Ethical and Epistemic Egoism and the Ideal of Autonomy Linda Zagzebski Abstract In this paper I distinguish three degrees of epistemic egoism, each of which has an ethical analogue, and I argue that all three are incoherent. Since epistemic autonomy is frequently identified with one of these forms of epistemic egoism, it follows that epistemic autonomy as commonly understood is incoherent. I end with a brief discussion of the idea of moral autonomy and suggest that its component of epistemic autonomy in the realm of the moral is problematic. i In this paper I argue that the ideal of epistemic autonomy is incoherent. I’ll begin with an exploration of three forms of epistemic egoism, each of which has an ethical analogue, and will argue that each form of epistemic egoism is inconsistent. Given that epistemic autonomy is often described in a way that makes it indistinguishable from epistemic egoism, it follows that epistemic autonomy as widely understood is incoherent. I will end by raising some questions about the coherence of autonomy in the moral sense. Let us begin with the strongest form of epistemic egoism, the position I will call extreme epistemic egoism.1 The extreme epistemic egoist maintains 1 This is the position Richard Foley (2001) calls “epistemic egotism,” but he drops the 1 that the fact that someone else has a belief is never a reason for her to believe it, not even when conjoined with evidence that the other person is reliable. If she finds out that someone else believes p, she will demand proof of p that she can determine by the use of her own faculties, given her own previous beliefs, but she will never believe anything on testimony. Similarly, the extreme ethical egoist maintains that the fact that someone else has an interest is never a reason for her to take it into account when she acts. She will act for the sake of the interests of others only if it can be demonstrated to her that doing so serves her own interests.2 So the extreme epistemic egoist puts no epistemic value on the beliefs of others. The fact that another person has a belief does not count in her considerations about what to believe. Similarly, the extreme ethical egoist puts no practical or moral value on the interests of others. The fact that another person has an interest does not count in her own desires or practical considerations. Extreme ethical egoism is very implausible and it is hard to find a philosopher who endorses it, but many philosophers have endorsed extreme term in Foley (2005). The term “egotism” is probably not apt because “egotism” as it is used in ethics has more to do with the way a person assesses her own importance than with the way she treats her interests relative to the interests of others. 2 By “interests” I mean to include desires, aims, values, and things we care about. I do not mean to limit interests to what is good for one. 2 epistemic egoism, although of course, it would not be usual to call it by that name. Elizabeth Fricker describes epistemic autonomy as follows: “This ideal type relies on no one else for any of her knowledge. Thus she takes no one else’s word for anything, but accepts only what she has found out for herself, relying only on her own cognitive faculties and investigative and inferential powers.” (Fricker, p. 225) Notice that what Fricker calls “epistemic autonomy” is the same as what I am calling “extreme epistemic egoism.” Fricker finds the idea that one should trust one’s own epistemic faculties and beliefs but not those of another laudatory and cites Descartes, Locke and others as supporting it.3 Her objection is that it is impractical; we would have very little knowledge if we could not rely upon testimony. A superior being could do so, however, and such a being would be superior for being able to do so. Fricker says: ..a superior being, with all the epistemic powers to find out everything she wanted to know for herself, could live up to this idea of complete epistemic autonomy without thereby circumscribing the extent of her knowledge. Given the risks involved in epistemic dependence on others,.. this superior being is, I suppose, epistemically better placed than humans are. That is, if she knew at first hand just as much as I myself 3 Fricker could have found much earlier support in Plato’s Theaetetus (201B/C) where Socrates claims that the jury members in a court case do not know what the eyewitness knows because the jury believes only by “hearsay” (ex akoes). 3 know in large part through trust in others’ testimony, she would be epistemically more secure, hence both practically more independent, and– in some abstract sense– more autonomous than I am. In the same way that I might regret that I cannot fly, or live to be 300 years old, I might regret that I am not such a being. (p. 243). Fricker’s suggestion here seems to be that extreme epistemic egoism would be an ideal if we could live up to it, but it is undesirable because of our limitations. The need for epistemic trust is thus due to our inferiority. An extreme epistemic egoist with superior epistemic powers would not need epistemic trust in others, and she would be epistemically superior to us. Why does extreme epistemic egoism seem like an ideal under the name “epistemic autonomy,” whereas extreme ethical egoism is quite the opposite? Fricker’s remarks above suggest a partial answer. Ethical and epistemic egoism differ in their relations to trust. One does not need to trust another person in order to take into account her desires, interests, and aims, whereas it is necessary to trust the epistemic faculties and belief-forming history of others in order to take their beliefs into account in forming one’s own beliefs. So suspicion of the trustworthiness of others is a consideration in favor of extreme epistemic egoism, whereas it has no relation at all to the acceptance or rejection of extreme ethical egoism. But even if worries about trust make extreme epistemic egoism more acceptable than extreme ethical egoism, that does not explain why many 4 philosophers treat extreme epistemic egoism as an ideal. If the problem with trust is that it leaves us epistemically insecure, given that many people are untrustworthy, why should I be any more secure if I rely upon myself? I do not have evidence that I am more trustworthy than all other people. For one thing, it is impossible for me to obtain evidence of my trustworthiness as a whole since I have to use my faculties and previous beliefs in order to gather and evaluate the evidence, so it is in principle impossible for me to have evidence that as a whole I am more trustworthy than all other people. By relying upon my powers, I do have evidence that many other people are untrustworthy, but why should that lead me to fall back on my own powers? Using those same powers, I also have evidence that I am sometimes untrustworthy, and I have evidence that in some domains some other people are more trustworthy than I am. As far as I can see, fear of untrustworthiness can make us epistemically insecure, but it does not support extreme epistemic egoism. Furthermore, if the untrustworthiness of others is the ground of the ideal of autonomy/extreme egoism, that does not explain why the ideal is not one in which persons are epistemically dependent upon perfectly trustworthy other persons. Suppose we compare an imaginary community of epistemically trustworthy persons who collectively acquire the same range of knowledge as Fricker’s imaginary superior individual. Would the epistemically autonomous individual still be superior to a member of the superior trustworthy community? If epistemic autonomy is really an ideal, the answer would have to 5 be yes, but I do not know what the support for that would be. A second form of epistemic egoism is the position we can call strong epistemic egoism. The strong epistemic egoist maintains that she has no obligation to count what another person believes as relevant to her own beliefs, but she may do so if she sees that given what she believes about them, they are likely to serve her desire for the truth, that is, she sees that they are reliable. Similarly, according to the strong ethical egoist, she has no obligation to count the interests of another as relevant to her practical considerations. She might count their interests as relevant if she sees that there is a reliable connection between serving their interests and serving her own interests, but she acknowledges no obligation to do that. So the strong ethical egoist maintains that she has no unchosen obligation to desire what another person desires because he desires it, and the strong epistemic egoist maintains that she has no unchosen obligation to believe what another person believes because he believes it. The strong epistemic egoist will believe on testimony only when she believes the testifier is reliable based on the use of her own faculties and reference to her own previous beliefs, but she acknowledges no obligation to do so. In the same way, the strong ethical egoist will desire what someone else desires only when she sees that doing so is instrumentally connected to satisfying her own desires, but she acknowledges no obligation to do so. There is a third form of epistemic egoism that I find interesting. What I 6 call the weak epistemic egoist is someone who maintains that when one has evidence that someone else’s beliefs reliably serve one’s desire for the truth in some domain, one is not only rationally permitted, one is rationally required to take their beliefs into account in forming one’s own beliefs.4 Likewise, the weak ethical egoist is a person who maintains that one is rationally required to take into account the interests of others in those cases in which she has evidence that serving their interests serves her own interests. Otherwise, she has no obligation to care about anyone else’s interests. Although strong and weak ethical egoism are not as implausible as extreme ethical egotism, I assume that both are implausible, and I do not think there are many philosophers who have defended either one. In contrast, strong or weak epistemic egoism appeals to those who uphold the ideal of epistemic autonomy because it preserves fundamental dependence upon oneself while conceding the fact that we must rely upon the testimony of others for much of what we believe and know. I interpret Elizabeth Fricker as defending a version of weak epistemic egoism. Fricker argues for a principle of testimony according to which one properly accepts a proposition on the basis of testimony only if 4 Foley (2001) discusses epistemic egoism and its ethical parallel, but does not mention what I call weak egoism. 7 one correctly recognizes that the testifier is epistemically better placed than oneself with respect to the proposition in question. That makes her position a version of epistemic egoism. Fricker goes on to argue that in such cases it is not merely rationally permissible, it is in fact rationally mandatory to defer to the other person. That makes her a weak epistemic egoist.5 One reason to accept epistemic egoism, then, is the desire to retain autonomy as far as possible while having a healthy amount of knowledge, but it is hard to see why we should accept epistemic egoism as an ideal. We have already seen that egoism cannot be defended on the grounds that I am more trustworthy than others since I have no reason to believe that. Perhaps the reason is that I must rely on my own powers, but I have a choice about whether to rely on the powers of others. It is true that reliance upon my own faculties and previous beliefs is inescapable, whereas reliance upon others can be escaped if one is willing to give up many beliefs. But that does not support the position that it is better for me to rely upon my own powers above those of 5 Fricker defends a Testimony Deferential Principle paraphrased as follows: A hearer, H, properly accepts that P on the basis of trust in a speaker, S’s testimony that P, if and only if S speaks sincerely, and S is epistemically well enough placed with respect to P to be in a position to know that P, and S is better epistemically placed with respect to P than H, and there is no equally well-qualified contrary testimony regarding P, and H recognizes all these things to be so. (p. 232). 8 others. If some form of epistemic egoism is an ideal, that cannot be defended on the grounds that it is good for me to do only what I must do in any case. That would be very implausible. The result is that both strong and weak epistemic egoism are just as puzzling as extreme epistemic egoism. All three forms of egoism propose an ideal of epistemic autonomy that needs defense, and all three forms have problematic ethical analogues. ii So far we have not seen a reason to accept epistemic autonomy as an ideal if it is identified with one of the three forms of epistemic egoism, but we do not yet have a reason to reject epistemic autonomy/egoism either. Perhaps there is some other reason to treat epistemic egoism as an ideal that I have not mentioned, or perhaps epistemic egoism is a plausible position, even if not an ideal. But I want now to argue that the demands of consistency push the epistemic egoist into weaker and weaker forms of egoism, forcing her eventually to reject egoism. None of the three forms of epistemic egoism can be coherently maintained. The extreme epistemic egoist trusts only her own powers and previous beliefs as a means to getting further true beliefs and knowledge. But if she lives in a universe similar to our own, the use of her own powers will show her that there are other people who are trustworthy means for giving her the truth. She finds out that other people are reliable in the same way she finds out that the grass will grow-- by perception and induction. It takes a further use of her 9 powers to infer that a particular belief of a particular other person is probably true, but there is no difference in principle between that inference and many other inferences she makes routinely and routinely trusts as an extreme egoist. So by using her own powers she sees that she is permitted to trust the powers and beliefs of many other people, and she begins to accept some beliefs on testimony. Trust in her own powers requires her to weaken her extreme egoism and to become a strong epistemic egoist. However, if she were only permitted and not required to trust these people, she would have to have a reason not to trust them based on her own powers and beliefs. That might happen in some cases. Perhaps the beliefs of trustworthy others conflict with each other or with her own beliefs, or maybe the exercise of her faculties gives her conflicting verdicts on the trustworthiness of another. But again, if she is living in a universe anything like our own, there will be many cases in which there is no such conflict. By using her own powers and relying on her own previous beliefs, she will see that certain other people are trustworthy sources of truth on some occasion, and there is no reason not to trust them. The use of her own faculties leads her to see that trusting them is mandatory, not optional. She is then required by a consistent trust in her own faculties to become a weak epistemic egoist. Let us now look at the reasonableness of weak epistemic egoism. What distinguishes egoism in general from its rejection is that all else being equal, the egoist puts greater trust in her own faculties than in the faculties of others. 10 As we have already seen, the egoist does not have evidence that she is a more trustworthy epistemic agent than many others in relevantly similar situations. She has evidence that she is more trustworthy than some others in some domains and less trustworthy than some others in some domains, but she does not have evidence that she is more trustworthy on the whole than all other people; nobody has such evidence. She therefore lacks evidence for her egoism. But the lack of evidence for egoism is not sufficient to show that egoism is unreasonable. After all, I lack evidence that my faculties as a whole are trustworthy, but I assume that it is reasonable to have basic trust in my faculties as a whole. Why couldn’t egoism be reasonable in the same way basic self-trust is reasonable? I want now to argue that epistemic egoism is inconsistent with the egoist’s own standards. I am interpreting the epistemic egoist as someone who cares about the truth. She trusts only her own faculties and the faculties of others whose reliability she has discovered through the use of her own faculties because she believes that that is the best way to get the truth. Since she cares about truth, she commits herself to being a conscientious believer, one whose epistemic behavior is governed by caring for the truth, and it is rational for her to trust herself when she is conscientious. She also has evidence that she gets the truth when she is conscientious, but like everybody else, she must trust herself in advance of the evidence since she must trust herself in order to collect and evaluate the evidence. So the rational epistemic egoist trusts herself 11 when she is conscientious in attempting to get the truth, and this trust is not based on evidence of her trustworthiness. Now if the epistemic egoist is rational, she is committed to trusting others when they are conscientious, when they have the qualities she trusts in herself. Trusting herself commits her to trusting others when they are in the same position she is in; that is, when they are in similar circumstances, have apparently similar powers and abilities, and act as conscientiously as she acts when she trusts herself. If she is consistent, she must trust them as much as herself, other things being equal, since she has no basis upon which to trust herself more than those she perceives to be epistemically equally well-placed. Let me stress that she is not committed to trusting them because she has evidence that they are trustworthy. She is committed to trusting them because there is no relevant difference between her grounds for trusting herself and her grounds for trusting them. Assuming it is reasonable to trust herself, it is reasonable to trust others. If she insists upon trusting herself– her faculties, beliefs, and emotions-- more than others, she must be trusting her faculties, beliefs, and emotions just because they are her own and not someone else’s. She cannot consistently do that if she thinks there is any reason to trust herself. Any reason she can point to is a reason that applies to many others. There is the possibility that she trusts herself and distrusts others without any reason other than the fact that her own powers and beliefs are hers and the powers and beliefs of others are not hers. But if that is what she 12 is doing, she is valuing her own powers more than the truth. When she has to choose between relying upon her own powers and beliefs without trusting others, and relying upon others when she finds by the use of her own powers that relying upon them is the way to truth, she will choose the former. Such a person is not an epistemic egoist. Rather, she is an extreme ethical egoist in the realm of the intellect. I have not given any arguments against ethical egoism in this paper, but I doubt that many philosophers would want to accept epistemic egoism at the cost of commitment to extreme ethical egoism of this sort. Assuming that the latter position is unacceptable, all three forms of epistemic egoism should be rejected. Richard Foley offers a different argument that epistemic egoism is incoherent. Foley begins with an observation we have already discussed: a normal, non-skeptical life requires a significant degree of self-trust since there are no non-circular tests of the reliability of our faculties and opinions as a whole (2001, p. 99). Foley then argues that if I have self-trust, I must trust those from whom I acquired my beliefs. That is because I would not be reliable unless they are. In fact, I am not only committed to trusting my precursors, I am committed to trusting my contemporaries since they acquired their beliefs from roughly the same sources from which I acquired mine (p. 102). That is enough to make the three forms of epistemic egoism incompatible with self-trust, and since self-trust is a rational requirement, the rejection of epistemic egoism is a rational requirement. We therefore have a prima facie 13 reason to believe whatever these other people believe in advance of evidence for their reliability. We should trust them for roughly the same reason we trust ourselves. Foley goes on to argue that self-trust commits us to widening the scope of epistemic trust even farther. Since people all over the world at all times are more similar than dissimilar in their faculties and environment, the fact that some person somewhere at some time has a certain belief gives me a prima facie reason to believe it myself. This is the position Foley calls epistemic universalism (pp. 103-5). According to the epistemic universalist, the fact that another person has a belief is a mark in favor of its credibility, no matter who the person is. The epistemic universalist always treats the fact that another person has a belief as a reason to believe it herself, but that reason can be defeated by evidence of the person’s unreliability or by evidence against the proposition believed. So whereas the extreme epistemic egoist says we should never put epistemic trust in others, and the strong and weak epistemic egoists say we should trust them only if we have evidence of their trustworthiness, the epistemic universalist says we should trust them unless we have evidence of their untrustworthiness. My argument against epistemic egoism is that the exercise of my own powers, powers that I trust, commits me to trusting others. The epistemic egoist trusts her own powers, and the exercise of those powers in a world like our own commits her to trusting others, which is to say, she is committed to 14 giving up epistemic egoism. Foley’s argument is different. He argues that the fact that I trust myself commits me to trusting others. Since self-trust is reasonable because it is inescapable, prima facie trust in others is reasonable because a condition for my own trustworthiness is the trustworthiness of others. Foley then uses a thesis of broad intellectual egalitarianism to extend his argument to an argument for epistemic universalism. My argument does not extend as far as an argument for epistemic universalism.6 Like the forms of epistemic egoism, epistemic universalism has an ethical analogue. According to the ethical universalist, the fact that someone else has a certain interest or desire gives me some reason to take that interest or desire into account in my deliberations. I always have a reason to make someone else’s interests my interests simply because their interests are their interests. Again, that reason can be defeated or overridden, but the ethical universalist maintains that I have a prima facie reason to take an interest in the interests of everybody else, just as I have a prima facie reason to believe what anybody else believes according to the epistemic universalist. Notice that there is no argument for the incoherence of ethical egoism 6 I find it very hard to know whether epistemic universalism should be accepted because there are no pure test cases in which all I know in favor of p is that some person of whom I know nothing believes p. Finding out that somebody believes p invariably brings with it other information, either about the source of the belief or its content. 15 that parallels either Foley’s or my argument for the incoherence of epistemic egoism. My argument against epistemic egoism starts from the assumption that all sides have a common desire for truth, and the dispute between the epistemic egoist and the non-egoist is about trust in the attempt to get truth. But there is no common assumption of the desire for some good that means to which is the basis for the dispute between the ethical egoist and the non-egoist. I do not see that the exercise of my taking an interest in whatever I am interested in commits me under pain of inconsistency to take an interest in the interests of others. Similarly, there is no ethical parallel to Foley’s argument because even though the fact that I trust my own faculties and previous beliefs commits me to trusting the faculties and beliefs of others since my trustworthiness depends upon theirs, caring about my own interests does not commit me to caring about the interests of others since what I care about does not depend upon what other people care about, and my interests do not depend upon other people’s interests. Of course, many philosophers have argued that it is irrational to care about my own interests and not those of others, but it is not inconsistent, or at least, if there is an inconsistency, it is not as straightforward as it is in the case of epistemic egoism. I suspect that the widespread rejection of ethical egoism is primarily due to the fact that many of us find it morally repellant and we trust the emotion of moral repulsion. Arguments that ethical egoism is irrational are used to bolster 16 a pre-existent rejection of the position. In contrast, as we have seen, epistemic egoism is not repellant, and, in fact, philosophers often find it appealing. A person who personally disvalues the interests of others upsets us. A person who personally disvalues the beliefs of others does not. It is interesting to consider why that might be the case. My conjecture is that we do not get upset about people with differing strategies to a shared end (the truth), but we do get upset about people who do not value our ends and may even thwart them. But that might not be quite right. It seems to me that we do get upset at extreme epistemic egoists who do not take our word for anything, and we often get upset at the epistemic egoist who demands proof of our reliability before believing us, proof that we usually cannot provide. To do so, we would have to know what they already believe and accept as premises of a demonstration, and we would then have to lay out the evidence of our reliability, a procedure that is not only cumbersome and time-consuming, but is unlikely to do much to foster a relationship with them. In fact, it seems virtually guaranteed to keep a distance between us. That suggests that if there is no difference in the behavior of the epistemic egoist and the non-egoist, we are not likely to complain about epistemic egoism. In fact, we probably wouldn’t even notice it. It is only when we are not trusted that we take offense. However, I take it that the dispute over epistemic egoism is interesting because there typically is a difference in the behavior of the epistemic egoist and the non-egoist. Epistemic egoism affects 17 the way epistemic communities function, and it no doubt affects the way other sorts of communities function. Think of the problem of the legendary Cassandra, whose ability to foretell the future was not trusted by the Trojans, with disastrous results when they did not heed her warning that the Trojan horse was a hoax. But even more telling was the effect on her. Aeschylus tells us it drove her mad. One of the morals of the story of Cassandra is that we need to be trusted epistemically, as well as in other ways. I think, then, that not only is epistemic autonomy a position that cannot be consistently maintained, but I think that the attempt to live by it probably has undesirable consequences for community life. I would like to end this section by noting that the rejection of epistemic autonomy does not commit us to rejecting intellectual autonomy in all forms. I have focused on the issue of autonomy in the adoption of belief or non-belief about standard objects of belief, which are generally understood as propositions. But the human intellect does much more than form beliefs. An important state of intellect which we value and to which the arguments of this paper do not apply is understanding. I surmise that whereas other people can give us beliefs, other people cannot give us understanding; at least, we cannot pick up understanding from them in the straightforward way we can pick up their beliefs. Autonomy may be necessary in the quest for understanding, not because there is something allegedly better about the autonomous understander over the non-autonomous understander, but because we can 18 only get understanding on our own. Similar points apply to traits of intellectual character. Nobody else can make me open-minded or intellectually cautious or thorough or fair or humble. But that is not because there is an ideal of intellectual autonomy to which I should aspire, but because there are certain things I have to do myself. iii It is interesting to consider the connection between epistemic autonomy and moral autonomy. As I interpret the ideal of the morally autonomous agent, she is autonomous in two ways: (1) She figures out the moral law for herself and trusts nobody but herself to figure it out, so she is an extreme epistemic egoist about morality. (2) She is self-legislating; she obeys a law she gives to herself. The issues raised by moral autonomy are among the deepest and most important of all those examined in ethical theory, but all I will do in this brief concluding section is to mention some ways the arguments of this paper might apply to moral autonomy. These remarks are intended only as a prelude to future work. Is it coherent to be an extreme epistemic egoist about morality, as the morally autonomous agent is? Such a person would not necessarily be an extreme epistemic egoist about non-moral matters. She could even be an epistemic universalist about non-moral matters. So she might think that there is something importantly different about moral beliefs that makes them 19 immune to the argument I gave against epistemic egoism. Perhaps she has the position that the moral beliefs of different persons do not conflict, or she might think that the conflict is not cognitive, or she might think that no two people are ever in the same epistemic situation with respect to moral beliefs. Perhaps there is something more subjective or distinctively personal about moral beliefs that would make it appropriate to rely only upon oneself for such beliefs, on the grounds that no one else can contribute the personal element to her beliefs. That was notably not the thinking of Kant, of course, but it might be the thinking of a contemporary upholder of extreme epistemic egoism about the moral. Suppose instead that I think that I should trust myself in forming my moral beliefs at least in part because I form these beliefs conscientiously; I try to figure out the truth about moral matters. I also notice that there are other people who are just as conscientious as I am in their moral beliefs, and some of their beliefs conflict with mine. I see for myself that some other people do what I do when I am conscientious in figuring out what morality requires and what a morally virtuous person is like. That is, they do what I trust in myself. Furthermore, I may admire them in the way they think about moral matters and I trust my emotion of admiration. If so, I can easily trust some of the moral beliefs of some other people as much as my own and I might trust some of the beliefs of some people more than my own. With these assumptions, I should reject epistemic egoism about morality for the same reason I would be led to 20 reject epistemic egoism about non-moral beliefs. How would Foley’s argument against epistemic egoism apply to moral beliefs?7 Recall that Foley argues that I would not be trustworthy in my beliefs unless many other people are trustworthy also. That is because he assumes that most of my beliefs were acquired from other people, and I would not be reliable unless they are. But we probably do not take moral beliefs on testimony to the same extent that we take beliefs in many other categories on testimony, at least not after we reach adulthood, so the inconsistency between self-trust and failure to trust others is not as striking in the moral case as it is with our beliefs in general. Furthermore, the set of moral beliefs is small enough that it does seem possible to live by Fricker’s ideal of extreme epistemic egoism in the moral domain without circumscribing one’s moral knowledge. So I am not sure that Foley’s argument against epistemic egoism should lead us to reject epistemic egoism about the moral. But Foley also has an argument for epistemic universalism, which would presumably apply to moral beliefs. The epistemic universalist ought to acknowledge a prima facie reason to accept the moral beliefs of any other 7 Foley seems to be sympathetic to the view that we should be more reluctant to rely on others for our moral opinions than for other kinds of opinion (2001, p. 115), but he supports that contention by expressing sympathy for the view that moral judgments lack truth value, in which case, neither his argument nor my argument against epistemic egoism would apply. 21 person. Of course, that reason is often immediately defeated by the conflicting beliefs of other persons, so the argument does not get us very far in determining what to believe, but Foley’s argument does require the rejection of epistemic autonomy in the moral realm. I think, then, that some of the arguments of this paper should lead us to be skeptical of the first component of moral autonomy, the component of epistemic autonomy about morality. What about the second component of moral autonomy? If I should not value my cognitive powers above those of others just because they are mine, why should I value my will just because it is mine? The problem is especially acute if my will depends upon my intellect in a significant way. If the ideal of epistemic autonomy fails, it may carry with it the failure of the ideal of the autonomy of the will. But it is doubtful that the ideal of the autonomy of the will depends entirely on the ideal of the autonomy of the intellect, and there are some very interesting issues here about the nature of the self and the place of the will (if there is any such thing) at the core of the self. I have focused on the way the ideal of epistemic autonomy tends to undermine itself. I cannot say whether the autonomy of the will undermines itself in the same way. It is curious that we accept the limitations of a material world, but we hate submitting to the will of another, and we hate submitting to the intellect of another. We are right to resist being abused or dominated or controlled, but I have argued that there is nothing wrong with submitting to the intellect of another just because it is the intellect of another and not our own. Submission 22 to a will is a more complicated case because submission implies a will to submit. We can have a will to submit to the intellect of another, and we can have a will to submit to the will of another. I do not see that there is anything inconsistent in refusing to do the latter, but neither do I know of a plausible argument in favor of refusing to submit to the will of another either. References Foley, Richard. 2001. Intellectual Trust in Oneself and Others. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. __________________. 2005. “Universal Intellectual Trust,” Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology 2 (1): 5-11. Fricker, Elizabeth. 2006. “Testimony and Epistemic Autonomy,” in The Epistemology of Testimony, edited by Jennifer Lackey and Ernest Sosa, Oxford University Press. Biography Linda Zagzebski is George Lynn Cross Research Professor and Kingfisher College Chair of the Philosophy of Religion and Ethics at the University of Oklahoma. She is the author of Divine Motivation Theory (2004), Virtues of the Mind (1996), The Dilemma of Freedom and Foreknowledge (1991), Philosophy of Religion: An Historical Introduction (2007), and On Epistemology, forthcoming 23 from Wadsworth/Broadview Press. 24