
47
F.
Other Anglophone African States
The non-domestication of international human rights treaties, conservatism, lack of
knowledge about global trends, the virtual non-availability of ESCR precedents, and an
inadequately equipped civil society have been the combined factors for the stunted
development of ESCR jurisprudence by most judiciaries in Africa. 199 A survey of the
judicial terrain across Africa reveals that pronouncements relevant for ESCR
jurisprudence are to be gleaned mainly from decisions on other tangential issues.200 Thus,
while it will not be preposterous to assert that the growth of human rights jurisprudence is
generally stunted in much of Africa because of deep and complex inherent and structural
to adapt itself to change. See generally Chinonye Obiagwu & Chidi Anselm Odinkalu, Combating Legacies
of Colonialism and Militarism, in HUMAN RIGHTS UNDER AFRICAN CONSTITUTIONS: REALIZING THE
PROMISE FOR OURSELVES 233 (Abdullahi Ahmed An-Na’im, ed., 2003) (asserting that only a “liberal
interpretation of locus standi will encourage public interest litigation” in Nigeria).
199
See generally Mirna E. Adjami, African Courts, International Law, and Comparative Case
Law: Chimera or Emerging Human Rights Jurisprudence?, 24 MICH. J. INT’L L. 103, 124 (2002)
(identifying what he referred to as the “insurmountable obstacles in developing a domestic human rights
jurisprudence” in African courts). Although the context of that discussion is civil and political rights, it
nonetheless finds relevance in the present discourse.
200
See e.g., Minister of Home Affairs v. Bickle, 1983 (2) Zimb. L. Rep. 400 (SC) (where the
Supreme Court of Zimbabwe struck down an emergency law that automatically forfeited the properties of
perceived “enemies” of the State); Katekwe v. Muchabaiwa, 1984 (2) Zimb. L. Rep. 112 (SC) (where the
Zimbabwean Supreme Court literally abolished the age-long customary rule that exclusively entitled
fathers to sue for seduction damages when their daughters were not yet married); Ephrahim v. Pastory,
(1990) LRC (Const.) 757 (where the Tanzanian High Court declared as invalid a rule of Haya customary
law that denies a woman the power to sell land. The court had held the customary law rule to be
unconstitutionally discriminatory”, id., at 764); Dow v. Att’y Gen. Bots. (1991) LRC (Const.) 574 (where
the Botswana Court of Appeal held that a statute that purported to deny citizenship to children of female
citizens married to alien fathers was discriminatory and therefore unconstitutional); New Patriotic Party v.
Insp. Gen. Police, [1992-1993] Ghana L. Rep. 87 (where the Supreme Court of Ghana held the Public
Order Decree, 1972 to be inconsistent with the constitutional freedoms of assembly and association. The
court had referred to the African Charter this way: “Ghana is a signatory [sic] to this African Charter. I do
not think that because Ghana has not passed specific legislation to give effect to the Charter, the Charter
cannot be relied upon”, id., per Archer, at 87); Longwe v. Intercontinental Hotels, (1993) L.R.C. 221
(where the Zambian High Court declared that the denial of access to the plaintiff into the bar of the hotel,
on the ground that she was female, amounted to unconstitutional violation of the non-discrimination and
equality provisions of the Zambian Constitution). See generally Grace Patrick Tumwine-Mukubwa, Ruled
from the Grave: Challenging Antiquated Constitutional Doctrines and Values in Commonwealth Africa, in
CONSTITUTIONALISM IN AFRICA: CREATING OPPORTUNITIES, FACING CHALLENGES 287, 301-302 (Joe
Oloka-Onyango, ed., 2001) (analyzing the impact of judicial activism on the domestic application of
international human rights norms through cases from Southern Africa).
48
problems,201 many African judicial institutions function under limitations that have
reduced human rights to abstract ideas, stultifying their appreciation as legal imperatives.
Some scholars have painted the reality of how societal perceptions about the
Ugandan judiciary have negatively affected ESCR promotion and protection.202
And in their careful scrutiny of housing rights and related litigation in Kenya,
Bodewes and Kwinga had described the judicial landscape as follows:
In Kenya, politics play a much more important role than the rule of law in
the area of housing and land disputes. The adjudication process, which
was intended to provide the necessary safety valve to protect the
rights…has totally collapsed under the massive weight of corruption. As a
result, the courts have turned a blind eye to both the unlawful and forced
evictions of residents…and have sanctioned the rabid land grabbing that is
endemic in Kenya today. In Kenya, there is a dearth of jurisprudence in
the area of housing rights….203
There can hardly be any realistic disputation that the above assessment broadly
epitomizes the stunted evolution of ESCR jurisprudence in Africa.
The aim of my extensive foray into the contemporary state of ESCR jurisprudence
in Africa is to identify trajectories for constitutional interpretative thrust that will promote
ESCR jurisprudence and invariably, a rights-based approach to democratization,
development and good governance in Africa. From the decisions examined, an inevitable
201
See generally EJAKAIT J.S.E. OPOLOT, A DISCOURSE ON JUST AND UNJUST LEGAL
INSTITUTIONS IN AFRICAN ENGLISH-SPEAKING COUNTRIES 25-91, 108-144, 203 (2002) (identifying
colonial legal heritage, anachronistic traditions of legal education, corruption, politicization of judicial
appointments as some of the most notable factors that have impeded effectual judicial response to human
rights in many African countries).
202
See Susan Dicklitch & Doreen Lwanga, The Politics of Being Non-Political: Human Rights
Organizations and the Creation of a Positive Human Rights Culture in Uganda, 25(2) HUM. RTS. Q. 482,
495 (2003). Indeed, a leading Ugandan human rights NGO had described the dysfunction of the Ugandan
judiciary this way: “[T]he judicial processes are poorly managed, funded, poorly coordinated and
susceptible to corrupting influences. As a result, public confidence in the justice system is undermined.
Economic, social and political conditions render the justice system irrelevant to the peoples’ needs who are
ignorant of their rights, formal laws and procedures of the systems.” Foundation for Human Rights
Initiatives, Striving for Justice 8 (2000), quoted in Dicklitch & Lwanga, id., at 493.
203
Christine Bodewes & Ndaise Kwinga, The Kenyan Perspective on Housing Rights, in
NATIONAL PERSPECTIVES ON HOUSING RIGHTS 221, 236 (Scott Leckie, ed., 2003).
49
inference emerges: that African juridical entities can no longer afford to be complacent in
the delivery of social justice whatever their ideological leanings might be. The path to
that lofty goal lies in the integrative approach to constitutional interpretation of human
rights.204
The consciousness would need to be strengthened among jurists and other
stakeholders in the administration of justice in Africa that in the whirlpool of the dynamic
social, economic, legal and policy complexities of contemporary Africa, their role as
interpreters and arbiters must be underpinned by a constant watch on the products of
democratization and governance. It can no longer be the norm that the judiciary should
insulate itself from social realities more so when it has become axiomatic that
considerable number of human groups and minorities – the homeless, HIV/AIDS patients
and orphans, disabled persons, the unemployed, the illiterate, rural dwellers, refugees,
children, the aged, people of ‘different’ sexual orientations – are often marginalized even
in a democratic set-up.205
As Bhagwati strongly admonished: “It is now being increasingly realised that civil and political
rights have no meaning and value unless they are accompanied by economic and social rights. This is
particularly important in Third World countries. We in the Third World countries have unique problems,
totally different from those in the Western countries…we in the Third World are trying to bring about
change in the social and economic conditions of the large masses of people with a view to uplifting them
from the quagmire of poverty and ignorance and so making basic human rights meaningful for them….”
See Bhagwati, Fundamental Rights in Their Economic, Social and Cultural Context, in DEVELOPING
HUMAN RIGHTS JURISPRUDENCE VOL. II 79, 82 (Commonwealth Secretariat & Interights, Second Judicial
Colloquium on the Domestic Application of International Human Rights Norms, 1989).
205
See generally Michael Kirby, The Role of the Judge in Advancing Human Rights by Reference
to International Human Rights Norms, in DEVELOPING HUMAN RIGHTS JURISPRUDENCE VOL. I 57, 81
(Commonwealth Secretariat & Interights, First Judicial Colloquium on the Domestic Application of
International Human Rights Norms, 1988) (stressing the empirical assertion that in the interplay of the
agencies and organs of modern government, democratic institutions do ignore or penalize “minorities or
marginal persons”). See also Maria Foscarinis, Downward Spiral: Homelessness and Criminalization,
14(1) YALE L. & DEV. POL’Y REV. 1 (1996).
204
50
VI.
CONCLUSIONS
As I already demonstrated, through progressive, expansive or proactive
interpretative techniques, many national judicial institutions have jettisoned the notion of
the non-justiciability of constitutional provisions implicating rights. In many of the
jurisdictions explored, the bulwark of opposition to proactive judicialism is crumbling,
giving way to efforts at rendering substantial (distributive) justice to vast populations.
Little wonder that Peretti argues that “[j]udicial activism and decision-making based on
personal political preference or calculations of political acceptability do not pose a great
threat to the Court’s power and independence. What does pose such a threat is extreme
judicial restraint or, alternatively, judicial activism accompanied by political insensitivity
and carelessness.”206
Reflecting on the Indian judiciary’s legendary breakaway from its earlier
conservatism to respond to the demands of social pressure and its implications for Africa,
now late Zimbabwean jurist, Dumbutshena had argued:
India has many more problems of poverty, ignorance and illiteracy that we
have in…Africa. Yet it is in India that judicial activism has changed the
face of justice…The question of delivery of justice to the disadvantaged
was paramount in the minds of Supreme Court judges. They reformed its
procedures and jurisdictional rules relating to constitutional and legal
rights of the poor classes who could not approach the court for redress of
their grievances…This was judicial activism at its best.207
If, therefore, by any figment of imagination, the responses of European and
American courts are considered peculiar to former colonialist/imperialist legal traditions
and thus objectionable, can the Indian approach be equally so assailed by African
scholars, jurists and activists? By no means.
206
TERRI JENNINGS PERETTI, IN DEFENSE OF A POLITICAL COURT 184 (1999).
Enoch Dumbutshena, Judicial Activism in the Quest for Justice and Equity, in THE JUDICIARY
IN AFRICA 185, 191-192 (Bola Ajibola & Deon van Zyl, eds., 1998) (emphasis added).
207
51
Without doubt, the gains of global socio-economic rights advocacy through the
jurisprudence of the South African courts cannot but be a veritable pointer to the capacity
of other African States to achieve tangible accomplishment in social justice delivery and
rights-based development if they are so willing.208 Herein lies the very heart of any
credible human rights and development agenda in Africa. The outcome of decisions like
Magaya v. Magaya209 clearly demonstrates the tragic consequences that non-activist
judiciaries portend for Africa and Africans.210
It now behoves African judges, courts, and lawyers as well as human rights
activists to take up the challenge of building a socially relevant and responsive rule-based
human rights system on the domestic fronts. For preliminaries, it will be most appropriate
for African judges, lawyers as well as human rights scholars and activists to ask
themselves the same question as Indian judges had asked themselves since the dark
emergency years until present time:
Can judges really escape addressing themselves to substantial questions of
social justice? Can they simply turn round to litigants who come to them
for justice and the general public that accords them power, status and
respect and tell them that they simply follow the legal text, when they are
aware that their actions will perpetuate inequity and injustice? Can they
208
It is noteworthy that since South Africa acceded to the African Charter, only one individual or
inter-state complaint has been brought against it before the African Commission, namely, Prince vs. South
Africa (2004) AHRLR 105 (ACHPR 2004). There is no gainsaying that this situation demonstrates the
robust output of the institutional structures, particularly the judiciary, in tackling the legal and
constitutional challenges for human rights in the relatively ‘new’ state.
209
[1999] 3 LRC 35 (Zimb.) (SC).
210
In this case, the Zimbabwean Supreme Court upheld a rule of customary law that denies a
woman heirship to her father’s estate. In this particular instance, the heirship passed to the appellant’s halfbrother, son of the late father’s second wife. In its outrageous decision, the Supreme Court held that
customary inheritance rules override the constitutional right to non-discrimination. For a scholarly critique
of this decision, see David M. Bigge et al, Conflict in Zimbabwean Courts: Women’s Rights and
Indigenous Self-Determination in Magaya v. Magaya, 13 HARV. HUM. RTS. J. 289 (2000). Equally
outrageous was the refusal of a Lagos State High Court in Nigeria to allow an HIV-positive litigant to enter
the courtroom to give evidence in her own case challenging her dismissal from employment on the ground
of her HIV status. The judge declined to listen to all arguments that HIV could not be transmitted by the
litigant’s entry into the courtroom. See, High Court Judge Denies Person Living With HIV/AIDS Access to
Court, SERAC@WORK, July 2001 (Magazine), at 1.
52
restrict their inquiry into law and life within the narrow confines of a
narrowly defined rule of law? Does the requirement of constitutionalism
not make greater demands on the judicial function?211
Even courts that were traditionally conservative are finding it no longer
problematic to identify discriminatory practices where there are any. Strikingly,
discrimination coupled with the denial of access to the necessities of life constitutes the
most problematic obstacle to meeting the goals of good governance, constitutionalism
and sustainable human rights culture in Africa.212
Apart from normative standardization, critical engagement with the integrative
human rights approach will facilitate the opportunity for judiciaries as well as quasijudicial bodies in Africa to develop appropriate remedies for all human rights obligations.
Since many ESCR issues are most likely to be fluid and dynamic, national courts would
be able to respond systematically, much like the Indian judiciary has done and is doing, in
rendering purposive constitutional justice to the aggrieved, deprived, marginalized, and
oppressed in Africa.
Far from being an ex cathedra pronouncement on all the dynamics that should
inform critical engagement with the concept of unenumerated rights in African states, this
essay would have fulfilled its purpose if it stimulates further scholarly scrutiny in that
direction.
211
Bhagwati, Fundamental Rights in Their Economic, Social and Cultural Context, VOL. I, supra
note 204, at 61.
212
See Tajudeen Abdul Raheem, Pan-Africanism and Constitutionalism, in CONSTITUTIONALISM
IN AFRICA: CREATING OPPORTUNITIES, FACING CHALLENGES 5255-57 (Joe Oloka-Onyango, ed., 2001).
53
Download