USES AND ABUSES OF PHILOSOPHY IN CHIROPRACTIC I.D. COULTER, PH.D. "It was the best of times, It was the worst of times, It was the age of wisdom, It was the age of foolishness, It was the epoch of incredulity." Charles Dickens A Tale of Two Cities In many ways, these lines by Dickens accurately portray the present state of philosophy in chiropractic. There is, on the positive side, a new interest in philosophy and a small, but active, group of scholars publishing papers in this area. Where Donahue could, in 1989, plead for annual conferences on philosophy (1), two such conferences have since occurred, at the Canadian Memorial Chiropractic College in 1990 and at Alice Springs, as part of the Chiropractic Association of Australia meeting in 1991. In both instances, the presented papers were published in refereed journals. Further, in 199 1, The National College of Chiropractic published its first Philosophical Constructs for the Chiropractic Profession and is currently publishing the second in this series. While it is too soon to predict what the impact of this activity will be on chiropractic, some major themes are already emerging. This paper will comment on two such items. THE NEW PERSPECTIVE ON PHILOSOPHY The first theme is an increasing recognition that chiropractors have abused the term "philosophy" to describe chiropractic. For the most part, what was described was not philosophy, or where it was, it was not chiropractic. Most of "chiropractic philosophy" turns out to be begged, borrowed, or stolen from elsewhere. Philosophies such as vitalism, holism, critical rationalism, etc, were neither developed by chiropractic nor unique to it. This has led several authors to suggest that there is no chiropractic philosophy, but that there could be, and perhaps should be, a philosophy of chiropractic (2-5). As McAndrews notes: "The meanings of the term philosophy are not, in my opinion, well understood by the profession. It has been so distorted by use in improper contexts, by use when assigned an inappropriate meaning and by being involved when the subject had little or nothing to do with philosophy (anecdotes about the effectiveness of chiropractic care) that an effort to trace its use back to a clear beginning is almost fruitless." (6) This situation led the present author to propose at the Australian Conference three philosophical propositions: 1. Chiropractic philosophy has no future. 2. Chiropractic philosophy has no past. 3. Chiropractic has no philosophy. (7) Disturbing as this might seem to most chiropractors, no other conclusion is possible to anyone who is either conversant with chiropractic history, and the origin of Palmer's ideas, or with philosophy. Writers, such as Kleynhans have gone further and suggested that even a philosophy of chiropractic is not possible. (8) The second major theme that is emerging is that the solution to this problem is not a retreat from philosophy, but a greater immersion in the fields of general philosophy on the part of chiropractors, and the application of these to chiropractic problems. That is, the solution is for the APPROPRIATE use of philosophy and not its abuse. Increasingly, the proposed candidate within the fields of philosophy is either the philosophy of the science of chiropractic (9-13) or a newly constructed philosophy of the science of chiropractic (6-14). The work of such philosophers as Thomas Kuhn is being utilized in this task of applying the philosophy of science to chiropractic (15 -22). THE CAUSES There is also an increasing understanding of why the abuse, rather than the use, of philosophy occurred. Part of it is historical. Palmer, for all his intellect, was himself confused about philosophy and its role and passed on this confusion to the profession (23, 24). Further, chiropractic philosophy emerged as a way of defending chiropractic in court and not as a fundamental exercise to clarify chiropractic thought. Under B.J. Palmer, the philosophical tenets became doctrine and dogma which were challenged only at the risk of challenging true chiropractic - the very antithesis of genuine philosophical inquiry (22- 24). The continuation of this unfortunate legacy was due in large part to chiropractic's intellectual and academic isolation. Had chiropractic formed part of mainstream university education, it would have been forced to develop a more sophisticated philosophical defense, or suffer the indignity of being laughed out of the academic court (25). The expression of the concerns of the new perspective is not itself new. Weiant had earlier suggested that the term chiropractic philosophy be abandoned since it described no academic discipline (26) and Eisenberg, as early as 1969, was using the general branches of philosophy - in particular, logic to both examine the philosophical defense of chiropractic and the fallacies in allopathic medicine's attack on chiropractic (27). Such writers as Watkins tried valiantly to erect a powerful philosophy based on science for clinical practice (28). But until recently these have tended to be isolated and lonely voices within the profession. The real philosophy was held to be that peddled by the metaphysical merchants and which amounted to little more than practice-building motivational seminars - all given by persons who, to steal a line from Donahue, would not know a principle from a prince. What has changed is the number of voices now being raised and the source of the voices. As Donahue has noted, traditionally the "philosophy" was left largely to those in the "straight" camp of chiropractic while the "mixers" tended, as a reaction, to deny the need for philosophy (1). Either rejecting, or embarrassed, by what was proffered as philosophy, they abandoned philosophy altogether and went in search of the Holy Grail of rational chiropractic, that is, science. The new voices, however, are increasingly from the camp of "rational" chiropractic. This traditional schism created a very false dichotomy in chiropractic between those who choose science verses those who choose philosophy, and the result has been described elsewhere as the chiropractic wars (2). Tragically for chiropractic, these never were philosophically alternative choices. The best of science is inextricably involved in philosophy and is inherently metaphysical (25). On the other side, metaphysical beliefs are heuristically more useful in an applied field when tied to science and placed within rational discourse. All the physical structures ever built by humankind from the pyramids of ancient Egypt to the San Francisco Harbor bridge contest to this principle. The sciences underlying the structures, such as euclidean geometry, are not metaphysically free, but metaphysics made useful. DOES IT MATTER There is a tendency amongst practitioners to write off such discussions as academic exercises having no importance for them or their practice. Two considerations of chiropractic will make the illogicality of this stance obvious. Quite clearly, the conspiracy by medicine against chiropractic hurt us (and was judged to have done so by the courts or the injunction against medicine would never have been issued). At the very heart of the attack of medicine, and the way it was portrayed publicly, was the claim that chiropractic was unscientific and that allopathic medicine was scientific. Anyone familiar with the philosophy of science at least from the 1930s with the introduction of the work of Sir Karl Popper, would have known that the attempt by philosophers to demarcate science from science (despite Popper) had failed. Furthermore, they would have also known that medicine's claim to be a science had no epistemological base. It is not that chiropractors did not suspect both of these things, and some may have even understood them, but they lacked both the philosophical sophistication or credibility to mount a successful challenge. Furthermore, so called "chiropractic philosophy" was totally incapable of providing the intellectual weaponry for a successful counter attack. Chiropractors, for the most part, made the intellectual mistake that this was a battle about scientific research and either capitulated in the face of the total lack of chiropractic research (on the grounds that medicine was right) or turned to a form of rationalism that was in essence anti-scientific and which said, in effect, that we do not need research since our patients prove every day that chiropractic works. Chiropractic attempted to fight a philosophical battle on the basis of patient testimonials. It is little wonder that medicine was largely successful in this battle since chiropractic failed to correctly identify the nature of the battle, the weapons with which to fight it, or the strategies to win. Instead, it fell back on its only defense, the use of politics. While this did allow chiropractic to survive, it is often been falsely interpreted by chiropractors as a victory. One only has to enter any university in the land and begin a conversation with the science faculty about chiropractic to understand the terrible damage medicine's philosophical attack continues to inflict on the perception of chiropractic. One result of this attack was to force chiropractic to become more "scientific," but in the sense of including more science in the curriculum. Keating has correctly identified this as a response and has termed it a flight into rationalism although the present author would term it rationalization not rationalism (29). Perhaps, even more important, was the confusion that has been created within the public and the patients of what chiropractic is. For most of their history, chiropractors have identified themselves in two philosophical camps, straights and mixers, and have done considerable battle under these banners as if they meant something important - worth living or dying professionally for. In the Canadian study of chiropractors, the researchers attempted to investigate the importance of these philosophical camps to both the chiropractors and the patients (30). Each chiropractor was asked to identify which camp he felt he belonged to, that is, whether they would describe themselves as predominantly straight or mixed (no definition of the terms were given). Furthermore, each chiropractor, at the end of the study, was asked to give his/her definition of chiropractic and these were coded according to the elements that were stressed. The results are shown in Table 1. In Table 1, the first column gives the percentage of the total sample of chiropractors who stressed, for example, philosophy; the second column gives the percentage of those who described themselves as mixers who stressed philosophy, and column three, the percentage of straights who did. The first obvious conclusion from Table I is that the groups are not that distinguishable in terms of how they define chiropractic and that in neither group is the philosophical element the one most stressed. This is a result somewhat at odds with the rhetoric of chiropractic which would have us believe that straights and mixers have fundamentally different definitions of chiropractic. However, even more interesting was the result that of those giving essentially a straight definition of chiropractic (as judged by the researchers), 47 percent were self-described mixers. Conversely, of those giving an eclectic definition of chiropractic, 46 percent were self- described straights. Whatever else these camps do in chiropractic, it would appear that giving concise, clear, and distinct definitions of chiropractic is not one of them. A further question tapped the extent to which the chiropractor used philosophy to explain the illness and treatment of the patients, and for the justification of chiropractic. The study also asked the patients to describe chiropractic. Their responses, like the chiropractors, were coded with regard to whether they included any thing about the philosophy etc. of chiropractic. The relevant information is given in Table 11. In the table, the first column gives the percentage of the chiropractors who stressed philosophy in explaining the illness; those who used philosophy to justify chiropractic are in column two. The third column gives the percentage of patients who utilized any philosophy etc. in describing chiropractic. The data in Table 11 (not included) indicate that philosophy is used much more by chiropractors to justify chiropractic than to explain illness or treatment which supports the contention that it traditionally was introduced more for this reason than for anything else. More importantly, however, is the fact that very little of the philosophy gets through to the patient or is utilized by them in explaining what chiropractic is. If chiropractic is truly an alternative health philosophy, then it is apparent that the patients are unable to articulate what chiropractic philosophy is. It is this lack of philosophical clarity amongst chiropractors themselves that almost guarantees that the patients, the public, and the politicians will have only the vaguest idea of "chiropractic philosophy," That which defies clarification, definition, and articulation generally also defies communication. USE OF PHILOSOPHY The solution to the problem of abuse is not that complicated. It requires recognizing that philosophy is an activity not a doctrine. Further, it is a reflective activity whose purpose is clarification of thought. It does this through a process of critical reflection and conceptual analysis, that is, by subjecting all the concepts of a discipline to rigorous critique. Ladd proposes four propositions for philosophy: 1. Philosophy is always the philosophy of something: it has no subject matter of its own; hence we have a philosophy of law, of science, of education, of chiropractic 2. Philosophy inevitably and necessarily implies a critical evaluation of concepts and the structures in which they are framed 3. Philosophy is problem-oriented; in fact, it exists to solve problems 4. Philosophy is inexorably controversial (3 1) Once the nature and purpose of philosophy is understood, the second requirement is that chiropractors become educated in philosophy at least to the same level that they now are in the biological sciences. This would require at a very minimum that they receive an introduction to the various branches of philosophy such as metaphysics, logic, ethics, aesthetics, epistemology and the fields most relevant to chiropractic, such as the philosophy of science. However, if all that occurs is that some courses in philosophy are added to the curriculum, while our graduates will at least be more literate in philosophy, we will be repeating the problem alluded to earlier with the basic sciences: rationalism. Therefore, a third step requires that at least some of the profession become engaged in the application of philosophy to chiropractic problems. Bernard Shaw, in his play Major Barbara, berates the morality of the Salvation Army taking money from an armament manufacturer. Major Barbara's response is that they are only too happy to get the money out of the manufacturer's hands and into the hands of the Lord where it will do some good. Chiropractors similarly need to get philosophy into the hands of some chiropractors where it can do some good for chiropractic. The purpose in all this is not to stifle debate, but to stimulate it. No concepts should be ruled as a priori valid or invalid but each should be subjected to debate within a rational discourse. Those that survive such an intellectual baptism of fire will strengthen the profession; those that do not hopefully will not survive. Our concepts would emerge stronger, clearer and defended by intellectually respectable argumentation. As Bachop has noted, in its present form, the concept of innate is a form of word game whereby chiropractors assume that by naming something they have, by that act, explained it (32). He also notes that the argument in favor of the concept is a tautology; that it is true by definition and is therefore an analytic statement. Unfortunately for chiropractors, when they invoke the concept of innate, they mean it to say something true about the body and health, that is, they intend it as a true statement about the real world. Logicians have already shown that analytic statements are definitionally true irrespective of what may be true in the world. For example, "all men are men" is a definitionally true statement since there is no definition of man that would make it untrue. This would mean, for example, if one man was in fact a wolf, the statement would still be true. If one wishes to make an empirical statement about the world, it cannot be made (logically) as an analytic statement. A philosopher would therefore be legitimate in asking what do chiropractors posit the concept innate as? Do you intend it as a truthful statement about the world? If so, you cannot frame it as an analytic statement or defend it with a tautology. Empirical statements must, of necessity, allow for the possibility of being untrue. Of course the truth is most chiropractors have no notion of what kind of concept it is. It is for this reason that Donahue concluded that the concept could not survive the critical evaluation of an undergraduate student in philosophy (33). This is not, as some other chiropractors would have it, a defeat of the metaphysical/philosophical system underlying the concept of the innate (i.e. vitalism), but simply a defeat of the inappropriate way it has been formulated and used in chiropractic. CONCLUSION This conclusion is more in the form of a plea. Neither of the broad philosophical camps in chiropractic, irrespective of how they are labeled, straights versus mixes, traditionalist versus eclectic, rationalists versus innatists, scientists versus intuitive - has been immune from the abuse of philosophy. We might usefully adopt a biblical approach and announce a plague on both their houses. As the author has noted previously, not only are they both wrong with regard to philosophy, they are both wrong for the same reason: ignorance (2). What needs to emerge is scholars in chiropractic that are philosophers. I mean persons literate in philosophy, who understand the crucial debates occurring within the fields of philosophy, and who are themselves engaged philosophically in the important issues of chiropractic. One does not become a great scientist by observing science, reading science, or talking to scientists. One becomes a great scientist by doing science. It is this doing of philosophy that chiropractic needs to get on with. To illustrate this point, several chiropractic authors have now invoked the concept of paradigm of Thomas Kuhn to describe chiropractic. However, to date, none of this work has been done within the critical debate that surrounds Kuhn's work within philosophy (20). Kleynhans has made an excellent suggestion that the positive-empiricist paradigm of contemporary science is inappropriate for understanding the doctor-patient relationship and that phenomenology is a more appropriate paradigm (34). But phenomenology itself has been widely discussed and critiqued, within the social sciences along with other nominalist paradigms such as symbolic interactionism and ethnomethodology. To adopt these concepts or paradigms without immersing ourselves in these debates will simply move chiropractic from the philosophical fat to the philosophical fire. Chiropractic could usefully learn from other disciplines in examining how they have used philosophy for similar problems (35). Further, they need to relate these issues to the task of deriving both a philosophy of health and a philosophy of chiropractic health care that is logically consistent with the former, and derivable from it (36). Such work is time consuming and often tedious. Those doing it must also continue to eat, earn a living, and for the most part, do other things to survive. In chiropractic, at present, philosophy more resembles a hobby than a career. It is possible to get research grants and support; it is even possible to create a research career of sorts in chiropractic. Your articles will get published in refereed journals. No such support is available for philosophers, and while the articles will probably get published, they will be in the commentary section where the implication is that they are somehow less important, or took less work, than original research. In the author's experience, philosophical writing is much more onerous than scientific writing. It requires, as a prerequisite, much more reading in more diverse areas of scholarship. Any who doubt this are directed to review the leading philosophical journals and merely look at the footnotes for the articles which in themselves are frequently longer than many scientific papers. It requires a greater demand for clarity, logical consistency, and coherence, particularly since philosophy claims as its purpose the clarification of thought and is therefore hoist by its own petard. To paraphrase Ben Jonson, one should not wonder that it is not done well; one should wonder that it is done at all. And at the end of it all, you are almost certain, in the words of Charlton, to get up the collective noses of the profession, but philosophy to which persons are indifferent to would be no philosophy at all. There lies the dilemma of the philosopher. How does one convince his/her professional peers to support them in an exercise in which he/she will challenge all the ideas they hold dear; suggest they reject much of what they have learned as illogical, irrelevant, or philosophically illiterate; and expect to get thanked, paid and honored for doing so Perhaps they might turn to philosophy for comfort: "Philosophy is that which enables the rich to say there is no disgrace in being poor." "Philosophy is the study which enables man to be unhappy more intelligently."