National CPD Distance Learning Programme 2010 © Citizenship Foundation and Birkbeck, University of London Unit 1d The three strands of the English Citizenship Curriculum What kind of citizen? We have already seen that Crick argued that the new citizenship curriculum should aim to enable young people to develop into active, informed, critical and responsible citizens (para. 1.10). These different characteristics represent the ideal citizen to be shaped by the citizenship curriculum. But they must be nurtured in different ways: citizenship education therefore must be seen as being made up of different strands, each contributing vital knowledge, skills or dispositions to the whole. Crick identified three major strands that should constitute good citizenship education: social and moral responsibility, community involvement and political literacy. Crick himself acknowledged that what his Committee was proposing went beyond the aims of his earlier campaign for ‘political education and political literacy’ (para. 2.9). Even though, on his earlier definition, political literacy included a willingness to take action in pursuit of a political goal, the Crick Committee envisaged that the classroom teaching of political ideas and contemporary issues should be enriched by forms of community activity in order to embed the theory in the actual practice of participation. Such participation would provide the richest possible context for the development of the necessary skills for effectiveness in public life. Interestingly, writing later about the introduction of the citizenship order, Crick commented that such community activity had not been seen by the Committee as a mandatory part of the subject. The Report strongly recommended pupil participation both in school and in the local community as good practice, but not to be part of a statutory order – ‘value-added’, if you like. We thought we were being politically prudent […] being acutely aware both of the dangers of appearing to overload the bending backs of so many teachers. […] But the Secretary of State sent word to the working party who were drafting the consultative order (civil servants, QCA, teachers, advisers) that actual participation could be mandatory, if we cared so to recommend. We did not demure. […] Without the experiential , participative side of citizenship learning, some schools could turn (and still might if inspection 1 National CPD Distance Learning Programme 2010 © Citizenship Foundation and Birkbeck, University of London does not follow the aims as well as the precise language of the order) the brave new subject into safe and dead, dead-safe, old rote-learning civics. [Crick, 2000, p.119] The requirement to include participation as part of the statutory curriculum provides a considerable challenge to busy classroom teachers, and has made it necessary for Ofsted to pass judgement on what might constitute a reasonable minimum entitlement to participation for all students, given that it is likely to prove very difficult to provide opportunities for all students to be involved in off-site community activities. We shall return to this point. Of course, one major difficulty with the term ‘political’ is that, strictly speaking, the teaching of politics in its own right is traditionally confined to the secondary curriculum because few children show an interest in the niceties of political processes and institutions before adolescence. However, what Crick proposes is a continuous and progressive curriculum, based around a framework of key concepts, which can and should be taught at every key stage, at the appropriate level. In this way, a radical new vision of what citizenship education can be opens up, marking a major step forward from earlier, much narrower conceptions. Citizenship education should be understood as the nurturing of the child’s social and moral development in the early years through learning about a wide range of topical issues, near at home and overseas, from the discussion of school rules and classroom or playground behaviour, to the alleviation of poverty in the developing world and through the encouragement of critical thinking, of emotional literacy, and of the abilities to think critically and express and defend one’s own thoughts in discussion. The failure to conceive of civic education as developmental in this way, has lead many European countries in the past to confine citizenship education to more narrowly framed civics courses in the secondary years, a fairly common pattern being a one year’s course in year 9 and another in year 11. A side effect of this arrangement has been that across Europe, civic education has traditionally been taught by non-specialists, given its modular appearance in the time-table. History and philosophy teachers have often been required to teach it and in many cases, as in England where too many non-specialist tutors are similarly engaged, it is taught badly, without enthusiasm and is widely regarded as low status and ineffectual by students and teachers alike (Rowe, 2006). Such a subject arrangement, where citizenship is on the margins of the curriculum, is not enough to attract committed enthusiasts into the profession in numbers. There is no career for them, except as teachers of examination level politics or sociology. However, once citizenship education becomes nominated as a specialist subject, resources are set aside to ensure there is a supply of committed, specialist teachers and the subject is allocated appropriate curriculum time. And when the subject is taught by such teachers, it becomes transformed from low status, irrelevant and boring 2 National CPD Distance Learning Programme 2010 © Citizenship Foundation and Birkbeck, University of London taught by a reluctant workforce, to a dynamic subject, valued by very many students and central to the life and ethos of the whole school. Let us look at these three strands in a little more detail. Social and Moral responsibility Note how in paragraph 2.11 Crick denies that moral thinking is ‘prepolitical’. It is too simple to think that in the primary years, the citizenship curriculum will address inter-personal issues of right and wrong (such as why we have school rules, or why bullying is unkind) and leave truly political issues to the secondary years. There are many genuine citizenship issues to be discussed in the primary years, such as care for the environment, racism, children’s rights and so on. Whilst it is true that, developmentally, full-blown politics is not for the primary school child, there is a sense in which children are developing their understanding of key political ideas from the very beginning. At the centre of political debates are central questions concerning equality, fairness, justice, rights, responsibilities, power, authority and so on. In an important study of pre-school children between 18 months and three years, Dunn (1988) showed that these are the very concepts that preoccupied them a lot of the time in their developing relationships with parents and siblings. The bases of their excuses, justifications, and jokes include not only the idiosyncratic practices of a particular family, but some of the key principles of the wider culture outside the family: principles of possession, positive justice, excuses on grounds of incapacity or lack of intention, even gender-role division of labour. [p172] This underlines the importance of discussing citizenship issues explicitly with children from the early years. Such issues relate to how we should live and work together, in school and in the community, with other people, particularly those with whom we may not share the same values. What are the school rules for and are they fair? How should we work together to address behavioural issues in the class? Why is it wrong to be unkind or to treat others with disrespect? How can we all help to make the world a better place? Why should we raise money for charitable causes or care about the natural world? Moral thinking, in its own right, is a key element of citizenship thinking. Simply to question whether something is fair is to think morally and underneath all political judgements and all visions of how society might be improved, are moral values. For this reason, citizenship education, as Crick says, should include an element of ‘moral education’. This term ‘moral education’ often sounds alarms bells amongst teachers, who fear that they might be asked to instruct children and young people in what is right and wrong. In other words, they understand ‘moral education’ as ‘moral instruction’, begging the question, ‘Whose morals are we 3 National CPD Distance Learning Programme 2010 © Citizenship Foundation and Birkbeck, University of London supposed to be teaching?’. Rowe (2006) argues that teachers in both primary and secondary schools need to become confident in using the kind of questions which elicit moral thinking, e.g., considering who has rights, assessing responsibility for actions, apportioning blame, showing empathy, thinking about the consequences of actions, discussing fair outcomes, proposing how a situation could be improved, and so on. Citizenship issues are rich in opportunities to employ these forms of moral thought. The more students are exposed to, and are encouraged to use these form of thinking, the more likely they are to internalise them and use them spontaneously in their own reasoning. As in any other discipline, moral thinking improves with practice. Students cannot use concepts with which they are unfamiliar and solving moral problems gets easier with practice. It is important here to remember that thinking morally is not the same as being a good person, or having particular personal values or virtues. We use moral reasoning to refer to thinking about issues in terms of whether they are right or wrong, good or bad, fair or unfair, important or unimportant. Thinking morally can lead to more morally right actions - it can assist the process of becoming fairer in one’s judgements, more able to recognise the claims of others in any given situation and thus less egocentric. Being asked to think about the consequences of actions for other people, or how other people think or feel about a situation, can actually have a sensitizing effect, nurturing emotional literacy (also a key aim of the national Social and Emotional Aspects of Learning (SEAL) programmes). We would argue that good citizenship or political decisions are informed not only by good political judgements but sound moral ones. Political literacy From one point of view, citizenship education can be regarded as the induction of young people into the way our society resolves its differences in a fair and non-violent manner. To put this another way, citizenship education introduces students to the ‘nation’s conversations’ or the debates of the moment. This has been described as a public discourse model of citizenship (Rowe, 2000). In his chapter in Developing Citizens Ted Huddleston (2006, p.147) draws on a public discourse model of citizenship education and suggests that political concepts are simply those ‘without which democratic thought and communication would not be possible’. Here, it is helpful to consider the fact that within mono-cultural organisations, like families, there may be high levels of agreement about a range of social and moral issues (though this is not, of course, guaranteed). Conversations in such nonpublic settings rest on many shared cultural and value-based assumptions which do not need to be articulated or justified. However, when people move from the private to the public sphere to discuss shared problems 4 National CPD Distance Learning Programme 2010 © Citizenship Foundation and Birkbeck, University of London with people who do not share the same values or world view, new forms of argumentation have to be learnt and employed. New justifications have to be offered for the stances taken and some arguments (such as ‘this is wrong because my religion says so’) can no longer be used because others do not recognise them as valid. So, it becomes a central concern of citizenship education to assist young people understand and negotiate the public sphere. Without such understanding, active citizenship is simply not possible. What characterises ‘political’ discussions? Bernard Crick suggests that politics is the ‘jostlings of self-interest, group interests and ideals’ (Essays on Citizenship (2000) chapter 2, p 14). This is a very different view of citizenship from it being all about voluntary service to others. Fundamentally, politics is about questions such as, ‘What kind of society do I want and what can I do about it?’, ‘How shall we deal with this problem as a society?’, ‘Is our society fair?’ and ‘What is for the common good?’. These key questions underlie a great deal of public debate and they should equally infuse classroom discussions. If the above are fundamental procedural questions, substantively, political thinking and discussion may draw on law, politics, ethics, economics, sociology and philosophy depending on the particular issue under the spotlight. Thought about in this way, it is little wonder that many people never manage to achieve an adequate level of political understanding. Citizenship education aspires to help young people sufficiently master these discourses to enable them to become politically literate and thus to be able to participate with confidence in public life. Community involvement Community involvement is the logical outcome of political thought. In one sense, community involvement can be said to begin when students begin to think in an engaged way about what is going on around them, they have taken the necessary first step. As their understanding of how society functions develops, so does their capacity to envisage ever more effective solutions to social and political problems. Indeed, merely thinking about political issues is a necessary form of social engagement and should not be dismissed as of no consequence because it is not ‘active’. Not every citizenship topic readily leads to a ‘change action’, though teachers must always ask themselves what students might be able to do as a result of any specific study. Learning about, for example, how a law is made may not lead to social action (though the lessons can be extremely active) but it can lead to enhanced understanding of how we are governed and give students much greater awareness of how power is wielded. This is an important step towards becoming a ‘critical’ citizen, and criticality is a vital civic virtue in any democratic society. 5 National CPD Distance Learning Programme 2010 © Citizenship Foundation and Birkbeck, University of London Whilst community involvement is a compulsory element of the curriculum, it is worth bearing in mind that citizens’ of liberal democracies are not obliged to get involved. They have the right to take no interest or part in public life, though others might argue that such people are neglecting their moral duties by opting out in this way. So, can the current curriculum, with its insistence on community involvement be justified? Arguably, yes. The purpose of education is to expand possibilities for action for its students and unless citizenship seeks to develop the skills of political action, then it leaves to chance the development of an important entitlement for all democratic citizens. Whether they choose to use these skills in later life is up to each individual – it should not be the role of the school to deny emergent citizens such life enhancing skills. Study Tasks Take a topic you are already teaching and think about how it might separately support the development of students’ social and moral development, political literacy and community involvement. Or take a new topic and treat it in the same way. Take a topic from the citizenship syllabus and analyse it in terms, not of knowledge, but of the key citizenship questions it should help students focus on? How can school life be constructed in such a way that all students can be offered opportunities to participate in citizenship acivities? For example, what steps can be taken to guard against school council engagement being limited to an elite group of students? References Crick, B. (2000) Essays on Citizenship. London, Continuum Dunn, J. (1988) The Beginnings of Social Understanding . Oxford, Blackwell. 6 National CPD Distance Learning Programme 2010 © Citizenship Foundation and Birkbeck, University of London Huddleston, T. (2006) ‘From Political Education to Political Literacy: equipping young people for life in a more genuine democracy’ in Breslin, T. and Dufour, B. (eds) Developing Citizens. London, Hodder Murray. Rowe, D. (2000) ‘Common Schools, Good Citizens: towards a public discourse model of moral education’ in Best, R. (Ed) Education for Spiritual, Moral, Social and Cultural Development. London, Contiuum Rowe, D. (2001) ‘Value Pluralism, Democracy and Education for Citizenship’ in Collins, J., Insley, K. and Soler, J. (eds.) Developing Pedagogy: researching practice. London, Paul Chapman Publishing Rowe, D. (2006) Developing Moral Thinking in Primary and Secondary Schools in the ‘Teaching Thinking and Creativity’ Vol 7:1. Birmingham, Imaginative Minds Publishing Further Reading for Unit 1 Making Sense of Citizenship: A CPD Handbook by Ted Huddleston and David Kerr, section 1 ‘What is Citizenship?’ pp 1-14. Developing Citizens (Breslin and Dufour), Chapter 3.3 by Ted Huddleston ‘From Political Education to Political Literacy’, pp 143 - 150 Developing Citizens (Breslin and Dufour), Chapter 1.3 by Ian Davies ‘Citizenship in the National Curriculum: contexts, requirements and expectations’ pp25 – 34. 7