Meiho Institute of Technology Working Paper: December 2006 Moving beyond tacit and explicit distinctions: A realist theory of organizational knowledge Dr Ashok Jashapara School of Management Royal Holloway University of London Abstract This paper challenges the popular notions of tacit and explicit organizational knowledge and argues that its philosophical underpinnings derived from Gilbert Ryle are problematic due to their logical behaviourist perspective. The paper articulates the philosophical problem as the neglect of any role for the mind in organizational activity and the representation of mental activity as purely a set of behaviours. An alternative realist philosophy is advanced taking into account the potential of adopting a number of competing philosophical perspectives. The paper forwards a realist theory of organizational knowledge that moves beyond the surface behaviours of tacit and explicit knowledge and argues that collective consciousness and organizational memory play primary and deeper roles as knowledge mechanisms and structures. Consciousness is not a Hegelian world spirit but rather a real process embedded in people’s brains and mental activity. Further, the paper argues that organizational routines provide the contingent condition or ‘spark’ to activate organizational knowledge processes. The implications of this model are explored in relation to the measurement of intellectual capital. The theory developed in this paper represents the first attempt to provide a coherent philosophically grounded framework of organizational knowledge that moves organizational theory beyond neat conversion processes of tacit and explicit knowledge. Keywords: organizational knowledge, realism, consciousness, memory, tacit knowledge, explicit knowledge, past experience, organizational routines, philosophy. -1- Meiho Institute of Technology Working Paper: December 2006 Introduction The reality for many western economies is that capital and labour intensive industries have continued to decline and the relative importance of knowledge-intensive industries has increased. One of the key driving forces behind this situation has been the rapid rise of information technologies that have created opportunities for generating and disseminating new forms of knowledge across organizations (Empson 2001, p. 812). Knowledge has become the most important source of competitive advantage and given rise to the emerging discourse of knowledge management (Drucker 1995; Drucker 1999). In the UK, central government has acknowledged the fundamental economic role knowledge plays in promoting innovation, creativity and the exchange of ideas (Department for Education and Employment 2000). In organizational theory, Edith Penrose (1959) provided the insight that every firm confronts a different set of heterogeneous resources leading to different responses to competitive pressures. In time, this basic assumption gave way to the resource based view (RBV) of the firm where a firm’s performance is ultimately driven by its valuable and unique resources rather than external factors such as industry forces (Barney 1991, 2001; Conner 1991). As early as the 1960s, Etzioni (1964, pp. 77-78) was mindful that the critical resource of a firm was the way it’s knowledge was produced, applied, preserved and communicated. More recently, these developments in organizational theory have led to the knowledge based view (KBV) of the firm where knowledge is considered strategically the most significant resource of a firm in terms of its market value and the primary source of Ricardian rents (Grant 1996; Grant and Baden-Fuller 2004: 66; Spender 1996, p. 59). But what is this entity termed knowledge in organizations? From a philosophical perspective, the very essence of knowledge has been debated for over 2000 years in western philosophy and shows no signs of abating. If the pressing task in organizations is increasingly the management of knowledge, it is important that scholars make explicit their conceptions of this valuable resource and the assumptions underlying them. For instance, Abrahamson & Eisenmann (2001, p. 67) treat knowledge as a substance or commodity that can be traded rather like a football depending on its supply and demand characteristics. Similarly, Hansen and Haas (2001, p. 2) adopt a similar (internal) market metaphor to describe the dissemination of electronic document records within organizations. In contrast, scholars such as Orlikowski (2002, p. 252) view knowledge as a process or an ‘ongoing social accomplishment’. It is only through interaction between an individual’s latent knowledge and knowledge manifest in their surroundings that knowledge emerges as a social phenomenon (Carlile 2002, p. 295). The current popular conception of organizational knowledge makes a distinction between tacit and explicit knowledge. Such a logical behaviourist perspective derives from the philosopher Gilbert Ryle (1949) who made a distinction between ‘knowing what’ (explicit) and ‘knowing how’ (tacit). In The Concept of Mind (1949), Ryle criticizes Cartesian dualism arguing that descriptions of human behaviour need never refer to anything but the operations of human bodies. Michael Polanyi (1967) helped clarify our understanding that these two forms of knowledge were not distinct entities but existed along a continuum. A theoretical development of these notions of knowledge has been the articulation of processes that convert one form of knowledge to another in organizations. Nonaka (1994) proposed four separate processes called socialization, combination, externalization and internalization in this knowledge conversion process. -2- Meiho Institute of Technology Working Paper: December 2006 However, there have been numerous criticisms of these popular conceptions of knowledge and the simplistic conversion processes. Knowledge conceived as tacit and explicit suffers from ontological incoherence, vagueness, objectivity, functionalism and emptiness from its all-embracing view (Alvesson and Karreman 2001, p. 997). Knowledge can become an allencompassing but little revealing concept (Tsoukas and Vladimirou 2001, p. 974) particularly in certain contexts. Also, scholars question whether knowledge is more likely to be created through Nonaka’s (1994) neat conversion processes or rather through debate, dialectics and collective enquiry (Lanzara and Patriotta 2001, p. 945). The aim of this paper is to move discourse on organizational knowledge beyond the limited logical behaviourist perspective and provide a conception of organizational knowledge that is grounded philosophically in critical realism. The paper begins by explaining key tenets of realist philosophy and provides a critique of key competing philosophical positions adopted by management scholars. The paper argues that Ryle’s (1949) behaviourist approach becomes philosophically problematic when all aspects of the human mind are ignored and reduced to a set of behaviours. An alternative realist theory of organizational knowledge is proposed that builds on the surface level phenomena of tacit and explicit knowledge and argues that collective consciousness and organizational memory play key roles as knowledge mechanisms and structures even though they may not be directly observable. The paper concludes by noting general implications of our realist theory for the management of knowledge and for further research. Competing Philosophical Perspectives: A Realist Conception of Knowledge The Enlightenment vision of realism is that the real world exists independent of us, our experiences, our thoughts or our language (Sayer 2000, p. 2; Searle 1999, p. 4). It seeks to penetrate surface phenomena and disclose deep social structures (Brown et al. 2002, p. 774). Realist theory employs abstraction to move beyond appearances in social reality to their ‘real’ essences in terms of deeper causal structures and mechanisms. However, when theories of social reality change (their transive dimensions) it does not necessarily mean that their intransitive or inherent characteristics change as well (Searle 1999, p. 11). The realist conception of explanation rejects the Humean ‘billiard ball’ secessionist view of regularities among sequences and events. Hence, the conventional impulse to gather data on regularities and repeated occurrences is seen as misplaced. Such analyses tend to provide purely an understanding of formal relations in social phenomena. Instead, explanation depends on identifying causal mechanisms and how they work, especially the conditions under which they are activated (Bhaskar 1975). These mechanisms or social processes have powers and liabilities whether or not they are activated. For example, an unemployed person has the power to work even though they may not do so at the current time (Sayer 2000, p. 192). Hence, the focus of explanation is to identify substantial relations in the form of necessary (internal) and contingent (external) relations that cause certain events to occur (Harré 1986). In terms of generalisations, realist scholars adopt pluralistic methodological approaches which seek out formal relations through quantitative studies and the more substantial relations of causal mechanisms and structures through qualitative means. The realist notion of theory is a conceptualisation or way of seeing something. This is very different from the conception of a theory as an ordering framework or ‘filing system’ as common in disciplines with high levels of orthodoxy such as economics. In these ordering frameworks, observational data, predominantly in mathematical form, is used to explain and -3- Meiho Institute of Technology Working Paper: December 2006 predict empirical events. However, the objectivity of such observations is questioned from a realist perspective as the observations are seen as theory laden rather than being considered as theory neutral. Theory is recognised to affect observation leaving it conceptually saturated. For example, we are aware that if a theory gains certain currency in organizations, managers begin to act in accordance to the theory rather than act opportunistically through their own insights. Apart from the explanatory and descriptive aspects of knowledge, realists adopt a critical theoretical stance that has an evaluative, critical and emancipatory role in its understanding of social phenomena. This involves criticizing an organization or society’s self understanding rather than adopting a disinterested stance common in more positivist or scientific approaches. Before his untimely death, Ghoshal (2005, p. 77) argued that the absence of moral or ethical considerations in our theories has had a negative impact on management practices as well as contributing to business failures such as Enron. A number of competing philosophical perspectives have been adopted in studying organizational knowledge. The dominant management scientific paradigm is built on the assumption that there is no distinction between the social and natural worlds. Realism is built on a rejection of this positivist stance. The naturalism debate argues that the positivist stance ignores social relations and intersubjectivity between subjects and objects and assumes that all social realities are directly observable. It is not surprising that our transitive theories in social science do not produce universal laws and logically coherent theories. Another premise of the scientific endeavour is that the social world can be characterised as a closed system. The reality is that social systems are open, complex, ambiguous and messy. The same causal powers can produce very different outcomes (Sayer 2000, p. 19). Human actors have the ability of modifying the external configuration of systems as well as a capacity for learning and self change to modify internal characteristics. The processes are dynamic and in a perpetual state of flux. The diametrically opposite ‘subjective’ perspective to the positivist paradigm is idealism. This paradigm asserts that the only reality is one of ideas and constituted by our perceptions. Hence, instead of making our knowledge claims answerable to an independent reality, we make external reality answerable to our representations (Searle 1999, p. 16). Cartesian scepticism asserts that despite all our evidence for knowledge claims, we may still be mistaken. However, this argument conceals a controversial premise that one must have sound reasons for believing something but no good reasons for doubting it (Macmurray 1957). Realists recognise that to isolate mental activity as the distinctive feature of the self is to exclude the possibility that action, the material world and other people have definitive importance in our understanding of what is human (Macmurray 1961). The realist philosopher, John Macmurray (1957), suggested we substitute the Cartesian dictum ‘Cogito Ergo Sum’ (I think, therefore I am) to ‘Ago Ergo Sum’ (I do, therefore I am). He insisted that action was more primary than thought with the assertion that thought begins only where action fails (Macmurray 1933). While an interpretive understanding is an important and necessary feature of social phenomena, realists argue that it does not mean that there is no scope for causal explanations (Sayer 2000: 6). Social phenomena are concept dependent but causal explanations can be determined in terms of material changes as well as their underlying causal mechanisms and structures. Postmodernist perspectives emphasise the diversity of the world, the plurality of perspectives and the difficulty of obtaining reliable knowledge (Stones 1996, p. 2). Such -4- Meiho Institute of Technology Working Paper: December 2006 relativist perspectives where knowledge is divided into discrete systems of thought can nullify the key role of criticism and evade critical evaluation. The problem of incommensurability is that we cannot understand radically different discourses while we retain our own beliefs. However, in practice, some form of translation is always possible and incommensurability can be seen as a way of protecting favoured discourses from criticism (Collier 2003). Feminist critique of male stream science has contributed the notion of ‘situated knowledge’ concerning questions of power in what constitutes knowledge (Grimshaw 1996; Haraway 1991; Harding 1991). Knowledge bears social markings of its context including the sex, race and gender of its authors as well as the media through which it is transferred. From this perspective, the dominant position of the western, white, heterosexual male in research provides one situated view of knowledge even though it may often be passed within an academic community as having universal applicability (Sole and Edmondson 2002). Such a feminist perspective would support a drift towards a relativist position. However, this stance would deny the role of critical enquiry particularly where feminist standpoints argue that certain positions are advantageous over others (Haraway 1991, p. 191). In essence, all knowledge is social, situated and contextual. However, the feminist critique becomes problematic when it is assumed that certain forms of knowledge are only applicable to particular groups from which they arise such as acupuncture for the Chinese and French social theory for the French. Realists accept the need for reflexivity to guard against myopias and biases in their research but would argue that it would be wrong to dismiss research a priori from certain groups such as white males as distorted but not that conducted by black females on the same grounds.(Sayer 2000: 55). A Realist Theory of Organizational Knowledge In the mind-body problem, the logical behaviourist philosophy of Gilbert Ryle(1949) becomes problematic when all forms of mental states and especially consciousness are ignored. Consciousness is reduced to little more than behaviour or dispositions to behaviour of the body and computational states of the brain. The default position of such materialism is that the world is entirely made up of physical or material entities and that consciousness does not exist as a real and irreducible entity. This view is challenged by the realist philosopher, John Searle(1999), who argues that the primary characteristic of the mind is consciousness. All our everyday experiences create states of sentience or awareness that have a first person ontology. Conscious states are an inner, subjective, first-person and qualitative phenomena. They are caused by brain processes and, hence, are biological phenomena. Consciousness can be considered as higher level processes created in the structure of the brain. As such, consciousness is completely material and irreducibly mental at the same time (Searle 1999, p. 69). There is no duality between mind and body. -5- Meiho Institute of Technology Working Paper: December 2006 FIGURE 1 Realist conception of individual and organizational knowledge -6- Meiho Institute of Technology Working Paper: December 2006 The problem with Ryle’s (1949) behaviourism can be illustrated in relation to an experience such as pain. For example, an individual can be in pain but may refuse to show the behaviour linked to it. If one observes an individual’s behaviour of pain, is there any difference between the person being in pain and pretending to be in pain? Also, does an individual only have access to their experience or belief in pain through observing their own behaviour? This limited perspective applies equally to Gilbert Ryle’s popularised notions of tacit (know-how) and explicit (know what) knowledge. From a realist perspective, Ryle’s notions of knowledge can be considered as surface level phenomena in terms of behaviours observed at individual or collective levels. This paper forwards a realist conception of organizational knowledge, as shown in Figure 1, and argues that consciousness and organizational memory play primary underlying roles as knowledge mechanisms and structures even though they may not be directly observable. Let us begin by exploring knowledge at an individual level. When a new problem or situation arises, it will trigger a personal conscious experience as a mental state. This qualitative subjective experience will be informed by the person’s memory of dealing with similar problems or situations in the past. This conscious experience may create positive, negative or indifferent attitudes towards the problem. In turn, the person’s consciousness will influence the nature of tacit or explicit knowledge they bring to bear on the problem. These are directly observable behaviours in terms of an individual’s knowledge base and skills. In any new situation, the way an individual responds (action or inaction) will be determined by their level of knowledge and intentionality. Intentionality is a mental process that occurs within an individual and concerns their representation of objects, events and states of the world related to any given situation (Searle 1999, p. 104). These intentional states may be conscious, semiconscious or unconscious such as hopes, desires, beliefs and fears. The condition of satisfaction of any intention is action within the person’s locus of control (Zaibert 2003, p. 211). However, other forms of intentionality such as beliefs and desires about the external world do not need to result in action as they may be outside the person’s locus of control. For example, the desire of a new graduate to become Managing Director of a large company may go unrealised for some time and result in inaction. The cycle of learning occurs when action fails and gives rise to thoughts and reflections that may influence present consciousness or become stored in memory as past experiences. When new problems or situations arise in organizations, they are experienced immediately in terms of a collective consciousness based on dialogue, discussion and interaction between individuals. This may occur in formal environments or informal ones such as communities of practice. Shared meanings and representations are established in the collective psyche. Such representations may be literal or metaphorical. The nature of the collective consciousness will be determined by the strength and quality of relationships in the social network; whether it is a team, a department or the whole organization. Organizational culture or sub-cultures shape the collective consciousness through the facility of stories and narratives and provide a symbolic representation of norms and values through which the new situation is tackled. Collective consciousness does not exist in a vacuum and is influenced by organizational memory and collective remembering. This takes the form of past experiences retold orally in narratives despite the fallibility of human memory. Organizational history is drawn again in light of history of present circumstances (Foucault 1970). Our past experiences are surfaced and modified to provide insight to our present circumstances. Organizational memory may also be stored in information systems such as data warehouses and case-based reasoning systems and their value is in their utility to inform the collective consciousness. -7- Meiho Institute of Technology Working Paper: December 2006 The observed knowledge behaviours of tacit or explicit knowledge occur as a consequence of certain knowledge mechanisms activated in the collective consciousness. This may take the form of information made meaningful through a variety of classification, categorisation and retrieval processes. Alternatively, the knowledge behaviour may manifest as organizational capabilities or core competences (Prahalad and Hamel 1990) such as exploration and exploitation behaviours in response to previous outcomes of success or failure (March 1991). This paper argues that organizational routines provide the contingent conditions or spark to enable this three level model of organizational knowledge, as shown in Figure 1, to occur in organizations. If the ultimate consequence of organizational knowledge is its capacity for action (Inkpen 2000, p. 1020; Macmurray 1933), there needs to be some coherence between knowledge and shared intentions in organizations. This collective intentionality is a web of related and interlocking attitudes that leads to the choice and execution of certain actions rather than others from the domain of organizational capabilities. In a competitive context, this intentionality becomes the strategic intent where the web of mental attitudes and aspirations are centred on goals outside the scope of current organizational resources (Hamel and Prahalad 1989). This intentionality acts as a major driver for organizational commitment and motivation of employees and determines whether certain actions are realised or remain unrealised. Knowledge Behaviour: Explaining the Commodity of Explicit Knowledge A normative perspective of knowledge is to view such an entity as an asset; an objectively definable commodity. Such a perspective has disciplinary roots in economics where exchanges of knowledge are governed by an internal market for the commodity within organizations (Empson 2001, p. 813). At this level, knowledge can be construed as information (Leonard and Sensiper 1998, p. 113). The qualities of this information ‘substance’ (Nunberg 1996, p. 115) that become important in organizational terms are its accuracy, its relevance and its classification and categorisation. The reason that inaccurate information is an issue is that people may be misled and make inappropriate decisions from this information. Independent corroboration and agreement between different information sources does not always indicate that the information is accurate. Instead, Fallis (2004, p. 472) suggests that the verifiability of information or testimony should be based on the plausibility of a claim and the evidence offered to support the claim. This is the ‘operationalism’ theory of meaning deriving from logical positivism. An alternative ‘picture theory’ of meaning from Wittgenstein (2001/1921(original)) proposes that the extensional meaning of a word is its referent. For instance, the extensional meaning of “routines” is the set of all past, present, and future routines in organizations (Svenonius 2004). In terms of relevance of a piece of information, many scholars assume that relevance can be established by studying the relevance criteria of users. However, from a realist perspective, any document can be relevant for a given purpose whether or not the user believes it to be so (Hjørland 2004, p. 497). The information or document is external to the cognitive state of the user and does not depend on it. The classification and categorization of information becomes important when one adopts a container metaphor of knowledge. The effective organization of knowledge allows -8- Meiho Institute of Technology Working Paper: December 2006 information to be gathered and retrieved efficiently. In any knowledge domain, “categorization is the process of dividing the world into groups of entities whose members are in some way similar to each other” (Jacob 2004, p. 518). Categorization is much more flexible than classification and allows creative and nonbinding associations between entities. In contrast, classification divides any knowledge domain into an arbitrary system of mutually exclusive classes. Two systems that have been adopted for classifying knowledge in libraries are Ranganathan’s (1960) Colon Classification and The Broad System of Ordering (Mills 2004). However, the very notion of ‘information’ is problematic depending on its epistemological assumptions. For example, Floridi (2002, p. 39) argues for a social epistemology of information based on neither an externalisation (naturalization) or internalisation (mind of the beholder) of information (Floridi 2004, p. 661). Instead, this declarative commodity of information is defined in relation to data, as meaningful data. The problem is that information becomes divorced from its utility value where the mass of information becomes noise rather than a key to unlock a given problem. Knowledge Behaviour: The Ambiguous Nature of Tacit Knowledge Tacit knowledge is not a factual commodity but takes on the character of a ‘process of knowing’ in organizations. Such knowledge is recreated in the present moment and is largely invisible in organizations except when questions are asked or problems need to be resolved (McDermott 1999). At such times, attempts are made to articulate the implicit, uncodifiable and procedural nature of this knowledge. The idiosyncratic nature of tacit knowledge means that it is not amenable to the classifications and categorizations of the more declarative knowledge. Hence, this lack of representation and the firm specific nature of this resource protects this knowledge from imitation by rival firms (Martin and Salomon 2003, p. 298). Such tacit knowledge is often embedded within a system or context of a work processes. This can make it much harder for competitors to imitate a process as the observability of different aspects of a process are further diminished (Birkinshaw et al. 2002, p. 274; Zander 1991). A subtle aspect of tacit knowledge is its ambiguity. The degree and diversity of experience in organizations is negatively related to ambiguity (Simonin 1999, p. 601). Hence, the more codifiable or teachable an organizational capability, the higher the risk of knowledge being transferred between firms (Zander and Kogut 1995, p. 85). The inverse of this ambiguity is that it can prevent firms from learning from their own experience and improving their performance over time (McEvily et al. 2000, p. 296). For this reason, ambiguity can provide organizations with external strengths and internal challenges at the same time. Knowledge Mechanisms: The Shared Experiences of Collective Consciousness From a realist perspective, consciousness is at the same time a mental state as well as an internal biological phenomena arising from activity in the brain. It has the quality of subjectivity as its mental state only exists as experienced by the individual (Searle 1999, p. 73). At an organizational level, collective consciousness is still experienced at an individual level as a mental state and is constituted and reconstituted in everyday experience (Orlikowski 2002, p. 252). It is not some sort of Hegelian world spirit or a ‘super mind’ floating above an individual’s head (Meijers 2003, p. 181; Searle 1995, p. 25). Instead, collective consciousness is produced in a process through interactions in work teams and communities of practice and -9- Meiho Institute of Technology Working Paper: December 2006 through daily dialogue and discussions occurring at different levels of an organization. Such consciousness is situated in a historical, socio-material and cultural context in which it occurs (Gherardi and Nicolini 2000, p. 330). Collective consciousness can be defined as the shared experience, meanings and representations of social networks in organizations. As such, it has cognitive, relational and cultural dimensions. The cognitive dimension concerns the collection of internalised symbolic systems that mediate between the individual and the external world (Karamanos 2003, p. 1878). Knowledge representations of social networks can vary along two dimensions; the literal to the figurative as well as the abstract to the concrete (Boland et al. 2001, p. 394). The shared representations, interpretations and systems of meaning among parties arise from shared language and codes (Cicourel 1973) as well as shared narratives (Orr 1990). The relational dimension of collective consciousness concerns the nature and strength of personal relationships developed through a history of interactions in organizations (Granovetter 1992). This aspect includes all aspects of relationships such as respect and friendship that may influence a person’s behaviour. This relational dimension is influenced by the levels of trust (Adler 2001; Stephens 2001), norms and sanctions (Coleman 1990), obligations and expectations (May et al. 2002) and identity (Parker 1997). The presence or absence of network ties between individuals and the configuration of social networks will have a marked bearing on the strength and intensity of personal contacts (Hansen 2002; Tsai 2001). An organization’s culture shapes a human mind but is also shaped by it through narrative language (Boland et al. 2001, p. 396). The cultural dimension of collective consciousness concerns the shared mental models around values, beliefs, attitudes and underlying assumptions in organizations. Values may be deeply ingrained principles, aspirational, minimum standards or accidental reflecting common interests of workers such as a distrust of management (Lencioni 2002). Shared mental models have a propensity to develop and transform themselves in informal networks or communities of practice using storytelling and narratives. Stories play an important role in cognitive embedding of ideas of work practices as well as social embedding of individuals and their ties in organizations (Hansen 1999). It is precisely this form of embedding that makes knowledge ‘sticky’ (Szulanski 1996; von Hippel 1994) in terms of its complex social and cognitive linkages and, hence, proves difficult for competitors to imitate. Knowledge Structures: The Art of Remembering and Forgetting in Organizational Memory Organizational knowledge structures differ from personal schemata as they are socially constructed and rely on consensus and agreement. They could be considered as mental templates of organized knowledge about an environment that allows interpretation and effective action in that environment (Lyles and Schwenk 1992, p. 157; Walsh 1995, p. 286). We argue that the primary knowledge structure in organizations is past experience as learning and knowledge acquisition are closely associated with memory and collective remembering (Middleton and Edwards 1990; Walsh and Ungson 1991). Middleton (2002, p. 93) maintains that history matters not only in terms of what came before but also in what comes next. These commonalities of experience help resource future trajectories of participation in organizations. A firm’s absorptive capacity is largely based on its past experience of a knowledge domain - 10 - Meiho Institute of Technology Working Paper: December 2006 prior to its transfer (Cohen and Levinthal 1990). If the former knowledge or skills gap is too great, learning becomes almost impossible. The collective memory in organizations develops its coherence by connecting and interweaving along the social and temporal dimensions. This social space of meaning allows the continuous flow of actions, narratives and images from one generation to the next. This enables practical and theoretical knowledge to be preserved and transmitted as well as formative past experiences (Brockmeier 2002, p. 18). Such organizational memory can be conceptualised as storage bins of past decisions including memories about individual actions, cultural developments and changes, transformations in structures, rules and procedures and workplace ecology (Walsh and Ungson 1991). Human memorizing and remembering also needs to be understood in terms of the social functions it fulfils and the cultural web in which it is integrated (Bruner 1994). Human individuals develop memory frames and practices as part of social communities and organise these individual memories in the context of their cultural participation and the process of everyday routines (Brockmeier 2002, p. 23). These frames of memory are defined by the cultures and subcultures in which they are embedded (Tschuggnall and Welzer 2002). The cultural memory in organizations comprises not only the practical and theoretical knowledge and experiences but also the moral and aesthetic values of the organization. These values are shaped through narratives which allow individuals to grasp a longer past and become manifest through stories, myths and organizational legends (Brockmeier 2002, p. 34). Collective forgetting plays an important role in past experience through the forgetting of elements that may no longer be meaningful or too painful in the present; a form of ‘structural amnesia’ (Assmann 1995). Forgetting may occur out of organisational necessity such as discarding organizational practices and routines that no longer fulfil changed circumstances or strategies that hinder organizational learning and new ways of doing things (de Holan and Phillips 2004, p. 1605). This loss of organizational knowledge may be accidental or purposeful. Firms may have difficulty in consolidating new knowledge due to their lack of absorptive capacity or may forget established knowledge over time due to deterioration of memory and a lack of mechanisms to maintain it. More purposeful forms of forgetting are when firms need to discard new forms of knowledge arising from experiments and innovations as well as established forms of knowledge through unlearning old habits and practices (de Holan and Phillips 2004, p. 1606; de Holan et al. 2004, p. 47; Hedberg 1981). The Contingent Condition: The Spark of Organizational Routines and Sensemaking The three levels of organizational knowledge shown in Figure1 provide a realist explanation of the necessary causal powers or internal relations but say little about the contingent conditions or external relations. In essence, what drives the cycle of organizational knowledge creation and transformation? For instance, gunpowder has the necessary condition to explode but does not do so at all times. It requires the contingent condition of a spark to explode (Bhaskar 1975). We argue that organizational routines play a principal role as contingent conditions and coordination mechanisms for dispersed knowledge in organizations. This is particularly acute in large organizations where ‘pockets’ of specialised knowledge exist and a firm’s effectiveness is based on its ability to integrate these spatially and temporally dispersed assets (Purvis et al. 2001, p. 117). These contingent conditions occur as formal hierarchical structures or as informal lateral relations in organizations (Tsai 2002, p. 180). - 11 - Meiho Institute of Technology Working Paper: December 2006 We argue that organizational routines are complex patterns of coordination that allow organizational members to integrate their specialist knowledge in the production of goods and services (Nelson and Winter 1982). They are regular and predictable patterns of behaviour and play an important role as an organization’s competence. Without them, organizations would lack an effective method for collective action. Organizational routines provide ‘connections’ or interactions between people which allow for the development of social ties between actors and transfer of organizational knowledge (Feldman and Rafaeli 2002). Organizational routines allow different perspectives to be explored and a common understanding or knowledge to be developed within an organizational context of power relations, performance expectations and organizational identity (Jashapara 2004, p. 77). The physical copresence of actors and their shared physical settings play an influential role in developing shared understandings and affiliations. This mutual knowledge is established by first hand experience, interactional dynamics and category membership (Krauss and Fussell 1990). Organizational routines operate at two levels in organizations to facilitate knowledge integration. First, they promote automatic and practicised patterns of interaction that allow knowledge integration for task performance. Second, they allow improvisation of responses and interactions as individuals explore new situations and challenges. By definition, these imply learning and the creation of dynamic capabilities (Zollo and Winter 2002). The distinction between an organizational routine and a dynamic capability is the level of reflection. In stable or static environments, organizational routines predominate and are characterised by stable patterns of behaviour. Routines can be complex but predictable and exhibit qualities of ‘single-loop learning’ (Argyris and Schon 1978). In contrast, in highly volatile market conditions, organizations may not be able to rely on systemic learning and existing knowledge. In such circumstances, organizations may reflect on their situation and question their underlying norms and assumptions. Such questioning is more indicative of ‘double-loop learning’ and a dynamic capability (Jashapara 2004, p. 80). In uncertain environments, these dynamic capabilities are likely to resemble simple routines based on few rules and a greater tendency towards improvisation (Eisenhardt and Martin 2000). Routines have the characteristic of requiring relatively little attention from organizational actors. However, when major differences are noticed between expectations and actual results, sensemaking processes materialise (Weick et al. 2005, p. 409). Thought begins as action fails (Macmurray 1957). Sensemaking is about a quest for meaning in organisations through the creation of plausible stories that are resilient in the face of criticism. The stories may provide diagnostic labels that offer plausible solutions for subsequent activity. Each story is communicated through different channels around the organisation and retold to mirror local circumstances. Sensemaking processes are not about accuracy in terms of organisational interpretations but rather the search for plausible stories that incorporate observations and past experiences (Weick 1995; Weick et al. 2005). Conclusions This paper has challenged the populist notions of organizational knowledge as tacit and explicit knowledge and shown that their philosophical bases are problematic coming from a logical behaviourist perspective (Ryle 1949). At best, these notions provide the scholar with surface level phenomena in terms of behaviours of individuals or groups. The materialist assumptions of this perspective neglect any role of the mind in organizational activity and equate mental activity purely to a set of behaviours. The paper argues that any meaningful - 12 - Meiho Institute of Technology Working Paper: December 2006 notions of organizational knowledge need to be more philosophically grounded. Otherwise, there is a risk in management literature of the perpetual appraisals of themes or patterns without any recourse to their philosophical underpinnings or criticisms. The dominant positivist paradigm in management research is criticised in its attempts to make closed systems out of open social systems and its rejection of intersubjectivity and learning in the naturalism debate. Similarly, idealist approaches of social constructivism, postmodernism and feminism are found wanting isolating mental activity as the distinctinctive feature of the self, invoking problems of relativism and incommensurability. Instead, the paper forwards a realist philosophy of a physical world independent of human beings that seeks to penetrate surface behaviours and phenomena and disclose deeper causal mechanisms and structures. The gaps identified in current organizational knowledge discourse are the neglect of collective consciousness and organizational memory as primary knowledge mechanisms and structures. The contribution of this paper is to move beyond the relatively static discourse of tacit and explicit knowledge and their simplistic conversion processes to a more philosophically grounded one that acknowledges the key role of collective consciousness and organizational memory. Consciousness is not some super mind floating in the sky but rather a real process embedded in people’s brains and mental activities simultaneously. In organizations, this collective consciousness is experienced at individual levels as shared mental models and is influenced by the nature and strength of personal relationships, the stories that provide cognitive and social embedding of ideas and people as well as the construction of meaning through language. Future research may wish to explore how language games in narrative or allegorical processes influence the nature and shifts of collective consciousness (Boland et al. 2001, p. 396; Gherardi and Nicolini 2000, p. 216; Wittgenstein 1953). In multicultural environments and internet conversations, there is the danger of misunderstandings through a lack of individual eloquence and speech performance (Chompsky 1968; Kalling and Styhre 2003, p. 66) that may have an adverse effect on collective consciousness. Future research could explore speech performance and power relations in social networks and their impacts on the collective consciousness. Past knowledge resides in the brains of individuals as well as artificial memories of organizational information systems. Potential tensions arise reconciling the literal memories of artificial systems with the figurative or allegorical stories of human actors. These issues can provide fruitful unfarrowed avenues of research into how perceptions of history change in the present over fallible notions of human memory juxtaposed by the relentless mechanical accuracy of organizational systems. An organization’s ability to absorb new knowledge or its absoprtive capacity (Bloodgood and Morrow 2003, p. 1779; Cohen and Levinthal 1990) is a direct function of the diversity of its past experiences. The practical value of the realist conception of organizational knowledge is in its contribution to the discourse of intellectual capital and its measurement for financial reporting. Organizational memory and past experiences have components of human memory and information systems in line with notions of human and organizational capital respectively (Reinhardt et al. 2001). The nature of collective consciousness in organizations relates closely with the level of social capital in terms of its cognitive, relational and cultural dimensions (Cohen and Prusak 2001; Nahapiet and Ghoshal 1998). There is an inherent difficulty in measuring collective consciousness as, by definition, it is diverse and ever changing at any given moment. Given that history is reinacted differently in the present (Foucault 1970), organizational memory is also in a state of flux. This makes measurement of organizational memory and collective consciousness somewhat challenging due to its very subjective nature. - 13 - Meiho Institute of Technology Working Paper: December 2006 A more fruitful methodological approach is to treat these aspects of intellectual capital as a narrative and ensuring that issues of bias and myopias are resolved (Mouritsen et al. 2002). In contrast, the behavioural and more observable dimensions of tacit and explicit knowledge can lend themselves to measurement as a form of customer capital. There is a pressing need among scholars and the accounting fraternity to establish rigorous and consensual metrics that can be used across sectoral and national boundaries. Bearing in mind the numerous theories of managing knowledge based on Gilber Ryle (1949) and his derivatives, this paper has provided a critique of this dominant perspective and offered an alternative realist conception of organizational knowledge. The paper has argued that philosophical introspection on the nature of organisational knowledge is necessary before it can be managed effectively in organizations. We hope that the analysis presented in this paper may serve to stimulate further theoretical interest in the knowledge based view (KBV) of the firm and practical interest in managing the different dimensions of collective consciousness and memory in organizations. - 14 - Meiho Institute of Technology Working Paper: December 2006 Bibliography Abrahamson, E. & Eisenman, M. Why management scholars must intervene strategically in the management knowledge market. Human Relations, 2001, 54(1), 67-75. Adler, P.S. Market, hierarchy, and trust: The knowledge economy and the future of capitalism. Organization Science, 2001, 12(2), 215-234. Alvesson, M. & Karreman, D. Odd couple: Making sense of the curious concept of knowledge management. Journal of Management Studies, 2001, 38(7), 995-1018. Argyris, C. & Schon, D.A. Organizational Learning: A Theory of Action Perspective. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley, 1978. Assmann, J. Ancient Egyptian antijudaism: A case of distorted memory. In D.L. Schacter, Coyle, J.T., Fischbach, G.D., Mesulam, M.M. & Sullivan, L.E. (Eds.), Memory distortion: how minds, brains and societies reconstruct the past. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1995. Barney, J.B. Firm resources and sustained competitive advantage. Journal of Management, 1991, 17(1), 99-120. Barney, J.B. Is the resource-based "view" a useful perspective for strategic management research? Yes. Academy of Management Review, 2001, 26(1), 41-56. Bhaskar, R. A Realist Theory of Science. Leeds: Leeds Books, 1975. Birkinshaw, J., Nobel, R. & Ridderstrale, J. Knowledge as a Contingency Variable: Do the Characteristics of Knowledge Predict Organization Structure? Organization Science, 2002, 13(3), 274-289. Bloodgood, J.M. & Morrow, J.L. Strategic organizational change: Exploring the roles of environmental structure, internal conscious awareness and knowledge. Journal of Management Studies, 2003, 40(7), 1761-1782. Boland, R.J., Singh, J., Salipante, P., Aram, J.D., Fay, S.Y. & Kanawattanachai, P. Knowledge representations and knowledge transfer. Academy of Management Journal, 2001, 44(2), 393-417. Brockmeier, J. Remembering and Forgetting: Narrative as Cultural Memory. Culture & Psychology, 2002, 8(1), 15-43. Brown, A., Slater, G. & Spencer, D.A. Driven to abstraction? Critical realism and the search for the 'inner connection' of social phenomena. Cambridge Journal of Economics, 2002, 26, 773-788. Bruner, J.S. The 'remembered' self. In U. Neisser (Ed.), The remembering self. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994. Carlile, P.R. A pragmatic view of knowledge and boundaries: Boundary objects in new product development. Organization Science, 2002, 13(4), 442-455. Chompsky, N. Language and mind. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1968. Cicourel, A.V. Cognitive sociology. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1973. Cohen, D. & Prusak, L. In Good Company: How Social Capital Makes Organizations Work. Boston, MA: Harvard Business School Press, 2001. Cohen, W.M. & Levinthal, D. Absorptive capacity: A new perspective on learning and innovation. Administrative Science Quarterly, 1990, 35, 128-152. Coleman, J. Foundations of Social Theory. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990. Collier, A. In Defence of Objectivity and Other Essays: On realism, existentialism and politics. London: Routledge, 2003. - 15 - Meiho Institute of Technology Working Paper: December 2006 Conner, K.R. A historical comparison of resource-based theory and five schools of thought within industrial organisation economics: Do we have a new theory of the firm? Journal of Management, 1991, 17(1), 121-155. de Holan, P.M. & Phillips, N. Remembrance of Things Past? The Dynamics of Organizational Forgetting. Management Science, 2004, 50(11), 1603-1613. de Holan, P.M., Phillips, N. & Lawrence, T.B. Managing Organizational Forgetting. MIT Sloan Management Review, 2004, 45(2), 45-51. Department for Education and Employment. Opportunity for All: Skills for the New Economy. London: DfEE, 2000. Drucker, P. Managing in a time of change. New York: Truman Talley, 1995. Drucker, P.F. Knowledge-worker productivity: The biggest challenge. California Management Review, 1999, 41(2), 79-+. Eisenhardt, K. & Martin, J. Dynamic capabilities: What are they? Strategic Management Journal, 2000, 21, 1105-1121. Empson, L. Fear of exploitation and fear of contamination: Impediments to knowledge transfer in mergers between professional service firms. Human Relations, 2001, 54(7), 839862. Etzioni, A. Modern organizations. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1964. Fallis, D. On verifying the accuracy of information: Philosophical perspectives. Library Trends, 2004, 52(3), 463-487. Feldman, M. & Rafaeli, A. Organizational Routines as Sources of Connections and Understandings. Journal of Management Studies, 2002, 39(3), 309-331. Floridi, L. On defining library and information science as applied philosophy of information. Social Epistemology, 2002, 16(1), 37-49. Floridi, L. LIS as Applied Philosophy of Information: A Reappraisal. Library Trends, 2004, 52(3), 658-665. Foucault, M. The Order of Things : An Archaeology of the Human Sciences. London: Tavistock Publications, 1970. Gherardi, S. & Nicolini, D. To Transfer is to Transform: The Circulation of Safety Knowledge. Organization, 2000, 7(2), 329-348. Ghoshal, S. Bad Management Theories Are Destriying Good Management Practices. Academy of Management Learning & Education, 2005, 4(1), 75-91. Granovetter, M.S. Problems of explanation in economic sociology. In N. Nohria & Eccles, R. (Eds.), Networks and Organizations: Structure, Form and Action. Boston, MA: Harvard Business School Press, 1992. Grant, R.M. Toward a knowledge-based theory of the firm. Strategic Management Journal, 1996, 17, 109-122. Grant, R.M. & Baden-Fuller, C. A Knowledge Accessing Theory of Strategic Alliances. Journal of Management Studies, 2004, 41(1), 61-84. Grimshaw, J. Philosophy, feminism and universalism. Radical Philosophy, 1996, 76, 19-28. Hamel, G. & Prahalad, C.K. Strategic Intent. Harvard Business Review, 1989, May-June, 6376. Hansen, M.T. The search-transfer problem: The role of weak ties in sharing knowledge across organization subunits. Administrative Science Quarterly, 1999, 44, 82-111. Hansen, M.T. Knowledge networks: Explaining effective knowledge sharing in multiunit companies. Organization Science, 2002, 13(3), 232-248. Hansen, M.T. & Haas, M.R. Competing for attention in knowledge markets: Electronic document dissemination in a management consulting company. Administrative Science Quarterly, 2001, 46(1), 1-28. - 16 - Meiho Institute of Technology Working Paper: December 2006 Haraway, D.J. Simians, cyborgs, and women: The reinvention of nature. London: Free Association Books, 1991. Harding, S. Whose Science, Whose Knowledge? Thinking from Women's Lives. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991. Harré, R., (Ed.). Varieties of Realism. Oxford: Blackwell, 1986. Hedberg, B.L.T. How organizations learn and unlearn. In P.C. Nystrom & Starbuck, W.H. (Eds.), Handbook of Organizational Design. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1981. Hjørland, B. Arguments for philosophical realism in library and information science. Library Trends, 2004, 52(3), 488-506. Inkpen, A.C. Learning through joint ventures: A framework of knowledge acquisition. Journal of Management Studies, 2000, 37(7), 1019-1043. Jacob, E.K. Classification and categorization: A difference that makes a difference. Library Trends, 2004, 52(3), 515-540. Jashapara, A. Knowledge Management: An Integrated Approach. Harlow Essex: Prentice Hall, 2004. Kalling, T. & Styhre, A. Knowledge Sharing in Organizations. Copenhagen: Copenhagen Business School Press, 2003. Karamanos, A.G. Complexity, identity and the value of knowledge-intensive exchanges. Journal of Management Studies, 2003, 40(7), 1871-1890. Krauss, R. & Fussell, S. Mutual knowledge and communicative effectiveness. In J. Galegher, Kraut, R. & Egido, C. (Eds.), Intellectual Teamwork: social and Technological Foundations of Cooperative Work. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum, 1990. Lanzara, G.F. & Patriotta, G. Technology and the courtroom: An inquiry into knowledge making in organizations. Journal of Management Studies, 2001, 38(7), 943-971. Lencioni, P.M. Make your values mean something. Harvard Business Review, 2002, July, 113-117. Leonard, D. & Sensiper, S. The role of tacit knowledge in group innovation. California Management Review, 1998, 40(3), 112-+. Lyles, M.A. & Schwenk, C.R. Top management, strategy and organizational knowledge structures. Journal of Management Studies, 1992, 29(2), 155-174. Macmurray, J. The Philosophy of Communism. London: Faber, 1933. Macmurray, J. The Form of the Personal: The Self as Agent (Vol.1). London: Faber, 1957. Macmurray, J. The Form of the Personal: Persons in Relation (Vol.2). London: Faber, 1961. March, J.G. Exploration and exploitation in organizational learning. Organization Science, 1991, 2(1), 71-87. Martin, X. & Salomon, R. Tacitness, learning, and international expansion: A study of foreign direct investment in a knowledge-intensive industry. Organization Science, 2003, 14(3), 297311. May, T.Y.M., Korczynski, M. & Frenkel, S.J. Organizationaland occupational commitment: Knowledge workers in large corporations. Journal of Management Studies, 2002, 39(6), 775801. McDermott, R. Why information technology inspired but cannot deliver knowledge management. California Management Review, 1999, 41, 103-117. McEvily, S.K., Das, S. & McCabe, K. Avoiding competence substitution through knowledge sharing. Academy of Management Review, 2000, 25(2), 294-311. Meijers, A.W.M. Can Collective Intentionality Be Individualized. American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 2003, 62(1), 167-183. Middleton, D. Succession and Change in the Socio-cultural Use of Memory: Building-in the Past in Communicative Action. Culture & Psychology, 2002, 8(1), 79-95. Middleton, D. & Edwards, D., (Eds). Collective Remembering. London: Sage, 1990. - 17 - Meiho Institute of Technology Working Paper: December 2006 Mills, J. Faceted classification and logical division in information retrieval. Library Trends, 2004, 52(3), 541-570. Mouritsen, J., Bukh, P.N., Larsen, H.T. & Johansen, M.R. Developing and managing knowledge through intellectual capital statements. Journal of Intellectual Capital, 2002, 3(1), 10-29. Nahapiet, J. & Ghoshal, S. Social capital, intellectual capital, and the organizational advantage. Academy of Management Review, 1998, 23(2), 242-266. Nelson, R.R. & Winter, S. An Evolutionary Theory of Economic Growth. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1982. Nonaka, I. A dynamic theory of organizational knowledge creation. Organization Science, 1994, 5(1), 14-37. Nunberg, G., (Ed.). Farewell to the information age. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1996. Orlikowski, W.J. Knowing in Practice: Enacting a Collective Capability in Distributed Organizing. Organization Science, 2002, 13(3), 249-273. Orr, J. Sharing knowledge, Celebrating identity in war stories and community memory in a service culture. In D. Middleton & Edwards, D. (Eds.), Collective Remembering: Remembering in a society. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage, 1990. Parker, I. Group identity and individuality in times of crisis: Psychoanalytic reflections on social psychological knowledge. Human Relations, 1997, 50(2), 183-196. Penrose, E.T. The Theory of Growth of the Firm. Oxford: Blackwell, 1959. Polanyi, M. The Tacit Dimension. New York: Doubleday, 1967. Prahalad, C.K. & Hamel, G. The Core Competence of the Corporation. Harvard Business Review, 1990, 68(3), 79-91. Purvis, R.L., Sambamurthy, V. & Zmud, R.W. The assimilation of knowledge platforms in organizations: An empirical investigation. Organization Science, 2001, 12(2), 117-135. Ranganathan, S.R. Colon classification: Basic classification. 6th ed. London: Asia Publishing House, 1960. Reinhardt, R., Bournemann, M., Pawlowsky, P. & Schneider, U. Intellectual Capital and Knowledge Management: Perspectives on Measuring Knowledge. In M. Dierkes, Antal, A.B., Child, J. & Nanaka, I. (Eds.). Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001. Ryle, G. The Concept of Mind. London: Hutcheson, 1949. Sayer, A. Realism and Social Science. London: Sage, 2000. Searle, J.R. The Construction of Social Reality. New York: The Free Press, 1995. Searle, J.R. Mind, Language and Society: Philosophy in the Real World. New York: Basic Books, 1999. Simonin, B.L. Ambiguity and the process of knowledge transfer in strategic alliances. Strategic Management Journal, 1999, 20(7), 595-623. Sole, D. & Edmondson, A. Situated knowledge and learning in disperse teams. British Journal of Management, 2002, 13, S17-S34. Spender, J.C. Making knowledge the basis of a dynamic theory of the firm. Strategic Management Journal, 1996, 17, 45-62. Stephens, C.U. The ontology of trust and the transformation of capitalism in a knowledge economy - A commentary on Paul Adler's ''market, hierarchy, and trust: The knowledge economy and the future of capitalism''. Organization Science, 2001, 12(2), 238-240. Stones, R. Sociological Reasoning: Towards a Post-Modern Sociology. London: Macmillan, 1996. Svenonius, E. The epistemological foundations of knowledge representations. Library Trends, 2004, 52(3), 571-587. - 18 - Meiho Institute of Technology Working Paper: December 2006 Szulanski, G. Exploring internal stickiness: Impediments to the transfer of best practice within the firm. Strategic Management Journal, 1996, 17 (Winter Special Issue), 27-43. Tsai, W.P. Knowledge transfer in intraorganizational networks: Effects of network position and absorptive capacity on business unit innovation and performance. Academy of Management Journal, 2001, 44(5), 996-1004. Tsai, W.P. Social structure of "coopetition" within a multiunit organization: Coordination, competition, and intraorganizational knowledge sharing. Organization Science, 2002, 13(2), 179-190. Tschuggnall, K. & Welzer, H. Rewriting memories: Family recollections of the national socialist past in Germany. Culture & Psychology, 2002, 8(1), 133-148. Tsoukas, H. & Vladimirou, E. What is organizational knowledge? Journal of Management Studies, 2001, 38(7), 973-993. von Hippel, E. 'Sticky information' and the locus of problem solving: Implications for innovation. Management Science, 1994, 40, 429-439. Walsh, J.P. Managerial and organizational cognition: Notes from a trip down memory lane. Organization Science, 1995, 6, 280-320. Walsh, J.P. & Ungson, G.R. Organizational memory. Academy of Management Review, 1991, 16(1), 239-270. Weick, K.E. Sensemaking in Organizations. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications, 1995. Weick, K.E., Sutcliffe, K.M. & Obstfeld, D. Organizing and the Process of Sensemaking. Organization Science, 2005, 16(4), 409-421. Wittgenstein, L. Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1953. Wittgenstein, L. Tractatus Logico-philosophicus. London: Routledge, 2001/1921(original). Zaibert, L.A. Collective Intentions and Collective Intentionality. American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 2003, 62(1), 209-232. Zander, U. Exploiting a Technological Edge: Voluntary and Involuntary Dissemination of Technology. Stockholm: Institute of International Business, 1991. Zander, U. & Kogut, B. Knowledge and the speed of transfer and imitation of organizational capabilities: An empirical test. Organization Science, 1995, 6, 76-92. Zollo, M. & Winter, S.G. Deliberate Learning and the Evolution of Dynamic Capabilities. Organization Science, 2002, 13(3), 339-351. - 19 -