In Nonlinear Dynamics, Psychology, and Life Sciences, July, 2001 Vol 5, No. 3: 197-204. Mathematics of Philosophy or Philosophy of Mathematics? Jeffrey Goldstein, Ph.D. Adelphi University Garden City, NY 11530 Keywords: difference equations; escape diagrams; lattice; logical paradox; model; nonlinear dynamical systems theory (NDS); phase portraits; philosophy of mathematics; self-reference. Abstract: This article examines recent attempts to gain insight into philosophical paradoxes through using NDS models employing iterated difference equations and resulting phase portraits and escape time diagrams. The temporal nature of such models is contrasted with an alternative approach based on the a-temporal and non-dynamical construct of a lattice. Finally, there is a discussion of how such strategies for understanding paradox transcend the realm of empirical research and enter territory in the philosophy of mathematics. Abbreviated title: Mathematics of Philosophy 3 Mathematics of Philosophy... 4 Mathematics of Philosophy... NDS and Self-referential Paradoxes Paradoxes involving self-reference have beguiled thinkers since ancient times. For example, the infamous paradox of Epimenides the Cretan, “All Cretans are liars,” results in the curious situation that it is “true if and only if it is false” (Barwise & Etchemendy, 1987). Such conundrums have not merely remained idle philosophical curiosities but have played a crucial role in much ground-breaking work in mathematics, logic, and computer science as in the work of Gödel, Tarski, and Turing (Machover, 1996). Furthermore, self-reference is inherent in the recursive functions at the heart of chaos, fractals, cellular automata, and similar phenomena in nonlinear dynamical systems theory (NDS). Yet, although it is true that general philosophical implications of chaos and complexity theories have not gone unnoticed (e.g., see Goldstein, 1996), only now is NDS beginning to be exploited to enrich our understanding of self-referential phenomena in philosophy and logic. Thus, Grim, Patrick, and St. Denis (1998) have recently employed NDS models to probe semantical self-referential paradoxes. I am familiar with only one work predating this current thrust that has used dynamics to directly model philosophical statements: Greeley’s (1995) NDS model of Greek philosophical texts. However, Greeley modeled entire philosophical texts, not self-referential paradoxes themselves. Because, the use of NDS to model philosophical paradoxes is inaugurating an entirely new arena of application of NDS, in this article I will examine the specific modeling strategies involved, and along the way, point out how these attempts at a mathematics of philosophy may be better understood as falling within the domain of the philosophy of mathematics rather than empirical research per se. 5 Mathematics of Philosophy... “Dynamical Semantics” In The Philosophical Computer, Grim, Mar, and St. Denis (1998) develop a “dynamical semantics” which employs dynamical systems to model philosophical paradoxes. The first step of their modeling strategy consists in the conversion of classical bivalent logic into an infinitevalued one in which truth or falsity is construed not as an either/or decision but, instead, a matter of degree for which numerical values are assigned. For instance, the proposition that p has the value v is considered untrue to the extent that p differs from v, v being the variable ranging over the interval [0,1]: ∣Vvp∣ = 1 - Abs(v - ∣p∣). (1) Then, in order to capture greater semantic richness, fuzzy logic rules for allocating numerical values are applied to the semantic qualifiers “very” and “fairly”, e.g., “very” as in “very true” is valued as the square of the value for true, whereas, “fairly,” a more hedged qualification, is modeled by square roots. Next, deliberations about the truth and falsity of a paradoxical statement are transposed into iterations of difference equations. For example, the notorious paradox of the Liar (“This statement is false”) is repesented by the difference equation: xn+1 = 1-Abs (0 - xn). (2) Each subsequent deliberation about the statement’s truth is the next iteration of the equation. Finally, phase portraits and escape diagrams emerging from the resulting dynamical equations are explored to gain insight into the deeper structure of paradox. As more elaborate paradoxes are modeled, this “dynamical semantics” becomes progressively more interesting. Thus, the dynamical model of the Liar reveals merely a simple oscillation since any initial value v generates a periodic alternation between the values v and 1- v 6 Mathematics of Philosophy... (the one fixed point attractor is ½ since ½ = 1- ½.). A similarly uninteresting dynamic is found even with the more complex-sounding paradox of the Half-sayer (“This sentence is as true as half its estimated value”) which is modeled with the equation: xn+1= 1 - Abs(1/2xn - xn). (3) Like the Liar, the Half-sayer goes to a fixed point for the value .5. An interesting departure, however, occurs with the similar sounding Minimalist (“This sentence is as true as whichever is smaller: its estimated value or the opposite of its estimated value”). From an initial estimate of 0.6, the Minimalist diverges outward to a Liar-like oscillation between 0 and 1, with 2/3 as a repeller. A comparison of the Minimalist and the Half-sayer demonstrates that although very congruent in appearance, they turn-out to have opposite dynamics: The Half-sayer has an attractor right where the Minimalist has a repeller whereas in classical logic their semantic behaviors are identical with an oscillation between 0 and 1 (0 for false, 1 for true). A paradox with even more fascinating dynamics is the so-called Chaotic Liar (“This sentence is as true as it is estimated to be false”) which is modeled as: xn+1= 1 - Abs(1 - xn) - xn. (4) This result is technically chaotic in the sense that it shows sensitive dependence on initial conditions, is topologically transitive, and the set of period points is dense. Grim, Mar, and St. Denis also confirm a chaotic logistic map for the sentence: “It is very false that this sentence is as true as it is estimated to be false”. With even more labyrinthian paradoxes, Grim, Mar, and St. Denis turn to escape diagrams which plot paths according to the amount of time it takes to escape some set threshold. Revised values for x and y are calculated simultaneously. For example, an escape diagram of the Chaotic Dualist (”X is as true as Y” and “Y is as true as X is false”) displays an intricately nested fractal. Yet, while the attractors for the variants of their 7 Mathematics of Philosophy... Chaotic Dualist are different, the general shape of their corresponding escape diagrams are clearly related. And, in a similar context, they discover the strange fractal of the Sierpinski gadget in the paradox of the Triplist: Socrates: What Plato says is true Plato: What Socrates says is false Chrysippus: Neither Socrates nor Plato speak truly. NDS and Limitative Theorems on Chaos One of the most intriguing and far-reaching implications of The Philosophical Computer’s “dynamical semantics” are its derivation of two limitative theorems (see Machover, 1996) on chaos. Here they are guided by their investigations of the Strengthened Chaotic Liar: Either the boxed sentence has a chaotic semantic behavior or it is as true as it is estimated to be false. Does the Strengthened Chaotic Liar have a chaotic semantic behavior or not? If it does, it will be true in its first disjunct, therefore, the entire sentence will be true. But the semantic behavior of a completely true assertion will not be chaotic. And if the statement does not have a chaotic semantic behavior, its truth value will depend on the second disjunct. But the latter will mimic the behavior of the Chaotic Liar which is chaotic. Guided by their discoveries of this paradox, and claiming fealty to a tradition in mathematical logic that is inspired by paradoxes (e.g., Godel by the Richard Paradox, Tarski by the Liar Paradox, and Chaitin by the Berry Paradox), Grim, Mar, St. Denis prove a theorem in mathematical logic that shows there can be no effective method for deciding whether an arbitrary expression of a system determines a function chaotic on the interval [0,1]. A related second limitative theorem concerns the non-calculability of chaos. I think these two limitative theorems are quite telling in how a dynamical exploration of 8 Mathematics of Philosophy... semantical paradoxes can lead to insights in more purely mathematical, i.e., non-empirical, areas. The Diamond Lattice and Paradox The Philosophical Computer justifies its NDS models by construing paradox in terms of a temporal sequence of deliberations with successive deliberations represented by subsequent functional iterations. Indeed, it is this temporal understanding of paradox which allows them to utilize NDS models in the first place. Such a temporal perspective on paradox, however, is not universally shared. Thus, the influential work of Barwise and Etchemendy (1987) on the paradox of the Liar relied on a hybrid of a-temporal and non-dynamical constructs including graph theory, “hyperset” theory, and the linguistic philosophy of John Austin. And much more recently, Hellerstein (1997) modeled semantic paradoxes using the non-dynamical construct of a lattice which is an array of points spaced with enough regularity that any point can be symmetrically transposed to any other point (e.g., the grid of integers formed by the points of all integral Cartesian coordinates). Since all its grid points are simultaneously present, a lattice is decidedly a-temporal, its main properties having to do with translational symmetry– hence its explication via group-theory (see Kramer, 1981). Contrasting such an a-temporal and nondynamical perspective with The Philosophical Computer’s dynamical approach can lead to greater clarity about the advantages and disadvantages of the dynamical understanding of paradox. Hellerstein’s lattice consists of four values/two components in the shape of a diamond: TRUE = T/T / \ I = T/F J = F/T \ / FALSE = F/F (5) 9 Mathematics of Philosophy... Appended to the customary T and F are two new paradoxical values: I (True but False) designating “undetermined” or “insufficient data for a definite answer”; and J (False but True) defined as “over-determined” or “contradictory data” (I and J are interchangeable). Hellerstein believes his audacious inclusion of two new paradoxical values is analogous to the way complex numbers are a 2-dimensional extension of the real number line that solve x2 = -1. At first sight, the Diamond lattice’s four values may seem paltry compared to the infinitevalued logic of Grim and company’s dynamical approach, yet it is the very simplicity of the Diamond-lattice that is its strength. For example, Hellerstein’s simple model of The Liar I ------------------- J (6) has two solutions, I and J, neither of which require a dynamical unfolding of deliberations. And, once this simple solution is accepted, Hellerstein can use it to resolve more sophisticated paradoxes like those of Russell, Grelling, and Quine. Hellerstein remarks that it is only logicians trained to treat paradox with respect bordering on terror who think there must be more going on than his simple solution. Thus, the logical paradox of “This statement is both true and false,” modeled as the lattice II ------- TF ------ JJ (7) suggests its self-referential similarity to the Liar, whereas, to discover a like similarity, Grim and company had to go to the much greater lengths of their dynamical equations and phase portraits. Likewise, Hellerstein interprets the Dualist paradox Tweedledee: “Tweedledum is a liar” Tweedledum: “Tweedledee is a liar” : as the lattice: TF 10 Mathematics of Philosophy... / \ JJ II \ / FT (8) This again hints at a similar symmetrical structure underlying disparate paradoxes. Moreover, like the forays of The Philosophical Computer into areas in pure mathematics, Hellerstein uses his lattice interpretations of paradox to reinterpret orthodox Cantorian set theory. There is a price, however, to be paid for the simplicity of the lattice, in fact, a dynamical price, since to explicate the power of the lattice approach, Hellerstein introduces two explanatory devices that are replete with temporal and dynamical associations. The first is an electric circuit with a phased operation, i.e., a spring-loaded relay, a switch, and a battery set-up so that if current flows, the relay is energized to break the circuit, but then when there’s no current, the spring-loaded switch reconnects the circuit. The result is a temporally oscillating “buzz” that is quite similar to The Philosophical Computer’s first oscillating dynamical model of the Liar. It’s important to hote, however, that the phased manner in which the electric circuit works points to its temporal and dynamical nature. Similarly, Hellerstein resorts to harmonic functions iterated in order to find fixed points in a manner comparable to the functional iteration of difference equations in NDS. Again, we see the entry of a temporal/dynamical-like notion. Conclusion -- Logical Paradox: Empirical Domain or Mathematical Structure? The very fact that the a-temporal lattice framework had to be supplemented by temporal and dynamical constructs indicates that some sort of dynamical perspective may be inescapable in the development of a more complete understanding of paradox. After all, since semantics 11 Mathematics of Philosophy... consists in processes of human meaning comprehension, paradox must include deliberations about truth values and, therefore, innately unfolds over time. And, of course, it is with such temporally unfolding processes where dynamical systems methods are so appropriate. Furthermore, although it may be a question of temperament, it seems to me that Hellerstein’s electric circuits and harmonic functions are impoverished compared to the rich visual representations afforded by phase portraits and escape diagrams. Yet, it is also true that the latter lack the striking simplicity of the a-temporal lattice models. Consequently, a melding of dynamical with non-dynamical constructs may turn-out to be the most promising new avenue for studying philosophical paradoxes. Another issue concerns the seemingly empirical nature of these modeling strategies. Typically, in empirical research, the adequacy of models are evaluated through their fit with research data, e.g., Guastello’s (1995) structural equations are shown to be better models when they fit the data better than alternatives. But, when it comes to the study of paradoxes, what exactly is to included within the set of data to which the equations are then applied? In the case of The Philosophical Computer, the data set is not forthcoming from initial measurements but arises only afterwards as an outcome of the modeling steps described above. We are not seeing some kind of measurement of cognitive processes involved with such deliberations, but, instead, an interpretation using a mathematical structure. This means that it would inappropriate to evaluate the resulting models by their ability to make better sense out of the data since it is these very models that create the data in the first place! Hence, what does the finding of chaos and fractals in models of paradox really amount to if the data itself arises from models using iterated difference equations which we now know from years of research will yield chaotic dynamics at appropriate parameter values? That is, where have Grim, Mar, and St. Denis actually found 12 Mathematics of Philosophy... chaos and fractals? In the logic of paradox or in their specifically chosen models of paradox? A similar problem is going on with Hellerstein’s lattices. This is not to suggest that these attempts at modeling paradox must necessarily fit the mold of conventional empirical research. But it does lead to the crucial question of how we are to assess their findings. Such musings seem to imply that the mathematical modeling of paradox is not merely a mathematics of philosophy but touches on basic issues in the philosophy of mathematics. Such a conclusion is buttressed by the fact that both the dynamical and the lattice perspectives are used to delve further into other mathematical arenas such as mathematical logic and set theory. Indeed, the very issue of whether to interpret paradox more in a temporal or an atemporal manner is itself an issue that transcends a purely empirical point of view. Again, we are forced to enter the realm of philosophical intuitions that go beyond empirical research as such. It is for these reasons the assessment of these two books requires something different than that for empirical research: they seem to be in a different genre altogether, one, I suggest, more related to mathematics per se, including the philosophy of mathematics, than empirical research. In conclusion, in my opinion, we can better appreciate these examples of modeling philosophical paradox by considering them as following a time-honored strategy in mathematical research: using what is known about one structure to explore a different structure which is isomorphic to the first, e.g., in algebraic topology where theorems in abstract algebras are used to explore topological phenomena isomorphic to those abstract algebras. Mathematics is not science and exploring mathematical structures is not the same as empirical research. Accordingly, it seems more appropriate to view modeling strategies discussed in this paper as the development of new type of mathematics, such as new nonstandard logics (e.g., see Haack, 1996), than traditional empirical research.. 13 Mathematics of Philosophy... ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I wish to thank Terry Marks-Tarlow for her helpful comments on an earlier draft of the section on The Philosophical Computer. REFERENCES: Barwise, J. & Etchemendy, J. (1987). The liar: An essay on truth and circularity. NY: Oxford University Press, 1987. Goldstein, J. (1996). Causality and emergence in chaos and complexity theories. In W. Sulis and A. Combs (Eds.), Nonlinear dynamics in human behavior (Studies of Nonlinear Phenomena in Life Sciences - Volume 5), pp. 161-190, Singapore: World Scientific Publishing. Greeley, L. (1995). Complexity in the attention system of the cognitive generative learning process. In A. Albert (Ed.), Chaos and society, pp. 371-386. Amsterdam: IOS and Presses de l’Universite du Quebec. Grim, P., Mar, G., & St. Denis, P. (1998). The philosophical computer: Exploratory essays in philosophical computer modeling. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press Guastello, S. (1995). Chaos, catastophes, and human affairs; Applications of nonlinear dynamics to work, organizations, and social evolution. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Haack, S. (1996). Deviant logic fuzzy logic: Beyond the formalism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Hellerstein, N. (1997).Diamond: A paradox logic. By. Singapore: World Scientific, 1997, Kramer, E. (1981). The nature and growth of modern mathematics. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Machover, M. (1996). Set theory, logic, and their limitations. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.