PRAGAMATIC INDUCTION Popper’s views on induction are more an evasion of Hume’s problem than a solution to it. But the fact of the matter is we need to make decisions about how to act. Life would otherwise come to a standstill In order to do this, however, we need to make predictions about what will occur. If, as Popper argues, science doesn’t do this, how can we make rational decision about courses of action to take? Also, is it true that science never aims to make predictions? We shall discuss this question as well. 1 Falsification and prediction Does Popper’s falsification program offer us any clues as to how to make rational predictions? Well, it does offer one negative suggestion: Don’t base predictions on falsified hypotheses. E.g., avoid F = 2ma3 This seems reasonable enough: if a true conclusion is desired, don’t reason on the basis of false premises. So we must choose theories that haven’t been refuted. But this isn’t much. In fact, if this is all we have to go on, we have a problem… 2 Infinitely many hypotheses We have only carried out finitely many tests. But there are infinitely many hypotheses. So, as Salmon points out, infinitely many hypotheses haven’t been ruled out. Remember, on Popper’s view neither F = ma nor E = mc2 has been confirmed or shown to be true. So, are we simply free to choose amongst them? But some will give predictions that conflict with those given by others. There appears to be no rational basis for preference when choosing hypothesis to help one make predictions. 3 Corroboration and prediction It is worth noting that on Popper’s view corroboration has no predictive power. It is nothing more than an appraisal of a theory’s performance in the past. A corroborated theory is simply a theory that hasn’t yet been falsified. To make this claim is not, Popper insists, to suggest that the theory will perform well in the future. Why not? The answer is that to do so would be to engage in inductive reasoning: theory T has performed well in the past so it will perform well in the future. As we have seen, Popper attempts to purge such reasoning from science. Science is not in the prediction business, on his view. 4 Import vs. content An important distinction: Corroboration has no predictive import. This means that the very fact that a theory is corroborated has no bearing on whether it will continue to be. Theories have predictive content. Many scientific hypotheses are universal generalizations, i.e. they cover events at all times and places. So, these theories do say something about the future. So, reasoning on the basis of a theory will provide a guide to action. The question is whether there can be a reason to prefer one theory over another This is a question about justification for a theory, not content of a theory. 5 Theoretical vs. practical rationality When it comes to reasoning, Popper distinguishes theoretical from practical concerns. The scientist is interested in coming up with good theories, i.e. theories that lead to many tests. Those that survive the tests are kept for further testing That is surely the rational thing to do: discard falsified theories and keep going with corroborated ones. This is theoretical rationality and it contains absolutely no presumption that a hypothesis is more likely to survive tomorrow because it survived yesterday. So what is one to do when reasoning about action? 6 A tension Popper claims, curiously, that we should use corroboration when choosing hypotheses on which to base predictions: …we should prefer the best tested theory as a basis for action…since we have to chose, it will be ‘rational’ to choose the best tested theory. (p. 440) This is a curious combination. On the one hand, the fact that a theory is highly corroborated says nothing about its future performance. On the other, when one must reason about the future, it is rational to pick the most corroborated theory. But how can corroboration lend any justification to the choice? 7 The problem How can it be rational to base a prediction on a theory in virtue of something that has no implications whatsoever for predictive power? Analogy: We compare two theories, T1 and T2. Both are corroborated. T1 has more vowels than T2. We insist: the number of vowels in a theory has no bearing at all on how the theory will perform in the future (seems reasonable). But, suppose we also say: if you have to pick one for prediction, pick T1 because, after all, it has more vowels. This is hardly persuasive given the first point. Popper’s view faces a similar predicament, according to Salmon. 8 Circularity Suppose S must act and H1 and H2 are the relevant hypothesis to choose from. Suppose H1 is corroborated but not H2. Isn’t it rational to pick H1? Watkins: S has nothing else to go on! Salmon: that simply begs the question. There is plenty more to go on: S could count vowels, toss a coin, consult a horoscope, etc. The point must be that there is nothing else to go on that is rational. 9 Problems with this reply Note: this response assumes that basing prediction on corroboration is rational. But this is circular reasoning, because the question under consideration is whether such a choice is rational. After all, perhaps no choice is rational (Hume’s conclusion). So even if S had nothing more to go on, it wouldn’t follow that such reasoning is rational. Finally, hasn’t Popper insisted all along that corroboration has no predictive import? So how can the choice be any more rational than flipping a coin? 10 Vindication Recall the import/content distinction. Let P = theory T is well corroborated. According to Popper, P has neither predictive content nor predictive import: It has no predictive content because it says nothing about future behaviour. It has no import because it cannot provide justification for assuming T will continue to be corroborated. If it did, this would be inductive reasoning. Salmon: but how can we reconcile the second point with the directive to choose the corroborated theory when making predictions? That directive has predictive import: it is supposed to rationally justify a choice. 11 Upshot In sum, Salmon’s criticism is that it is implausible to suppose both 1. That corroboration statements have no predictive import 2. That the directive to choose the most corroborated theory when making predictions is rationally grounded. Anti-inductivists need some way to vindicate (2) in light of (1). Until then, they have no way of arguing that some predictions are more rational than others. You might as well use astrology as astronomy; palm reading as physics. 12 Inductive logic How might the directive to choose corroborated theories be vindicated? The most plausible suggestion is that corroboration has predictive import after all. In other words, rational decision making relies on induction. So the project of purging induction from human reasoning appears unlikely to succeed. But, can theoretical science proceed without induction? 13 Theoretical prediction Salmon: Popper’s program appears to fail as an account of practical action; but it also an impoverished understanding of science. There is no reason to think that scientists only wish to make bold conjectures then criticize them. Many scientific predictions are made for theoretical or practical purposes e.g.: 1. Will this nuclear chain reaction come to a (natural) close? 2. Will this universe expand indefinitely? In both cases, interesting theoretical issues are at stake, not just practical action: We make such predictions to help us deepen our theoretical understanding. It is scientifically legitimate to forecast. 14 Induction here to stay In sum: Salmon argues that we need induction for practical decision making. We will also need it in science, even theoretical science. Logically, we could eliminate induction from reasoning, but that would leave us with a theoretical and practical repertoire that is severely impoverished. 15 Justifying induction pragmatically Reichenbach offers a strategy similar to that of Popper/Watkins in that it is a pragmatic justification. However, he offers a little bit more by way of justifying the rationality of induction. Let us examine his views… 16 Reichenbach’s take on the problem Reichenbach: Hume is right: We can’t prove that the conclusion of an inductive inference must be true. But the real question is: is induction useful when trying to decide how to act? It does seem possible to justify induction according to this standard. For example, perhaps we can show that: Induction is the best guide to action that we have (even if not that good). If this is the case, then the principle is justified. 17 An analogy Suppose S is dying. The doctor says: There are no known drugs or therapies that will save S. However, it is possible that this operation will remove the disease, but I don’t know that with any certainty. Reichenbach: It is justified to perform the operation. It is the best (and only) hope. Similarly: if induction turns out to be the best way to guide our lives, then it is justified to follow it even if we can’t prove it will work. Okay, but can we show that induction is the best principle here? 18 Reichenbach: Two possibilities: 1. The world is ordered. 2. The world isn’t ordered. If #2, then no method of prediction will work. So, using induction is no better but also no worse than anything else. So, using induction is as justified as anything can be. 19 Induction in an orderly world Assume, now, that the world is ordered. Then: any method of determining patterns of event occurrence will have to: Examine past frequencies. Project them into the future. In other words, all methods of empirical science depend on induction. So if any works, induction will work. If induction doesn’t work, nothing else will. Either way, induction is justified as the best (only) approach we have. So: whether the world is ordered or not, the best approach you can take to guiding your actions is the inductive approach. It is, therefore, justified. 20 Comparison with decision theory World is Ordered Good Reason inductively predictions Don’t reason Bad (no) inductively Predictions World Isn’t ordered Bad (no) predictions Bad (no) Predictions One action, A, dominates another action, B, iff, in all possible situations, the consequences of selecting A over B are at least as desirable as those of selecting B over A and sometimes better “Sure-thing (or dominance) principle”: the action is best which dominates the others. 21 Problem This doesn’t show very much. Even if induction is necessarily the best principle we have, it doesn’t follow that it is a very good one. Reichenbach: that’s just our predicament! The best we can do is to make our bets to the best of our abilities. There’s nothing we can do about the fact that future is at best uncertain. 22 Comparison with Popper Note that Popper also insists that we base predictions on theories that have been successful in the past because it is all we have to go on. But he simply assumes that this renders the view rational, i.e. everything else we might go on is comparatively irrational. Reichenbach’s position is different. He aims to show that induction, even if irrational, is the most rational prediction we could possibly have. He doesn’t assume this. 23 At least a little rationality Recall that Reichenbach argues that rational prediction can only succeed in a patterned world, and that in such a world induction is the best guide available. Nothing else could match it: not tossing a coin, not counting vowels, etc. Only a careful examination of past sequences and the formulation of general rules on that basis could possibly give a better than chance probability of correct predictions. So, induction is the only chance we have to go above 50-50 guesses. In this way Reichenbach presents us with a pragmatic defence of induction that differs from Popper’s. 24 Some problems remain Reichenbach has, perhaps, given us reason to use induction. But he has not given us any reason to believe conclusions based on inductive reasoning are likely to be true or that such reasoning is in fact rational. This still seems unsatisfactory. Is it plausible to suppose that, say, all your years of experience preferring elevators over window-leaps gives you no reason to believe elevator will continue to be safer? Is it reasonable to suppose that all you could believe is: we have no idea whether elevators will be safer tomorrow, but practically that is the best thing to believe? Do you really not believe they will be safer tomorrow? 25 Any hope left? It would be nice if we could come up with an inductive logic or program that would entitle one to have confidence in the actual beliefs formed as the result of inductive reasoning. So far, nobody has shown us a way to do this. But let us keep searching. 26