Philosophy and science: Putnam and Friedman 1. Putnam and the rejection of the “thing-in-itself” Recognizing the Kantian influence on his work (“my indebtedness to Kant is very large” – Putnam, Realism with a Human Face, 1990, p. 3) Putnam is antifoundationalist, i.e. he rejects “metaphysical necessity” (see “Is Water necessarily H2O?” in Putnam 1990) and he puts forward internal realism. Along the same lines as Goodman, but avoiding the relativism, Putnam rejects the absolutist picture of the world to be found in realism. Different languages, different theories, and different representations have the same value in different contexts. “In my picture, objects are theory-dependent in the sense that theories with incompatible ontologies can both be right.” (Putnam 1990, p. 30) Both language and science are deeply pluralistic in their ontology. For Putnam absolute realism or foundationalism has no sense. “I criticize the idea that the world picture of fundamental physics is metaphysically complete.” (see “Is the causal structure of the physical itself something physical?” in Putnam 1990, p. 95) Like Quine, Putnam accepts that stars, tables and micro-particles “exist” only because we can describe all these things in different conceptual schemes. Thus the concept of existence has to be related to conceptual frames. For Putnam, the question “How many objects really exist?” is an illusion. (Putnam 1987, p. 20) In fact the conceptual schemes are very similar to Carnap’s linguistic frameworks. Putnam internal realism (see “I should have called it pragmatic realism!” Putnam 1987, p. 17) rejects the notion of the thing-in-itself”. (Putnam 1987, p. 36) In this sense, realism is not incompatible with conceptual relativism. (Putnam 1987, p. 1 17) Again, from the EDWs perspective, there is the same problematic relationship between the world and the so-called “relative concepts” or “relative descriptions”. Conceptual schemes are empty in describing different entities that belong to the unicorn-world. As we shall see in the next section they are missing a kind of Kantian constitutive framework. Putnam asserts that assuming that there is a “thing-in-itself” presupposes a view from an “Archimedean point”. In this case it is about an ideal or impersonal knowledge. The same notion of a “God’s Eye View”, the same epistemic ideal of achieving a view from an “Archimedean point”—a point from which we can survey observers as if they were not ourselves, survey them as if we were, so to speak, outside our own skins—is involved in both cases. The same notion that ideal knowledge is impersonal is involved. (Putnam 1990, p. 17) 2. Friedman’s relative constitutive a priori principles Friedman re-introduced and developed Reichenbach’s notion of relativized a priori principles in explaining Newton’s and Einstein’s theories from mathematical physics. He replaces Quine’s holism of belief with a dynamical and stratified system of knowledge constituted on three levels: (1) empirical laws of nature (like Newtonian laws of universal gravitation or Einstein’s equation for the gravitational field; (2) constitutive a priori principles, such as principles from geometry and mechanics that construct paradigms (in Kuhn’s sense) or conceptual frameworks and “define the fundamental spatio-temporal framework within which alone the rigorous formulation and empirical testing of the first or base level principles is then possible”; and (3) 2 philosophical meta-paradigms or meta-frameworks that guide the transition from one paradigm or conceptual framework to another. (Friedman 2001, pp. 45–6) Extrapolating Kant’s idea, Friedman considers that a priori constitutive principles define “the fundamental spatio-temporal framework of empirical natural science.” (Friedman 2001, p. 43) For each scientific theory there are certain a priori constitutive principles that define its proper space of empirical possibilities. (Friedman 2001, p. 84) Extrapolating Kant’s idea, Friedman considers that a priori constitutive principles define “the fundamental spatiotemporal framework of empirical natural science”. (2001, p. 43) For each scientific theory there are certain a priori constitutive principles that define its proper space of empirical possibilities. (Friedman 2001, p. 84) However, the question is how we can define “the space of empirical possibilities” for each individual theory. In addressing this question, let us see how Friedman explains Newton’s and Einstein’s theories within his framework. Newtonian mechanics and Einstein’s theory of relativity contain two parts: (1) the empirical part containing such laws as universal gravitation or Einstein’s equations for the gravitational field; (2) the constitutively a priori part containing both mathematical principles utilized for constructing the theory (Euclidian geometry vs. the geometry of Minkovski’s spacetime, the Riemannian theory of manifolds) and fundamental physical principles or the “mechanical part” (the Newtonian laws of motion vs. the light principle, the equivalence principle). (Friedman 2001, p. 71)1 Newton’s and Einstein’s theories offer us different spatio-temporal structures. There are different reasons for which we cannot even compare these two theories. Einstein has transformed the light principle that was an empirical principle We have to recall that, in Parvu’s interpretation, for Kant, the “condition of possibility” appears at two levels: mathematical (axioms of intuition and anticipations of perception) and physical (analogies of experience, i.e. the transcendental laws of nature). 1 3 for Newton into a constitutively a priori one. “Einstein has ‘elevated’ an empirical law to the status of a convention or to the status of a coordinating or constitutive principle”. (Friedman 2001, p. 88) Within the special theory of relativity the spatiotemporal framework is Minkovski’s four-dimensional space-time.2 If in Newton’s theory the gravitational force is independent of inertial mass, in the general theory of relativity they are equivalent. “The inertial structure is defined in terms of ‘freefalling’ trajectories in a gravitational field” and so the “gravitational force is directly incorporated into the geometry of space-time and thus into the constitutive framework of our theory.” (Friedman 2001, pp. 89–91) In Newton’s period, people could not even conceive certain notions from Einstein’s theory. The general theory of relativity requires a different spatio-temporal framework than the one postulated by Newton’s theory. In this sense, Friedman presents “three revolutionary advances”: a new field of mathematics, tensor calculus or the general theory of manifolds (originally elaborated by Riemann), Einstein’s principle of equivalence, and his equations for the gravitational field. (Friedman 2001, pp. 37-8) The principle of equivalence and Einstein’s field equations require a curved space-time structure. Thus geometry “functions” as part of the constitutive framework for our experience. (Friedman 2001, p. 62) The constitutive a priori part establishes knowledge about experience and in this sense “they are a priori to or independent of experience.” (Friedman 2001, p. 73) The a priori physical principles (mechanical part) mediate between abstract mathematical tools and empirical phenomena. The function of this mechanical part is to create, in one mathematical-physical theory, “… for Einstein uses his light principle empirically to define a fundamentally new notion of simultaneity and, as a consequence, fundamentally new metrical structures for both space and time (more precisely, for space-time).” (Friedman 2001, p. 88) Friedman shows that the principle of equivalence has the same status within the general theory. The empirical content of the general theory is given by the application of the principle of equivalence to the inertial structure of Minkovski’s space-time. (Friedman 2001, p. 115) Friedman mentions that this idea is from Norton 1985/1989. 2 4 the necessary link between two parts with different structures: abstract and empirical. But a legitimate question here would be what exactly this concept of the “empirical part” designates? For Einstein, the coordinating principles constitute a new framework for space, time, and motion (Friedman 2001, p. 107) and therefore all the empirical laws have constitutive meaning only in the framework created by a priori constitutive principles. Even the individuation of entities requires such conceptual frameworks. 3 That is necessary not only because the entities that are in motion belong to a certain spatio-temporal framework, but also because “the knowledge of physical rigidity presupposes the knowledge of forces acting on the material constitutions of bodies.” (Friedman 2001, p. 110) For describing these forces it is a necessary geometry. Essential for Friedman’s perspective is his footnote on page 55 about Einstein, who adopted a perspective on the relationship between this necessary geometry and the entities as “practicall y rigid bodies” that ignores microphysical forces. (Friedman 2001, p. 114) The frame of reference for both theories is given by space, time, and motion but the theories refer to the same entities even if we can individuate empirical objects and their relationship only through such constitutional frameworks. In fact, the spatiotemporal structures of these theories are different mainly regarding their metric. Empirical tests – the perihelion of Mercury – supported Einstein’s theory. “The transcendental laws of nature” are, for Kant, the analogies of experience that determine the formal Nature. (See 2.3) 3 5