New Turns in the Secularization Debate Michael Mason Inst. Adv. Research Australian Catholic University Melbourne, Australia Paper presented at the Annual Meeting of the Society for the Scientific Study of Religion Salt Lake City UT October 31 – November 3, 2002 © M. Mason 2002. Not for citation or reproduction without permission. New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 2 --and living in Australia 2 Synopsis The debate on religion and modernization has taken some interesting new turns in the nineties. Peter Berger, leading former proponent of the “secularization thesis” has reiterated and developed his rejection of the view that the modernization process inevitably entails secularization, and speaks instead of the “desecularization of the world”, and the need to explain, not secularization, but the uniqueness of European secularity. Besides the converts to the “desecularization” thesis, some who have long opposed theories of secularization have deployed a new weapon: rational choice theory. Stark, Iannacone, Finke et al. have applied a “market model” to Christianity both ancient and contemporary, with some persuasive results. In the opposite camp, Brian Wilson, Frank Lechner and most recently Steve Bruce continue to argue the intimate link between modernization and the decline of religion. After some clarifications of the notion of secularization, this paper discusses Berger’s argument against his former theory. He interprets his former assertion of an “intrinsic” linkage between modernization and religious decline as implying that the former is a sufficient cause of the latter. It is argued here that modernization does have an intrinsic tendency to cause religious decline, but is neither a necessary nor a sufficient cause. Religions decline for other reasons, and may thrive despite modernization, because other factors counter modernization’s secularizing effects. Bruce’s recent formulation of secularization theory is assessed, emphasising its robustness against the usual critiques, and against Berger’s specific rebuttal of Bruce’s argument (in an earlier formulation). Several weaknesses in secularization theory exposed by the above discussion are identified: the lack of a systematic theory of the secularising components of modernization, and of the "moderating conditions" which impede modernization's secularizing tendencies; an inadequate understanding of pluralism, which in some circumstances promotes secularization, and in others enhances religious participation; lack of an epistemology of the pre-conceptual, non-discursive knowing involved in religious experience. In the light of recent developments, a clearer articulation of the relationship of secularization on the cultural, societal, organizational and individual levels is required. A “thicker” description of religion as experienced by the participants would enable improved operationalization in empirical research of some of the concepts involved; this in turn would lead to improved measures. Approaches to solutions are proposed, and the necessity of a multidisciplinary approach is emphasised. Australia, particularly the case of the Catholic church, is used throughout as an illustrative “middle-case” of the secularization thesis, lying on a continuum between England and the USA. Data from the national Census and several recent large-scale surveys show the rapid growth in the number of those who say they have “No Religion”, partly because of the movement of large numbers who previously stated a denominational identification into this category. Also demonstrated are declines in religious belief, adherence to religious ethical positions, and in church attendance. The development of secularization in Australia is shown as similar to the process in Holland described by Lechner. Against Casanova’s view of the continuing role for “public religions in the modern world,” these developments undermine the credibility, acceptability and political weight of the public advocacy role of the church, and threaten the demise of church structures supporting major ventures in education, health and social welfare on which that role had depended. New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 3 --and living in Australia 3 In due time, the debate over theories of "secularization" during the twentieth and twenty-first centuries will make a fascinating chapter in the history of ideas. That chapter is not yet ready to be written in earnest; the debate is still in progress, and no one can yet attain the necessary critical distance. But perhaps it is not too early, and at any rate it is too tempting to resist, to sketch some of its likely content. The debate, primarily among sociologists, concerns transformations of "religion", especially during the period of "modernization", and especially in Western societies. An adequate account of it will eventually be a difficult task. "Religion", "modernization" and "secularization" all prove to be slippery terms, whose meanings have themselves changed during the last century of discussion. Compared with other debates within sociology, that on secularization theory seems to have a peculiar intensity. It has not been able entirely to free itself entirely from ideological interests -- the zealotry of the threatened believer, on the one side, and the triumphalism of the Enlightenment reductionist on the other. Often too, because of the elusiveness of the subject matter and the notorious confusion of the terminology, controversialists have fired past each other: more accurate in what they affirmed than in what they denied. It is a matter for some wonder that anyone was still writing about secularization theory at all by 1990. By that date some authors considered it quite passé for a (sub-)discipline now grappling with the postmodern condition of religion. Others had long ago consigned it to the dustbin of disproven and useless sociological speculations. Peter L. Berger, author of the best-known and most convincingly argued version of secularization theory, had repudiated it ten years before (Berger, 1980, 1999, 2001), putting its remaining adherents on the defensive. Thomas Luckmann, co-author with Berger of The Social Construction of Reality (1967), a treatise in the sociology of knowledge which underlay Berger's approach to secularization in his The Sacred Canopy (1969), had from the first, in his own work on religion, The Invisible Religion (1967), eschewed the notion of secularization altogether, adopting a Durkheimian functional perspective on religion as basically identical with the culture's worldview, and deploring the tendency in sociology of religion to identify "church-oriented religiosity" with religion tout court. He saw secularization theory serving as the "myth" of Enlightenment intellectuals eager to assume the mantle of a new priesthood as unquestioned definers of reality (1977:17). British sociologist David Martin, who made a distinguished contribution to mapping the historical and geographical variants of religious transformation in Europe (1978), nonetheless showed considerable ambivalence towards the concept of secularization. Rodney Stark confidently erected its tombstone, entitling an article “Secularization R.I.P.” (1999). Why does it matter whether secularization theory did indeed expire or even whether some authors should attempt now to revive it? It matters because secularization theory undertakes to give an account of the condition of religion in modern society; because a respectable body of opinion, starting with the founding fathers of the discipline of sociology, considered religion and its development to be crucial to an understanding of that New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 4 --and living in Australia society, and because there is a well-defended view that in 2002 the world is still in a ‘late modern’ period1. 4 After the intense debate over secularization in the sixties and seventies, and sporadically since, some important components of it have become, if possible, more confused, rather than clearer. It may therefore be helpful to begin with a preliminary clarification of the concept, by highlighting three important moments in the history of secularization. A. Clarification of the concept of secularization The origins of secularization In its root sense, still preserved in dictionary definitions, the concept of secularization is completely distinct from and independent of, that of modernization. It refers simply to a “change in status” of something previously considered “sacred” or “religious”, whereby it is turned to secular use. ‘Secular’ (Lat. saeculum) means literally ‘of this age’, in contrast to the eternal; hence secular comes to mean: ‘of this world’. An object can be “reclassified” from the service of the “religious” world, to that of the mundane, everyday, or secular world. For example, Henry VIII secularized the English monasteries: turned the buildings, land and revenues over to favoured nobles; from “religious” to secular use. Pews made for churches are now found in fashionable living rooms. A chalice formerly used for the Eucharist could come to be used as nothing more than an ornate wine-goblet. These are all examples of secularization. Nor is there any implication in this process of the decline of religion. On the contrary: the most significant “secularizing” developments in human history have been inspired by religion itself! 1) The secularization of nature The religions of archaic societies pictured in their myths a unified cosmos in which the realms of gods, humans and nature were not distinguished. The universal ‘world-religions’ which succeeded them ‘demythologised’ this archaic vision. In Israel, most of all, the prophetic tradition evolved an understanding of a transcendent God, in opposition to the immanent fertility deities of the land, and of a world which is his creation, and so distinct from him. Thus the ‘disenchantment’ of the world--the vision of a secular realm distinct from an eternal creator God who transcends it, is itself a religious development. All further ‘secularization’ stems from this foundation. 2) The secularization of society—even of religious institutions The prophets likewise criticised temple worship, priesthood and kingship in Israel whenever these institutions sought to endow themselves with sacred absoluteness. Israel herself, although God's chosen people, was nonetheless frequently pictured as an unfaithful spouse, a whore. Jesus extended this prophetic critique of the Temple, of sacrifice, of priests, scribes and Pharisees and further radicalised it to include even the Law itself. This refinement of religious symbols and structures was mirrored in other realms. In archaic religions, although cultic activities were often led by priests, the political and religious leadership of the society were closely merged, with kings often claiming special kinship with the gods. In the emerging historic religions, political and religious leadership began to be separated, and a specialised religious elite 1 In short, that the social, cultural, economic, political changes that have taken place do not require the construction of the category ‘postmodern’, but can be accommodated with greater explanatory power in a within a variant of the category ‘modernity’ viz. ‘late modernity’ which is not so radically out of harmony with the key components of that construct as to require its nullification and replacement. New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 5 --and living in Australia 5 appeared, ‘representing’ the transcendent realm, in tension with the ‘secular’ political leadership (Bellah, 1970: 20-50). In the case of Christianity, after several centuries of persecution, church and state came into enduring alliance under the emperor Constantine. Christianity continued to grapple with the problem of God's separateness-from but involvement-with the world, stressing the former in its doctrines of God, Sin and Redemption, and the latter in the doctrines of Creation, the Incarnation, Grace and Sacraments. At the time of the Reformation, this issue came to a head with reference to the church and its role as the mediator of grace and salvation. Catholicism saw the church as sacrament, as the body of Christ, continuing the incarnation, mediating saving grace by its sacraments and teaching. For the churches of the Reformation generally, a kind of secularization or ‘disenchantment’ of the church itself was seen as a demand of the Gospel. The ‘Protestant principle’, emphasising the sovereignty of God, rejected ‘every human claim to finality and absoluteness’. ‘Every religious institution, every creed, every pattern of worship, shares in the limitations and distortions (i.e., sin) of human existence’ (Dillenberger and Welch, 1954: 313). So the church too is subject to corruption and requires continual reformation. This view denies ‘divinity’ to a human organization and strips away from the church, its saints and its rituals the aura of power which has given rise at times to elements of superstition and magic in practices of devotion. Dorothy Day, doughty modern champion of the poor, captures both Protestant and Catholic emphases in her famous remark on the church: ‘She may be a whore, but she's our mother.’ For many modern Christians, this ‘secularization’ of the understanding of the church represents, by biblical and theological standards, an unqualified advance--a major emancipation of the human spirit from the bondage of institutional idolatry. And the critical perspective on human institutions and human motivation, shaped by the prophets and the reformers, has become common coin in modern culture through the work of the ‘masters of suspicion’--theorists such as Marx, Freud and Nietzsche, whose work has tended further to unmask in all human endeavours the elements of mixed and self-serving motivation. This second major symbolic secularization also had its social consequences. The Reformation critique had weakened the political status of the church and legitimated the independence of secular political and economic institutions. Although Christian churches remained ‘established’ in European societies (even, in diluted form, up to the present in some countries), their capacity to infuse the whole of society with sacred meaning was greatly diminished. Accelerating developments from the middle of the eighteenth century brought social secularization almost to its logical conclusion. The American and French revolutions gave rise to states in which the churches were deprived of the legal privilege of establishment. Increasingly, even where there were religiously-based political parties, the State itself was considered to be ‘secular’--neutral as between the claims of various religious groups. Craft was no longer organised by religious guilds, commerce was freed from theological prohibitions on the earning of interest. Major social functions like education, health care and social welfare, which in the past have been conducted largely under the auspices of religious bodies, are now entrusted mainly to secular agencies (especially the State). 3) The secularization of culture If one major strand in the process of secularization is the religious emphasis on the distinctness of a transcendent God from the world of nature, and a second, the sovereign independence of the same God from all human social institutions, religious as well as political, then a third, of no less importance, is the secularization of culture through the vindication of the autonomy of reason. Christianity's origins in the New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 6 --and living in Australia 6 Hellenistic world meant that from the first it attempted to interpret its Judaic heritage in the light of Greek philosophy. The secularization of nature and society already carried the implication that these realities had their own intelligibility. Christianity took the further awesome step of assuming that God also was, at least to some degree, rationally intelligible. For the next thousand years, Christian theology expounded its scriptural base in terms of Platonist-Augustinian, and later Aristotelian, models. In the Aristotelian system developed by Aquinas, it is precisely because they depend on the nature of God (rather than on the divine will) that created realities share the intelligibility common to Being. The dignity and role of reason thus received religious legitimation, and in the centuries after the Reformation had both strengthened the this-worldly focus of the Christian calling, and weakened the church's dominance of intellectual life, reason found a voice independent of theology and gave birth to modern philosophy and science. 4) The impact of secularization What has been the cumulative impact of these major movements of secularization? So far we have stressed their religious inspiration and what many see as their ‘refining’ consequences for religion. Religion can be seen as strengthened by these changes; many believers would prefer, on religious grounds, to live in the religious and moral environment of a secular era rather than hark back to an earlier epoch. But we should not be blind to the fact that secularization also entails a contraction in the cultural and social reach and influence of religion. (It does not seem appropriate to refer to this as a ‘decline’ on the part of religion since it is at least partly caused by religious traditions redefining themselves and limiting their own scope – i.e. it is a case of religious self-restraint -- even if, as seems likely, the actors involved did not fully anticipate the consequences of their actions.) The societal process of secularization as we have defined it leaves religious institutions and levels of individual involvement much more open to variation than before. It opens the gates to further decline on institutional and individual levels, but these outcomes are subject to many other influences and so are neither certain nor irreversible. What Luckmann calls the ‘privatization’ of religion--its loss of dominion over the major social institutions of the public sphere, can come to mean that only in the individual's ‘private’ life, in the sphere of leisure and voluntary activities, is religion seen to have a place. Obviously, people nowadays make less use than formerly of religious beliefs and values in making sense of their lives, since these ‘other-worldly’ principles of interpretation have largely been replaced, in the secular institutions of the ‘public’ sphere, by ‘rational’ frameworks whose horizon is ‘this-worldly’. Detached from the political, economic and social functions which mobilise communities into being, religion can come to focus more and more on the solitary individual, or at best to involve only family and friends. In place of the great ‘ultimate’ questions of the meaning of life and death with which religion has been traditionally concerned, its primary themes are now often restricted to those on which alienated moderns confer a kind of ultimacy or sacredness: the autonomy of the individual and his ‘self-expression’ and ‘self-realization’.2 A host of therapies and ‘spiritualities’ compete in a kind of religious ‘supermarket’ to assuage the modern sense of rootlessness and loss of identity. They include some traditional religious themes, now detached from their theological and institutional base, but also Eastern syncretism, occultism, and ‘New Age’ nostrums. The secularization of knowledge in time went far beyond its religious origins (see Chadwick 1975, McLeod 2000). One influential modern worldview denies religion any relevance at all in the political, 2 This understanding of secularization was first formulated by Thomas Luckmann (1967). A later statement of his position is found in Luckmann (1990). New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 7 --and living in Australia 7 economic and social spheres, and goes further to deny the existence of God and the validity of all subjective conceptions of religious transcendence in the private sphere. ‘Secularism’, as it is generally called, constitutes a profound challenge to religion in its entirety. Often in recent years the word ‘secularization’ has been used to imply the inevitable, and desirable, demise of religion. It should be obvious that in this use, the word has taken on an ideological edge derived from what we have called secularism. In other words, it is a myth (Luckmann 1977: 17), which embodies the ‘interests’ of groups (especially intellectuals) who aspire to succeed to the position of cultural authority once held by religious functionaries. Secularization makes secularism possible, but its full realization is by no means determined. In summary, three major movements of secularization in human history stem from religious roots, and occurred prior to the modern era. Secularization, then, has no intrinsic relationship to modernization (as effect to cause). Secularization theory posits that the reverse is not true: that modernization does have an intrinsic tendency to promote secularization. This once-broadly-supported view has come under increasing criticism in the last twenty years, and is now on the defensive. Insight into the controversy can be furnished by examining the repudiation of secularization theory by Peter Berger, one of its principal modern architects, and the contrary efforts of able spokesmen, Frank Lechner and Steve Bruce, to maintain it. B. Berger’s argument against secularization theory, and specifically that of Steve Bruce Berger’s early definition of the modern process of secularization remains the simplest and clearest of all those that have been proposed: “the removal of sectors of society and culture from the domination of religious institutions and symbols” (1969). Bruce’s definition is somewhat more concrete: Secularization [is] a social condition manifest in a) the declining importance of religion for the operation of non-religious roles and institutions such as those of the state and the economy; b) a decline in the social standing of religious roles and institutions and c) a decline in the extent to which people engage in religious practices, display beliefs of a religious kind and conduct other aspects of their lives in a manner informed by such beliefs (Bruce 2002: 3).3 Both definitions tend to imply a link between the secularization of institutions and the secularization of consciousness; a link that Berger is now at pains to reject (Berger 1999: p. 3), and which Bruce wishes to argue is inherent. Earlier forms of secularization theory focussed almost exclusively on these developments in Western societies, and concluded that religion faced a continuing diminution of its role, functions and influence in modern society, culture and individual consciousness. They also assumed that the same pattern would be followed in modernizing societies in the developing countries of Asia, the Middle East and Africa. But then the vigorous emergence of religiously-inspired, anti-Western variants of modernity in these same countries appears to have inspired some former secularization theorists to reconsider their position. Among them was Peter Berger, who made a point of publicly renouncing some aspects of his former 3 This definition is similar to that of Brian Wilson (1982: 149). New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 8 --and living in Australia 8 theory (Berger 1980). Significantly, the title of that article is “From secularity to world religions”. Although Berger’s ‘recantation’ is now very old news, it is still the subject of debate, stimulated by a collection he edited (1999), by a symposium on his former secularization theory (Woodhead 2001), and no doubt by the fact that it remains a ‘burr under the saddle’ of subsequent secularization theorists like Bruce, who wish to embrace much of what Berger has repudiated, and therefore must deal with his reasons for rejecting it. In stark contrast to the titles of his earlier works, a collection of articles Berger edited in 1999 was called “The Desecularization of the World: Resurgent Religion and World Politics”. It serves to dramatise the response to modernization of societies outside the narrow confines of the West. Defying the predictions of religion’s decline in earlier secularization theories, a ‘resurgence’ of religion was observed as these societies discovered resources in both traditional4 and newer5 religions for imposing a variety of new shapes on the process of modernization as it evolved locally. Does this amount to a ‘desecularization of the world’? Perhaps not quite. It would be difficult to point to examples of societies where secularization has taken firm hold, which have subsequently been “desecularized” -- returned to something like their pre-secular religious condition. Some writers point to the replacement of ‘conventional’ religious forms by ‘New Age’ movements, and the increased growth of superstitious practices such as astrology, but as we shall show in the case of Australia, (and as others have already argued in other cases) these developments have little influence, and do not return a society to anything remotely like the pre-pluralist religious homogeneity and vigour of earlier stages. As the key reason for his repudiation of his former position, Berger cites the loss of his conviction that modernization necessarily causes secularization: Although the term ‘secularization theory’ refers to works from the 1950s and 1960s, the key idea of the theory can indeed be traced to the Enlightenment. That idea is simple: modernization necessarily leads to a decline of religion, both in society and in the minds of individuals. And it is precisely this key idea that has turned out to be wrong (Berger, 1999). Responding to Bruce, he phrases his argument a little differently: If modernization and secularization are intrinsically linked, one would have to argue that the United States is less modern than, say, the United Kingdom . . . As to the rest of the world, full of massive religious explosions, it won’t do to explain this in terms of a lesser degree of modernization. . . . There does indeed exist the phenomenon of secularization, and more specifically the version of it that one may call Eurosecularity. But one cannot assume that this is the normal concomitant of modernity (Berger, 2001). “Intrinsically linked” is taken to imply that the degree of secularization should correspond to the extent of modernization. Logical enough, if secularization necessarily, inevitably, follows from modernization. And we must of course agree with Berger that it has become clear that there is no strict and immediately effective link producing secularization as the inevitable consequence of modernization. 4 5 One example: a newly militant Islam. See for example, Martin, (1990 and 2002) on Pentecostalism. New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 9 --and living in Australia 9 But outside the realm of the physical sciences (where, for example, a rise in the temperature of a gas follows with law-like inevitability from an application of increased pressure) where do we ever find this kind of ‘necessary link’? Is it possible in history or social science ever to conclude from cause to effect; to say that B follows A with strict necessity? We submit that it is not, for the following reasons: unless we posit a completely mechanistic and deterministic model of human behaviour, influences on human action do not operate with the constraining force of physical causes; even if they did, we do not possess the comprehensive knowledge of complex human situations which would permit strict prediction. An influence in one direction may be countered by an unforseen, opposed influence; given all known influences, human agents may find reasons for actions in still other directions. In other words, “necessarily, inevitably” was always an overstatement of the theory’s rigour, and its removal merely introduces a modesty more becoming for a social science, but otherwise takes away nothing from the theory. Social science proceeds inductively by observing patterned regularities in human action; from these it forms, first, empirical generalizations which associate events with regularly concomitant circumstances.: “A and B are ‘associated’ phenomena: they ‘vary together’”. In some cases, it can hypothesise, test and tentatively posit a cause-and-effect relationship; but never with the deductive certainty of physical law. Students of modernization in Europe observed that it was often accompanied or followed by secularization, and proposed hypotheses accounting for some kinds of secularization by means of the causal influence of modernization. These hypotheses appeared to be verified in some countries, but their applicability to the United States was controversial. Over the following fifty years, the pace of modernization increased in various non-Western countries, and there it was observed that secularization did not appear to be following as expected. Berger’s conclusion seems justified: “it [secularization] is not the normal concomitant of modernization”. But does it follow that modernization is never a cause of secularization -- that there is no “intrinsic link” between them – that their apparent association is ‘spurious’, purely extrinsic or accidental? It seems possible to disagree with him concerning what is required for the link to be intrinsic. We submit that an ‘intrinsic link’ exists if the modernization process, or some specific form of it, has an inherent tendency or potency to secularize a society, a culture, an individual’s consciousness. Whether it succeeds in doing so may depend on other factors. If we are to understand Berger’s argument, we need to be conceptually precise in understanding terms such as ‘necessary’, ‘follows necessarily’, ‘intrinsic’. A cause is that which, of itself, considered according to what is proper to it, tends to produce a particular effect. It is not part of the definition of a cause that the effect always follows. A cause is said to be sufficient if given that cause, and without any other requirement, the effect does always follow. If A, then (always) B. This does not involve asserting that A is required for B to occur: it could simultaneously be true that if C, then always B. A cause is said to be necessary if the effect never occurs without it. If, and only if A, then B (but perhaps not always). In the absence of A, B never occurs. Given A, B may or may not occur. Just as a sufficient cause may not be necessary, so a necessary cause may not be sufficient: it may be the case that: if and only if A, and given also condition X, B may follow. Condition X is a condition sine qua non. It is not New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 10 --and living in Australia 10 itself a cause, but it “opens the gate” to the operation of a cause; without it, even given A, B will not follow. Given both A and the condition X, B may follow, but then again, it may not. A moment taken to apply these distinctions to the issue under discussion is sufficient to convince that modernization is neither a necessary nor a sufficient cause of secularization. Not a necessary cause, because secularization evidently has other causes: the instances we cited earlier of the great movements of secularization of nature, society and culture which occurred (under directly religious impulses) in pre-modern times show that modernization is not at all required for secularization to take place. Not a sufficient cause because secularization has not occurred to any significant degree in some societies where modernization is quite advanced. If then, modernization is neither a necessary nor a sufficient cause of secularization, are we forced to concede Berger’s point that there is no ‘intrinsic’ linkage between the two processes? No – and this is the nub of our argument against Berger’s rejection of secularization theory – modernization can even under these circumstances be properly considered a cause of secularization provided that it inherently, of itself, tends to bring about secularizing effects. The effects may not follow; it need not be either a sufficient or necessary cause, and may depend for its effect on a whole series of conditions, yet so long as, all other things being equal, modernization contains within itself components that tend to secularize a society, the “intrinsic link” between the two remains in force. The case that modernity, under certain conditions, tends to secularize, hardly has to be argued anew; Berger’s earlier work delineates those tendencies in great detail, and in fact, he still concedes that modernity has such a tendency – not “normally”, but at least sometimes: To be sure, modernization has had some secularizing effects, more in some places than in others. But it has also provoked powerful movements of counter-secularization (1999: 3). Berger’s second sentence here cannot be read to indicate that modernization can serve equally well to promote either secularization or its contrary (the actual effect depending entirely on some other condition), since this would contradict what the first sentence asserts: that (in some cases ) secularization is the effect of modernization. Obviously, it is through its tendency to secularize that it provokes the contrary reaction. So he retains the notion of modernization as a cause of secularization – i.e. tending to bring it about, regardless of whether the effect actually follows. This would seem to qualify modernization as having an “intrinsic link” with secularization, in terms of the clarification proposed above; Berger evidently takes the phrase “intrinsic link” to mean that modernization is a sufficient cause of secularization, so he rejects it. In cases where Berger concedes that secularization has occurred in modern times – e.g., to an advanced degree in contemporary Europe, while not denying that modernization may play a causal role, Berger does not see this as an adequate explanation. Europe is a deviant case, in contrast to the worldwide norm of the flourishing of religion, and the task of explaining it is “The most interesting topic for the sociology of religion today”(Berger, 2001: 194) . New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 11 --and living in Australia 11 It seems appropriate, then, to join him in his rejection of a rigid link of causal sufficiency between modernization and secularization, if not in his jettisoning of the whole of “secularization theory” along with it. His counter-arguments can be taken instead to indicate an incompleteness in secularization theory which requires a remedy. What conditions tend to bring about secularization as an outcome of modernization (e.g. in the European case) , and what other conditions delay, impede, or neutralise the secularizing tendencies inherent in modernization? We will return to this question below as an example of a lacuna in secularization theory. The version of secularization theory formerly espoused by Berger was moderate and highly nuanced; he did not predict as inevitable either the imminent or eventual demise of religion, (nor does Bruce). All of his former arguments linking modernization with secularization, (with the qualification that the “link” is flexible, rather than rigid) retain their validity, and their acuity in uncovering the tendencies inherent in the modernization process, to secularize not only societies, cultures and institutions, but the religious consciousness of individuals. Moreover, this explanation, with the clarifications we have suggested, still provides the best understanding of those cases where the loss of influence of religion in both social and personal life occurs, and where components of the modernization process can be shown to be at work. This is the position now championed by Steve Bruce. Berger stresses that he wants to retain one other component of his former theory: the effect of pluralism in undermining the taken-for-granted certainty of religious (and other) beliefs. But he no longer sees this effect as necessarily secularizing, even in the longer term: . . . it is possible to hold beliefs, and to live by them, even if they no longer hold the status of taken-for-granted certainties (in Woodhead, 2001:194). Berger does less than justice here to the full power of his former argument for the secularizing effect of pluralism. Its effect of removing a “taken-for-granted certainty” from religious beliefs could scarcely have occurred often in recent centuries, since such certainty was lost in most societies when they emerged from their primitive stage. Even the great-grandparents of present generations in Western countries did not exist in an era when religious certainties were completely taken-for-granted. The full phenomenological sense of this phrase implies that alternatives never arise in consciousness, are not even conceivable. But in some religiously pluralistic countries, people have lived for centuries cheek by jowl with members of other denominations, and thus fallen under Berger’s “heretical imperative”: religion was for them, at least to some extent, a matter of choice. That is implied in the very notion of ‘denomination’ as it is usually defined sociologically. Taken-for-granted certainty is not a feature of even the pre-modern religious paradigm – indeed, it probably should be confined to the milieu of “primitive” religions which seem to have originally inspired it. Pluralism however, as Berger himself has argued in the past, particularly in The Heretical Imperative (1975), has other secularizing effects not so easily set aside. So a second requirement for an adequate theory of secularization is the (re)gaining of an understanding of pluralism, particularly the kind of pluralism associated with modernization, and of the conditions under which it can be shown (against “new paradigm” rational choice theory) to promote secularization. New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 12 --and living in Australia 12 This brief review has shown that Berger has not completely abandoned secularization theory; rather his critique of it points to two aspects in which the theory requires further development. Before reflecting further on that task, it will be helpful to survey the contribution of Steve Bruce, who leaped fearlessly on to the wagon of secularization after so many others had abandoned it as obsolete, and drove off at speed, casting off the funereal drapes in which the “new paradigm” fraternity had swathed it. C. Bruce’s version of secularization theory Steve Bruce’s distinction is to have retained the best of past secularization theories, and to have done more than other sociologists since David Martin’s marvellous A General Theory of Secularization (1978), to tease out the mixture of causal influences and moderating or impeding conditions under which modernization sometimes brings about the secularizing social effects towards which it naturally tends, and is at other times impeded or delayed in bringing about such effects.6 It is to an assessment of his version of secularization theory in its most recent expression (2002) that we now turn. It is beyond our scope here to describe, even in outline, Bruce’s entire theory. It is not, in any case, too different from that of Brian Wilson or the earlier Berger. However, some salient aspects are worth noting: its robustness against the criticisms which led others to consign secularization theory to the sociological graveyard, and specifically against Berger’s rejoinder to it.7 Bruce has developed his theory in a number of recent works (1990, 1996, 1999, 2001,2002), one of which (1999) was entirely devoted to a rebuttal of the “supply-side” thesis of Stark, Fink, Iannacone and others. Here we focus on the latest presentation and fullest development of his theory in God is Dead: Secularization in the West (2002). Bruce defends his position against the usual criticisms of secularization theory by emphasising the following features of it (2002: 37): -secularization is not presented as either universal or inevitable; it is not comparable to a law of nature of the kind discovered in physics or biology; he describes the historically and geographically specific circumstances in which secularization occurs (or does not occur). The scope of the theory is confined to the situation of religion in Western Europe since the Reformation, and in North America and Australia. He goes slightly beyond Brian Wilson’s position on the point of inevitability, pointing out that some historically contingent changes, once made, are extremely unlikely to be reversed: they were not inevitable, but they did occur, and having occurred, became firmly established. Egalitarianism and an expectation of a high level of individual freedom in private life are two examples, both of which tend to promote further religious diversity. It is impossible to imagine these societies submitting to the authority required to return a religiously diverse society to homogeneity. -the theory does not rest on the assumption of “progress”, nor is it part of a “secularist” agenda; Bruce quotes sympathetically Weber’s view of the disenchanted, rational, bureaucratised world as an “the iron cage” and Wilson’s prognosis of the breakdowns likely in civil order in the absence of the controlling power of religiously-based morality. 6 Historians, on the other hand, have always emphasised this variability, and expressed scepticism about the possibility of adequately accounting for it by sociological generalizations. 7 An amicable exchange of views between Bruce and Berger occurs in Woodhead (2001) – Bruce wrote a chapter, and Berger a brief rejoinder. New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 13 --and living in Australia 13 -to those who criticise secularization theory as poor or very limited theory, Bruce concedes the point; but systematic and universal theories have tended to become so abstract as to have no practical usefulness. He cites Stark’s rational-choice “religious market economy” as an example. -despite the rapid and in some respects quite uniform advances in modernization, the trajectory of secularization is uneven or “lumpy”, because institutions caught up in the process have their own histories, which may lead them to resist consequences of modernization successfully. There are also causes of secularization which are independent of the modernization process: Bruce cites the example of the support of the Spanish Church for Franco, which probably alienated it from the masses. A century and more before, the French Church’s support for the ancien regime seems to have had the same effect of deeply and irreversibly alienating the populace. There are good reasons to suggest that some Catholics and members of other denominations will be alienated from their churches, and perhaps eventually from their faith, by the recent rash of revelations of sexual abuse of minors by clergy. The indications in our Australian findings8 are that it is the failure of Church authorities to exercise care for victims, and act to prevent future abuse, that is the focus of outrage and alienation among adherents, rather than a loss of confidence in clergy in general as if all were potential abusers of children. The institutions and their leaders seem to have been motivated much more by concern to maintain their good name, than by a sense of outrage, a thirst for justice, and compassion, together with an imperative towards active care, for those who had suffered serious harm. In ordinary, and even more in Christian, ethical terms, this is a serious and indefensible dereliction of duty, more to be expected of a ruthlessly self-interested corporation than a religious body. But the relevant point for the present discussion is that any effects of loss of influence of religion that follow in this case should not immediately be attributed to “modernization”. Scandal and disillusionment are sufficient explanation. On the other hand, the actions of governments and police in prosecuting, and of the media in reporting, abuses on the part of clergy, are a distinctively recent development in Englishspeaking countries, and have become possible as a result of an acceleration of secularization since the 1970s, which can be traced to typically “modern” changes in the relationship between religious bodies, governments and media, and society at large. Against those who criticise secularization theory on the grounds that it presupposes as a terminus a quo or starting point a “Golden Age” of total religious dominance which never empirically existed, Bruce argues convincingly that such critics make two mistakes: they expect to find the equivalent of modern Protestant ‘true believers’ in the past (we could add that though there were such enthusiasts, they were usually part of some sect-like movement of reform, and prefigured some Protestant characteristics – but of course this style of religiosity is essentially ‘oppositional,’ and was not the mediaeval norm). Second, such critics misread the abundant historical evidence of the powerlessness of the church to quell the perennial old magic and superstition, concluding falsely that Christianity never had much of a hold on the population. Bruce points out that such a conclusion seems to ignore the obvious: that such people lived in a ‘thoroughly supernaturalistic’ world (2002: 58). And we might add in support that from the perspective of the disciplines of anthropology and history of religions, the confident distinctions made by some sociologists between religion and magic seem likely to contain a hidden theological defensive component, and do not survive close examination; a more neutral view is likely to reclassify what Christianity has stigmatised as ‘superstitions’ as religious (in a more neutral sense), although perhaps 8 Appendix, Table 2. New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 14 --and living in Australia 14 belonging to a less religiously differentiated period. The only question, Bruce insists, is whether there is . . . an identifiable difference in the popularity and salience of beliefs, actions and institutions that assume the existence of supernatural entities with powers of action, or impersonal powers and processes possessed of moral purpose (58)9 In the following four chapters, Bruce engages the empirical evidence on religion and several major variants which some scholars nominate as successors of the older traditions, in their argument against the secularization thesis. So first he takes up the case of the condition of the former mainstream religion in Britain, and afterwards discusses the slightness of New Age religiosity, the influence of science in the process of secularization, and the vogue enjoyed by Westernised Eastern religious forms. We will shortly refer to Australian evidence on these themes. Three chapters on methodological flaws in commonly advanced arguments against secularization are particularly interesting and enjoyable. Here Bruce is in his element, he answers his critics in argument laced with sarcastic wit. Yet, unlike some less principled writers on the topic, he shows no real malice and does not engage in unfair distortions of the arguments of his opponents. Bruce is not an especially systematic thinker (one easily gets lost in his “paradigm”, and his explanation of it is laboured and unclear). More seriously, he appears to lose focus on part of his argumentative task: undertaking to vindicate the secularization paradigm includes showing not merely that there is evidence of a significant degree of secularization in the West, but that it is a result of modernization rather than adequately explicable as the result of other causes. One of the methodological chapters discusses the danger of so emphasising exceptions that their capacity to “prove the rule” is blurred; a second deals in brief compass with refuting the Stark et al “supply side” approach, while allowing its usefulness in some circumstances; and a third deals with methodological mistakes leading some writers to claims that they discern more ‘non-organised religion’ than Bruce finds warranted. An oddly-placed chapter discusses the claim that the charismatic movement constitutes an exception to the general thesis; then Bruce confronts what is always the most formidable counter-example: religion in the contemporary USA. While he does so convincingly on the whole, his repetition of Berger’s (early) strictures on the self-focussed religion of Norman Vincent Peale, and later, Robert Schuller, does not address the much more typical religious style of dominant groups like the Southern Baptist Convention. Bruce next presents the case for secularization in Britain in a very workmanlike way, showing a thorough mastery of data, with which he is obviously intimately familiar. In this paper, we will utilise Australian findings to furnish this part of the argument. Since this passage also contains Bruce’s preferred definition of religion, it is worth noting, that like Berger before him (1969, Appendix 2 “On substantive versus functional definitions of religion”), and for exactly the same reasons, Bruce argues for a substantive definition. 9 New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 15 --and living in Australia 15 Finally there is a very pertinent chapter on the claim that the advent of ‘postmodernism’ has inaugurated an era of potentially unlimited resurgence of religion – not in its past institutionally-based shape, but in the universalization of ‘spirituality’ and in the emergence of multitudinous new forms that are arising under the stimulus of the condition of new freedom for the individual in a post-Enlightenment, postrational society. This is one of the most clearly written chapters in the book, and at last deals explicitly with the secularizing components of modernization, and how they operate in practice to achieve their effects. While he does not directly cite the work of Alain Touraine, his refutation counters a good proportion of the arguments in favour of a new spiritual vitality giving rise to New Religious Movements, and a wave of uninstitutionalised ‘spirituality’ supposedly emerging in the unstructured postmodern situation. Bruce de-emphasises the role of science and philosophy as influences towards secularization. Michael Paul Gallagher (1990)10 takes the same approach, arguing that it is neither science nor philosophical atheism per se which convinces non-intellectuals to abandon their religious beliefs, but they “pick up the drift second-hand” that the experts in particular forms of rationality have (in the words of the famous reply given to Napoleon by La Mettrie, author of Man the Machine) ‘no need for the hypothesis’ (of the existence of God). To the “masters of suspicion”: Marx, Freud and Nietzsche, add Durkheim, Darwin and his successors down to Dawkins. We could summarise the positions of Berger and Bruce by saying that in the light of the interpretation we have offered above, there is little real conflict between them, despite the contradictory rhetoric. The difference between the former and later positions of Berger is a refinement, rather than a total repudiation, and Bruce’s position is largely compatible with Berger’s later one, despite Berger’s rejection of Bruce’s arguments. If by “the uniqueness of European secularity” Berger means that nowadays he does not recognise any secularizing trend elsewhere, we would have a real contradiction to deal with, but it is far more likely that he does not consider that the American evidence supports the conclusion that the US should be included with Europe as a secularized society. Where one draws the line in such cases raises complex problems involving the proper boundary between sociology and history; but Bruce, one suspects, would have to agree, which would do no real damage to his paradigm. While, in this assessment, Bruce makes an original contribution, and achieves the most comprehensive and defensible statement of secularization theory so far, nonetheless, a number of weaknesses in secularization theory constitute obstacles to further progress, and make it likely that secularization theory will remain in contestation for the foreseeable future. D. Secularization theory: some weaknesses and proposed refinements (This section is undergoing revision) The following are proposed as aspects of secularization theory which need strengthening: 1) Inadequate specification of the conditions which moderate the secularizing effects of modernization, for example, the intimate entwining of religion and ethnic or national identity; a pillarized structure on the part of one or more religious groups; and of other factors which seem, by contrast, to promote secularization, such as the “cultural revolution” of the early 1970s, whose impact on the Catholic Church in Holland is discussed by Lechner (1996). 2) Lack of a fully systematic theory of the secularizing components of modernization, and particularly of An Irish theologian and expert on ‘unbelief’, formerly Secretary of the Vatican’s Secretariat for NonBelief. 10 New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 16 --and living in Australia 16 the multiple dimensions of pluralism, its different effects in different circumstances, and on different types of groups; also of rationalization and privatization. 3) The relationship between the various “levels” of secularization: cultural, societal, organizational and individual, needs to be re-articulated in the light of recent theory, research and critique. 4) Some empirical research on religion, pluralism and secularization (for instance, some of the “new paradigm” studies), can be criticised as resting on a conception of the experience of the believer which is so phenomenologically “thin” that it tends to parody religion; a “thicker” description, to use Geertz’s metaphor, could lead to improved operationalization of the complex concepts of secularization theory and hence to better measures. a) Lack of a systematic theory of the moderating conditions of secularization. One component of a fully satisfactory sociological theory still lacking in both Berger’s and Bruce’s work is a systematic account of (at least the principal) factors which modify the effects of the secularizing tendencies of modernization – blocking them entirely, delaying them for long periods, and/or moderating their effects. This account should also indicate the conditions under which secularization at the societal or organizational level corresponds to secularization at the level of individual consciousness, and the factors which sometimes act to maintain a divergence between levels. To what extent is such an account possible? No doubt a considerable proportion of the variation in the course of secularization in different countries is shaped by irreducibly contingent historical factors, but the resources of sociological explanation do not seem yet to have been exhausted in the search for systematic factors. Observing the process of modernization in non-Western societies, scholars have become aware that the secularizing consequences which earlier theory led them to expect did not seem to be occurring. But why should we expect the process of modernization itself to be independent of the cultural matrix within which it is replicating?11 Eisenstadt proposes that there are “multiple modernizations” and “multiple modernities”: The classical theories of modernization . .conflated these different dimensions of modernity [structural, institutional and cultural], . . . and assumed that historically they do come together . . . that the basic institutional constellations which came together in European modernity and the cultural program of modernity as it developed in the West will “naturally” ultimately be taken over in all modernizing societies. . . . But the reality that emerged proved radically different (2000:39). Eisenstadt goes on to show how the Western paradigm of modernity is continually contested and redefined; and especially how strongly religious societies can give rise to “fundamentalist” responses which utilise some of the components of modernity (for example, by appropriating technologies resulting from globalization of communications) to campaign against other (especially Western) components. Luckmann (1990) argues that “fundamentalist responses” may be expected in non-Western societies, which have not shared the long and gradual cultural evolution of the West into its modern form: “The – relatively – sudden loss of religious legitimations for everyday life seems to lead to anti-modernist 11 David Martin (1978) developed a set of quite systematic explanations covering many of the major patterns of historical variation in the process of secularization. New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 17 --and living in Australia 17 reactions among substantial segments of the population of “modernizing” countries” (Luckmann, 1990: 137). However, there is still something in the notion that it is modernization that tends to accelerate and carry further the process of secularization (which arises quite independently from pre-modern and religious sources) that should give us pause. There are of course currently ‘modernizing’ societies; but in the West, the key characteristics of social ‘modernity’, such as advanced social differentiation, pluralism, bureaucratization and technological development, date back at least to the Industrial Revolution, and in the case of religious pluralism, to the Reformation. But although later manifestations of secularization may be seen to have their roots in these developments, the supposed secularizing impact of modernization was, to say the least, long delayed, and the delay varies greatly from one society to another. Clearly there are retarding factors at work. In Europe, secularization has a history peculiar to each nation, and severe declines in popular participation stretch back to the Revolutions of 1789 and 1848, and were deepened by each of the 20th century’s two World Wars; but in the English-speaking countries, after something of a religious boom in the fifties and sixties, it is particularly when we come to the nineteen seventies that accelerated social and cultural changes impacting negatively on religious belief and behaviour begin to be cited as empirical evidence of secularization. Yet neither in continental Europe nor in England and its former colonies, is secularization contemporaneous with modernization. No one denies these obvious facts, but they should surely give rise to a modification of theories that tie modernization and secularization together: if the former is a driving influence towards the latter, then there are obviously unnamed, but very powerful braking forces at work, impeding, or at least retarding for very long periods, the secularizing impact of modernization. Or are we compelled to admit that modernization is not at all the motor of secularization; it is some other influence, or at the very least, some later-developing component of modernization not present or effective in its earliest phases? A good deal of attention has been given to one moderating factor: the entwining of religion with national identity. Where the two are closely related, and especially when one nation is under hegemonic control by another, secularizing tendencies seem to be completely nullified. Poland in the Cold War era is an excellent example -- all the better because after the historic collapse of the Soviet Union, the formerly packed Catholic seminaries in Poland saw a considerable exodus, and religious fervour and practice have begun to decline significantly. Clearly there are other such factors, and the theory would be greatly improved by carrying forward David Martin’s work in this direction, begun in A General Theory of Secularization (1978). Eisenstadt’s recent work on ‘multiple modernizations’ (2000) is a valuable contribution. Australia makes an interesting case of the entwining of religion and ethnic (rather than national) identity. A high proportion of the convicts in the original settlements were Irish and Catholic. Although the Church of England was not formally established in the colony, it was de facto the religion of the hated establishment, symbolised to perfection in the figure of Rev. Samuel Marsden – “the flogging parson” – both a clergyman and a magistrate, notorious for the brutality of his sentences. Although secondary industry was slow to develop, the country was from its foundation culturally modern and secular in the post-Enlightenment sense. Its nascent institutions were strongly shaped by developing in the very heyday of English secularist thought. The State education system shaped in the 1850s was to New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 18 --and living in Australia 18 be “free, compulsory and secular” and its secularity was expressly and militantly anti-religious (particularly anti-Catholic). The position of religion in the colony was slighted from the very beginning. Yet, for all that, as the Catholic, Methodist and Presbyterian churches took their place amongst freedmen and free settlers, the course of the denominations until the middle of the twentieth century was one of steady growth. During the nineteenth century, and up to the end of World War I in the 20th, Catholics were the object of explicit prejudice and both social and economic repression, and led by combative Irish bishops,12 continued to enjoy the solidarity of an oppressed group with a visible common enemy, united by their religion and the massive alternative school system built largely without Government subsidies. 13 By the end of the Second World War, the Catholic education system had succeeded in its task of raising the social status of succeeding generations of Catholics, and they had been gradually admitted to the ranks of the public service, the professions (especially law and medicine), and all but the higher levels of business. Religio-ethnic solidarity began to matter somewhat less from this time, and in the wave of immigration, especially from Southern and Central Europe, during the nineteen-fifties, the church was transformed from an Irish ethnic enclave into the most “multi-cultural” of all religious groups. A structure had been built analogous to what European sociologists14 describe as “pillarization” – a layercake of institutions in different religious communities catering for their own members – neatly defined by Lechner (1996: 258) as “institutions that had secular functions and religious identities”. To the now enormous Catholic school system,15 and the network of diocesan newspapers, were added the “Jocist” youth movements, catering for secondary students (YCS), young workers (YCW) and tertiary students. They provided a wide variety of sporting and social activities, as well as a unique Christian formation system aimed at applying the teachings of the New Testament to the world of work.16 The movement is now virtually extinct, but sorely missed by the Church. One extraordinary development in this line was the formation of the “Democratic Labour Party”, a political party which had its roots in a movement of “Industrial Groups” designed to counter the influence of Communists in the trade unions and the Labor party. It received strong support from the Catholic hierarchy and laity, especially in the state of Victoria, and was successful in keeping the Labor Party out of federal government from 1954 until 1972 (Duncan 2001).17 12 Nobody personified the type better than Daniel Mannix of Melbourne; untypical in his learning and wit, he was nonetheless regarded by both the British and Australian governments as a dangerous radical because of his oratorical powers and his outspoken stand on the “Irish Question”. 13 After an early period of support for denominational schools, government aid was withdrawn over the twenty years after 1850, and partially subsidies were restored only in the nineteen fifties and sixties. “State Aid” now pays the salaries of the teaching workforce (formerly made up of religious order members, but now virtually entirely lay) but capital works are still funded by the sponsoring bodies. 14 See Lijphart (1975). 15 According to the to the Australian Bureau of Statistics, in 2000 Catholic schools catered for 19% of the Australian population of primary school age, and 21% of the corresponding secondary school agegroup. (ABS 2001). 16 The movement originated in Europe under the charismatic leadership of Josef (later Cardinal) Cardijn. 17 In Australia’s preferential voting system, votes of losing candidates are transferred to the voter’s next choice; the DLP urged its voters to give their second preference to the conservative “Liberal Party”. New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 19 --and living in Australia 19 This “pillarized” Catholic environment (to a much smaller extent, there existed also Anglican and Protestant counterparts, less necessary because Australian society was predominantly Protestant) formed a protective barrier impermeable to secularizing influences until right up to the Second Vatican Council, which coincided roughly with what Lechner, discussing secularization in the Dutch Catholic Church, calls the “cultural revolution” (1996: 259). The word ‘ghetto’ has sometimes been used of this Catholic subculture -- inappropriately, in our judgment, since it did not extend strongly to the world of daily work. In the economic sphere, Catholics “mixed in” – they were, after all, a quarter or more of the population, and by the nineteen forties, were fairly evenly distributed across social and occupational strata in proportion to their numbers, except at the top. The “pillarization” of the Dutch Catholic and Reformed churches Lechner (1989, 1996) describes was mirrored in Australia, more clearly in the Catholic case, until the early seventies. Since the religious situation was “closed” -- not “pluralistic” in the sense used by the “new paradigm” authors, “supply-side” theory would predict a low level of religious mobilization. On the contrary, the level of church attendance and other forms of participation was at an unprecendented high. And although the Australian Catholic Church was almost the opposite of the Dutch Church (far from being a center of Catholic intellectual life prior to the Vatican Council, it was an anti-intellectual backwater, and the Council took its bishops entirely by surprise), when the pillars collapsed in the mid-seventies, exposing Catholics to the religious “market” for the first time, attendance, as in Holland, began to decline and continued to do so until the present – an estimated 75% decline over forty years.18 Again, what occurred was the exact opposite of what “new paradigm” theory would lead us to expect. The similarity of the process in both countries underlines Lechner’s point (1996: 259) that: “the Church was dealing with forces beyond its control”. All the more clearly, in that while the Dutch Church became a world leader in attempting to adapt to the changes taking place in its environment, Lechner’s phrase “stuck in a pre-pluralistic rut” fits the Australian church quite well. It certainly could not be accused of voluntarily abandoning its former “strictness”. But the outcome was the same in both cases. Since “strictness” is on both sides of the equation, it drops out as a relevant explanatory factor. The case made by Bruce and Lechner for the inadequacy of supply-side theory is reinforced by this example. They emphasise the “embeddedness” of “markets” in cultures; the impact of “demand-side” factors on the assumed “relatively stable (potential) demand”; and the need for an acute verstehende appreciation of the perceptions of actors which shape demand – in other words, a fairly standard “oldparadigm” social-structural approach. As Lechner writes: “The critical question, of course, is how such perceptions are formed and changed. On this score, we have precious little formal theory of the kind Stark and Iannacone advocate.”(1996: 261). Continuing our discussion of how secularization theory should be supplemented, we will attempt to gather a few more theoretical components by considering next the dimensions of pluralism. b) The multiple dimensions of pluralism In attributing secularization to “modernization”, secularization theory has often failed to specify with sufficient precision which components of the complex and many-faceted process of modernization tend to have secularizing effects, and how they operate. One approach (Berger 1979: chapter 1) shows how new technologies of industrial production introduce a new complexity into the division of labour, 18 More detailed statistics on the changes are provided in the final section of the paper. New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 20 --and living in Australia 20 pluralizing institutions, leading to social differentiation and institutional specialization. Religious institutions are not exempt; religion becomes one specialised domain among others; the relevance of its conceptions and the power of its functionaries are now confined to one institutional sphere. Corresponding to the pluralization of institutions, there occurs a pluralization of plausibility structures; on the level of individual consciousness, a plurality of worldviews becomes available. The modernizing process favours the development of democratic societies with a free market for goods, but also for ideas as well. The Enlightenment Deists who framed the constitutions of modern states (including particularly those of the USA and Australia) enshrined in them the disestablishment of religion and legal support for tolerance of the ‘free exercise’ of religion. Carlin (1997)19 shows how the status of being one denomination among others exerts a range of pressures towards “indifferentism”, which extends tolerance to the theological level, militating against ‘exclusivism’ – the claim that one’s own religion is uniquely true and salvific – (or, in modified form, that although other denominations, even other religions, have their meed of truth, one’s own is superior to the others – alone possessing the fullness of revealed truth and the means of salvation).20 Adherence to a specific tradition is pressed towards reshaping itself into allegiance to a kind of “Christianity in general”. These pressures operate particularly within former ‘church-type’ religious bodies, whose institutions have been shaped by long periods of virtual religious monopoly or establishment. Orthodoxy and Catholicism are perhaps the best examples. Although the ‘sect-type’ groups in their environment are both openly exclusivist and proselytise aggressively, the sectarian stance vis-à-vis the world or their own society is for these large and diverse groups against their deepest instincts and their centuries of experience. Confronted with a virtual (though never official) Protestant and hostile establishment, these former churches may take on for a time some sectarian characteristics, strongly maintain their exclusivist selfunderstanding and their boundaries; but their world-embracing tendencies are re-asserted as overt opposition to them fades. Then they face a new series of dilemmas. There can be no denying pluralism as a fact: other Christian denominations and other religions exist, are close at hand, and have their own following. The option is open for the believer to “alternate” to one of these, to seek to combine elements from several, or to abandon them all by adopting a stance of scepticism and religious indifference. How to respond? There is often no prospect that these former ‘churches’ will ever be able to resume the status of religious monopolies; but the opposite, sectarian path, is also blocked to them. Those whose poverty condemns them to social marginality make readier sectarians. They are less concerned with social acceptability or the niceties of intellectual and social ‘good manners’, less embarrassed by a faith that views other faiths as deficient, inferior, or perhaps even as demonic. Much of the following page is a restructured, rephrased version of Carlin’s argument. This remains the official Catholic position as formulated at the Second Vatican Council and reiterated since then in numerous papal documents. 19 20 New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 21 --and living in Australia 21 But the former ‘church-type’ groups, because the breadth of their membership encompasses not only the less affluent, but also many who are well-educated and well-positioned in society, are drawn to extend tolerance beyond what is legally required, towards, first, “intellectual tolerance”. Perhaps there is no trait so characteristic of the Enlightenment ideal of Reason as this “openmindedness”. The demand for it is absolute (especially in academic life), infractions invite strong moral condemnation, and the only ideas to which it need not, indeed must not, be extended are those considered conservative and thus, of course, intolerant. A religiously pluralistic social environment grounds the impulse for intellectual tolerance to be extended into “social tolerance,” a requirement as fundamental as good manners (in Australia, one often hears the adage “No religion or politics!” stated as a ground-rule for a pleasant gathering). And from here, it is a surprisingly short step to pressures arising from within the group for “theological tolerance” – the renunciation of the group’s uniqueness / exclusivism. The claim of exclusive or privileged access to religious truth for one’s own denomination appears hubristic and embarrassing to a significant proportion of the membership, especially to the more cosmopolitan, the liberal intellectuals, the socially and economically upwardly-mobile. These usually include at least a proportion of the clergy, bishops etc. Often, such a stance is theologically legitimated as ‘ecumenical’ -- a demand of faith itself, showing respect for common origins and shared basic beliefs. But what presented itself so benignly as the abandonment of excessive claims now begins to show its teeth. “Christianity in general” is not a living faith with its own tradition and body of adherents, but a set of vague generalizations unviable as a religion. The traditions that engage a response of religious faith are irreducibly particular. On each cardinal issue of belief, each tradition has its own approach. But these approaches are often quite different, even contradictory; once one abandons the minimum of exclusivism implied in every particular tradition, there is no universally valid “reason” supporting the maintenance of a belief or moral standard. “Unanswerable questions” emerge as the denomination’s belief and moral system, its internal coherence lost, begins to unravel and disintegrate. I recall a loyal Catholic, long divorced, musing, with reference to remarriage: “If it’s all right for him [a non-Catholic colleague], why isn’t it all right for me?”. There is no longer any clear reason for imposing on oneself any moral demands more stringent than those of the most liberal tradition. It is insufficiently realised that two kinds of knowledge are in conflict here: the ‘synthetic’, ‘heartknowledge’, possessed in embracing a religious faith, pre-rational but holistic; and the partial, discursively rational ‘knowledge-about’ one’s faith. The tension between the two makes for the most agonising personal dilemmas. The more tolerantly one appreciates the religious views of others, the more out of place comes to seem a partisan enthusiasm for those of one’s own group; tolerance is extended naturally from the contrary doctrines of other faiths (provided they are not conservative) to expressions of unorthodox versions of one’s own faith, and eventually also to outright secularist and anti-religious thought: the liberal comes to feel that all are allies in the good fight – the crusade -- against the hateful bigotry and narrowness characteristic of the ‘fundamentalist’ – the sectarian ‘true believer’. This category is now broadened to New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 22 --and living in Australia include less-liberal members of one’s own denomination, especially those who wish to maintain its exclusive claims. 22 Since religious zeal, and with it, all forms of proselytism now appear at best vulgar, or at worst seriously offensive as invasions of the other’s privacy, or oppression of the other in an attempt to impose one’s view of the world (with what right? with what proof of its superiority? how breath-takingly arrogant!), groups which have reached this stage do not strongly socialise even the children of their own members. The sectarians, on the other hand, are restrained by no such scruples, and do all they can to recruit the younger generation of liberal-religious families. They have a measure of success, especially among those who for some reason experience a sense of religious deprivation, but in today’s Australia, greater success seems to go to the ‘Enlightenment fundamentalists’ whose tactics are often as anti-intellectual as those of their enemies, and who have only to reinforce the apathy and scepticism already endemic among youth. In summary, clarifying the components of modernization which tend to secularize, we can distinguish a number of dimensions of “pluralism”: -the “pluralism” of the “backslider”: no matter what post-primitive society or era one chooses as the benchmark of religiosity, it is extremely unlikely that it lacked a sprinkling of “dissenters”, “sceptics” and less-enthusiastic participants or “backsliders”.21 The possibility already constitutes at least a minimal pluralism – an alternative to consuming the one product available; -a much stronger variant emerges when religions encounter each other at close hand – the prophets of ancient Israel were acutely aware of the appeal of the hilltop shrines, home to the cults of the local fertility deities; -even when post-Reformation Europe was ruled by the principle of cuius regio, eius religio, believers of whatever stripe could not but be aware that the claims of their own churches were challenged by sharply alternative paths within Christianity itself; one’s religious convictions required a defense; -the classic denominational “free market” found its fullest expression in nineteenth and early twentieth century America, but existed, from the very foundation of the USA, under the shadow of the more radical alternatives generated by the Enlightenment: deism, scepticism, secularism; -in the second half of the twentieth century it was these “religious options” which came to predominate in England and on the Continent. This is increasingly the case in Australia; others have suggested that Canada and even the U.S. have not been immune to these influences. In today’s Australia, to confess and practice “no religion” is an open choice free from social stigma, and seems to be increasingly the option taken by youth. Pluralism of this latter variety goes beyond the assumptions of supply-side theory; but secularization theory needs to incorporate all these dimensions of pluralism. There is, however, one dimension of the Australian religious situation to which supply-side theory could be argued to apply: the steady growth of the Pentecostal and Mormon groups over the last fifteen to twenty years, during which time mainstream Protestant groups have declined. As is well known, both show numerous traits of “strictness” in contrast with mainline Protestants; both have thrived in the more open market brought about by the collapse of the Catholic and Anglican pillars; they are competing successfully with other denominations to gain a share of the remaining demand (although rather than 21 Ladurie (1978) has documented this memorably for fourteenth-century France. New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 23 --and living in Australia 23 stable, this is limited and diminishing). According to the Church Life Surveys, although they recruit some unchurched people, most of those who join have formerly been members of other denominations – mostly Protestant. Together, the two groups account for 1.3% of the population. On the other hand, they do not significantly restrain the drift away from the denominations to “No Religion”. This road carries the heaviest traffic, and is virtually one-way. New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 24 --and living in Australia 24 c) A less biased understanding of Rationality Perhaps the most decisive of all the weaknesses of sociological theories of religion and of secularization is their lack of a way of dealing with religious “insights” which are not discursively rational, yet are taken seriously as knowledge, rather than mere affect.22 It does not lie within the purview of any empirical discipline to establish its own first principles. All such disciplines depend for this grounding upon mathematics and philosophy. But, at least in areas where the interpretation of findings raises questions which go beyond the empirical realm, it is incumbent on the social scientist to make his or her philosophical presuppositions explicit. 23 Empirical research on religion raises a fundamental issue of epistemology: does religious faith involve a mode of knowing other than discursive rational “knowledge-about”? A negative answer may not be simply assumed, even if that is the Enlightenment consensus. It requires a convincing refutation of the contrary arguments, which have developed considerably in recent centuries, that a non-discursive mode of knowledge is at the heart of religious commitment. Sociological studies of religion are not justified in assuming an unreflectively positivist stance which does not even make explicit their epistemological presuppositions, let alone state or cite the philosophical arguments supporting them. Notable exceptions, in their work on religion, are William James ([1902], 1973), Clifford Geertz (1973), Robert Bellah (1970), and particularly Andrew Greeley (1974, 1981, 1986).24 The lack, in secularization theory, of a way of dealing with non-discursive religious “insights”, as a genuine form of knowledge is primarily a philosophical problem, located in the realm of epistemology; hence its solution is not within the scope of the empirical social science of sociology; however it may not for that reason be passed over. It is commonplace for the requirements of explanation in social science to depend on philosophy, and even to provoke developments in that discipline by discovery of a social scientific problem which at the same time implies a philosophical problem. A highly sophisticated solution to the problem was developed in the High Mediaeval period – in the work of Aquinas and his commentator, John of St. Thomas. This sphere of learning is a closed book to most post-Enlightenment scholars, and one deemed not worth the considerable trouble of scanning – difficult because the originals are in Latin, and couched within a framework so intellectually elaborate that years of study are required even to access it. The mediaeval approach is retrieved in the work of French philosopher Jacques Maritain, and utilised by Andrew Greeley (1981). 22 See below. It is to the credit of Berger and Luckmann that they lay out the presuppositions underlying their sociology in The Social Construction of Reality (1967), showing how their work is founded on Alfred Schutz’s social phenomenology. 24 We repeat with approval maxims such as ‘religion is caught, not taught’; we have abundant evidence, from research interviews, of outcomes of religious experience that combine insight and ineffability; we have to hand at least minimal philosophical tools such as Husserl’s account of ‘appresentation’ and Schutz’s theory of symbols, yet so intimidating is the dominance, especially in English-speaking academia, of primitive Enlightenment theories of knowledge such as the Cartesian formula of ‘clear and distinct ideas’, or the even thinner rationality of later positivism, that very few seem able even to follow William James or Schleiermacher in accepting the notion of a religious mode of ‘knowing’ which does not fit within these parameters. 23 New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 25 --and living in Australia 25 Schleiermacher makes cognitive claims for the experience of the gefühl of ultimate dependence; but many later commentators have persistently misdefined it as cognitively content-less “feeling”. A more recent philosopher (incidentally one not much interested in religion, but fascinated by the philosophy of science), Michael Polanyi, independently arrived, in the course of dealing with problems in scientific understanding, at virtually the same crucial insight as Aquinas and Schleiermacher into prediscursive, non-conceptual knowledge, and has laid out the conceptual tools for dealing with a closely similar type of knowledge in religion. The potential remains largely unexploited to this day, partly because Polanyi stands alone also as a philosopher with no obvious major successor(s).25 A successful application of his concept of “tacit knowledge” to religion would have the advantage of correcting the “cognitive bias” in most scholarly accounts of religion and of secularization26. The Enlightenment model of rationality, of which modernization is the carrier, seems the best candidate for the most potent of the secularizing components within the process – all the more so since right up until the present time, there is no well-understood epistemological legitimation for what the believer “knows” but cannot articulate discursively. Michael Paul Gallagher (1990) argues persuasively that the “trickle-down” effect into popular consciousness of the theories of the “masters of suspicion” (especially Marx, Nietzsche, Darwin and Freud) is a powerful influence in the erosion of faith. Enlightenment rationality assumes that only discursive reason gives rise to valid knowledge. Since religious “knowledge” is not verifiable by discursive reason, it is rejected as “myth”, falsehood. Although philosophers debate the topic explicitly, the impact on the popular mind seems to stem more from the social and physical sciences. Whatever their personal views, few scientists follow Richard Dawkins in propounding a full-blown “scientism” – the claim that scientific knowledge comprehensively disproves religion, and provides an adequate worldview. Yet, despite spectacular failures, science “works” in a limited fashion, most impressively, perhaps, to generate technologies accessible to consumers; and in doing so, confers enormous prestige on its form of knowledge. The popular perception seems to be that the ‘success’ of science vindicates the claims made in its name against religion. Enlightenment rationality is inherently secularizing when thus embodied in scientism: short of maintaining one’s faith and one’s understanding of science in separate watertight compartments (which is no doubt a common strategy), it is impossible for those not equipped with a contemporary epistemology to avoid severe cognitive dissonance when the religious perspective and this “popular scientism” are brought into confrontation. There is no middle point between two directly contradictory propositions. To choose one is to reject the other. “Rationality” as understood within rational choice theory is even more limited in scope than its parent. It is presented as a “cost-effectiveness” calculation of benefits to the self. This owes more to economics than to anything one would associate with the “choice” of faith. 25 An attempt to utilise elements of his thought to deal with the problem of religious knowing is the theme of an article in preparation. 26 A recent study by Moleski (2002) compares Polanyi’s “personal knowledge” with Newman’s “illative sense”. New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 26 --and living in Australia 26 Weber’s discussion of rationality, although often criticised as confused and confusing, has been influential on subsequent theorists. He defines Zweckrationalität, or “purposive rationality” as a meansends calculation: the ordering of action adapted to the achievement of a goal, or desired state of affairs. Even this ideal type of rational action is a good deal broader than the self-oriented calculation supposed to underlie “rational choice”. Somewhat awkwardly, Weber introduces Wertrationalität as a contrasting type of action, oriented to the realization of an end which is ultimate and unconditioned: an “absolute value”. Lacking a place in his system for the “non-rational” which is not irrational, (or what Pareto called the “non-logical” as opposed to the illogical), Weber is soon forced into describing the ultimacy component as irrational (whatever has the character of ultimacy transcends purposive rationality since, without a processus ad infinitum it is not possible to continue indefinitely the rational ordering of means to ever more superordinate ends).27 Yet it does not seem too far-fetched to see in this concept of Weber’s an attempt to combine both the knowledge characteristic of rationality and the pre-rational intuitive insight most characteristic of the experience of one who embraces a religious faith. d) Other limitations of secularization theory Weber confessed that he himself was “religiously unmusical”. He may have been too modest. Some of the participants in the debate over secularization certainly appear to be religio-musically challenged. One need not agree with Joachim Wach that a scholar whose field of interest is religion must be a religious believer. An adjudicator at a choral eisteddfod need not herself be a singer; but to be tone-deaf, or cursed with a visceral dislike of music, would surely constitute a significant impediment to the fulfilment of her professional task. The work of a few participants in the secularization debate still evinces old-fashioned secularist bias, while lack of theological or historical knowledge betrays others into parodies of the objects of their study.28 For an adequate theory of religion and secularization, a multidisciplinary approach is indispensable. It would find its most natural home in the “field” of History of Religions / Scientific Study of Religion / Religionswissenschaft, and should include: sociology, anthropology, psychology, philosophy (of religion, epistemology, philosophy of symbols, aesthetics), theology, history and phenomenology of religion. Obviously, to master all of these disciplines would require a polymath of Weberian proportions. But to be able at least to work across some part of the range seems required by the nature of the task of understanding religion, and hence also, of the task of an adequate theory of secularization. From this perspective, each of the present participants in the secularization debate could be likened to one who has assembled into a symmetrical pattern numerous pieces of a jigsaw of unknown total shape and size, and feels convinced that he has the whole puzzle assembled -- only to find, to his or her chagrin -- that although some others have some apparently identical pieces, each also has parts which do not fit into the patterns assembled by any of the others. Worse: the complete jigsaw is glimpsed to be several Parsons’s critique of Weber’s concept of rationality in his Introduction to Weber (1947). Bruce knows something of Protestant theology, but his slapdash summary of mediaeval Christianity (2000: 6) falls little short of a stock Protestant parody. Impeccably scholarly historical research has been done by Duffy (1992) on this period in England, and Bruce should have taken account of it. Similarly, the research of Ladurie (1978) provides a rich and nuanced account of religious dissent in fourteenth century Europe which should have informed Bruce’s discussion of religion’s alleged “Golden Age”. 27 28 New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 27 --and living in Australia times larger than the aggregate of all the pieces at present in the players’ possession. 29 27 The difficulties listed above can be distinguished into those that imply significant gaps in the theory which must be filled before it can perform its explanatory task, and those which are merely hindrances to the debate. The first three items identify deficits in the theory as it stands at present, which must be remedied if it is to develop further, and eventually serve its explanatory and hypothesis-generating functions. The fourth is merely a hindrance, yet intractable enough, and will only be overcome over a long time period, if at all. Yamane (1997) has proposed “neo-secularization theory”, as a perspective for unifying the variety of approaches to secularization which have appeared in recent years, each presented by its proponents as comprehensive, and in conflict with the others. From the perspective of this review, his proposal makes sense. D. Australia as a ‘middle case’ of secularization: indicators Throughout this paper we have referred to Australia as a case which should be of special interest to secularization theorists, since it stands between what some consider the extremes of England and the U.S.A. David Martin (1978) long ago proposed that England and its former colonies could be arranged on a continuum which showed the level of secularization (indicated by the national level of church attendance) decreasing in harmony with the decreasing degree of establishment of religion, thus: England English-speaking Canada Australia USA In the interim, Australia has moved closer to England in terms of level of active involvement in religion; or alternatively, it could be argued that the “distance” separating all three has decreased, with the US, Canada and Australia all moving to decrease the gap separating them from England and similar European countries. The alternative chosen depends on the conclusion one draws from the contradictory claims emerging from the last decade of research on the level of regular church attendance and other forms of active involvement in the US. Political scientist Robert Putnam reviews the extensive research on this issue in his discussion of social capital in the U.S.A., and concludes that: First, religion is today, as it has traditionally been, a central fount of American community life and health. . . . Second, the broad oscillations in religious participation during the twentieth century mirror trends in secular civic life -- flowering during the first six decades of the century and especially in the two decades after World War II, but then fading over the last three or four decades. . . . For the most part younger generations (“younger” here includes the boomers) are less involved both in religious and secular social activities than were their 29 I do not wish to imply that the entire picture could be accommodated only in the divine mind! Whatever else they may be, religions are human enterprises, and in principle as accessible to human comprehension as is humanity itself. Yet in practice, our rational understanding of humanity is far from comprehensive, and some aspects of it may always elude rational inquiry. New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 28 --and living in Australia 28 predecessors at the same age. . . .In short, as the twenty-first century opens, Americans are going to church less often than we did three of four decades ago, and the churches we go to are less involved with the local community (Putnam, 2000: 79). The second of Putnam’s conclusions fits the Australian situation admirably. The ‘fading’ of religious participation in Australia is shown in the following indicators from recent research. 1) Religious identification: The Australian Population Census30 (See Appendix, Table 1, Australia, Religion, Selected Censuses 1961-2001.) The quinquennial census of population and housing conducted by the Australian Government through the Australian Bureau of Statistics contains a measure of “religious identification”: “What is this person’s religion?”. From the 2001 census, it emerges that: -The population of Australia has increased over the period from 10.5 million in 1961 to 18.7 million in 2001, mainly by immigration, and natural increase among immigrants.31 -Total Christian has declined from 88% of the population in 1961 to 68% in 2001. -The mainstream Anglican and Protestant groups have declined most –e.g. Anglican from 35% to 21%; MPRCU32 from 20% to 10% (1961 – 2001). -The percentage of Catholics has fluctuated around 27% over the period, implying net numerical growth at the same rate as the population. This stable percentage, however, also serves to mask considerable decline in each of the recent censuses in the number who identify as Catholic. Counting the number of individuals in a 5-year age cohort (e.g. 25-29) at one census, and comparing that number with the size of the cohort 5 years older (30-34) at the next census, reveals a noticeable decline. The only possible causes of such a reduction in the size of the cohort between censuses are death, emigration or ceasing to identify as Catholic. Neither of the first two causes could account for more than a small fraction of the observed decline. These declines in identification are occurring mainly among those aged between 20 and 45. The fact that the Catholic percentage of the population remains stable indicates that the growth (by birth and immigration) in the number of at least nominal Catholics must be large enough to mask the “dis-identification” of a proportion of those in the age cohort 20-45. -Protestant sects show high levels of growth, led by Pentecostals and Mormons, both of which have grown by more than 10% since the 1996 Census; but the numbers remain small (Pentecostals have just reached 1% of the population), and the rate of “switching” is high. 30 Every five years, most recently 2001, conducted by the Australian Bureau of Statistics. The questionnaire contains an optional, but well-answered question which now reads: “What is this person’s religion?”. “Tick boxes” are provided for the eight most frequent answers; other responses are written-in and scanned. In former censuses the question read: “What is this person’s religious denomination?”. The introduction of the “tick boxes” in 1996 caused a perturbation in the long-term trends in the data; significantly more people chose to answer the question, especially in the case of the 8 groups named beside the boxes. 31 The birthrate among the Australian-born has been below replacement level over the whole period. 32 The mainline Protestant denominations are harder to track, because of the formation in 1977 of the Uniting Church of Australia, comprising all Methodists, nearly all Congregationalists, and about twothirds of Presbyterians. The artificial amalgam MPRCU (Methodist, Presbyterian, Reformed, Congregational, and Uniting) has been constructed to enable comparisons over time. New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 29 --and living in Australia 29 -“Other religions” has increased from .7% in 1961 to 4.9% in 2001, because of increased immigration, later in the period, from Asia. Buddhism, Hinduism and Islam show very high growth rates. -But “New Age” groups and movements, elaborately classified by ABS in consultation with local experts prior to the 1996 Census, show small numbers (less than 100,000). However this probably underestimates their significance, which may lie more in the formation of syncretistic blends with traditional faiths, rather than in attracting dedicated “adherents” for whom they constitute an entire worldview. -“No religion” has increased from .4% in 1961 to 15.5% in 2001. In 1971, an instruction was placed beside the question “If no religion, write: ‘None’”, causing a large decline in “Not stated”, and a large increase in “No Religion”. It seems likely (from surveys in which “Not stated” is not provided as a response option) that the majority of those who do not state a religion in the Census (9.8% of the population) would otherwise choose “No religion”, so the 15.5% for this category in the 2001 Census should probably be augmented to something over 20% in reality, making this group one of the largest, and the fastest-growing. Surveys show that while there is a great deal of “switching” among Protestant denominations, there is steady traffic from the mainstream denominations towards “No Religion”, and that nearly all of it is one-way. It is uncommon for individuals to move from “No religion” to either a mainstream denomination or a sect; Pentecostal growth has been shown to consist mainly of former members of other Christian churches (especially Protestant), rather than coming from the ranks of the “unchurched”. 2) Church attendance Mol quotes a 1960 Morgan Gallup Poll figure of 30% of Australians attending a church service in the last 7 days (1985: 56). His own survey found the same percentage in 1966 (1985: 58), and an additional 12% who attended 1-3 times per month. In 1998, 13% of the population attended church services weekly, and an additional 7% attended 1-3 times per month.33 The decline in weekly attendance over the 40-year period is 57%, in attendance monthly or more often, 52% . The 1960 poll mentioned above found Catholic weekly attendance to be 60%. An attendance count of Catholics was conducted in all dioceses in 2001, resulting in a rate of 15%, showing a 75% decline over the last 40 years.34 There has been only a small increase in the number who attend 1-3 times per month instead of weekly. The decline has added significance in the light of the maintenance, in Catholic teaching, of the obligation to weekly attendance. 3)Decline in religious beliefs and moral attitudes The first major survey of religion in Australia embracing almost the whole population took place in 1969 (Mol 1971); the most recent was the Australian Community Survey in 1998 (Bellamy et al 2002). A few questions are directly comparable, and illustrate the changes over the period. 1969 1998 Believe in a personal God 76% 35% Believe in a force or power35 12% 39% 33 1998 figures from Alan Black, Philip Hughes and Peter Kaldor, Australian Community Survey, cited in Bellamy et al.2002, p.8. 34 The 1960 percentages should probably be discounted by some fraction to allow for the well-known finding that replies to church attendance questions in polls or surveys are always higher than the results of head-counts. It would follow that the percentage declines would also be smaller. 35 Mol 1971, p. 44 and Bellamy et al 2002, p. 48. New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 30 --and living in Australia 30 (not in a personal God) Disapprove of premarital sex 63% 17% Denomination (if any) of marriage ceremony is recorded; in 2000, the number of marriages at which secular “civil celebrants” officiated was for the first time greater than the number celebrated by ministers of religion. Conclusion Public religions in the modern world Casanova (1996) argues that “public religions in the modern world” are playing a continuing role through their advocacy of public policies more consistent with their view of human values. His discussion appears to discount the impact on this role of decreasing levels of religious belief, and dwindling numbers of regular attenders. But this would also be consistent with the argument that any credibility the churches possess in the sphere of public policy, and any hearing they gain in public debates for their positions in on these issues, is due nowadays not to acceptance of their religious authority, or their role as moral arbiters, but to the major contributions they have made, over a very long period, in the fields of education, health and social welfare. But the secularizing developments we have described in Australia, which appear to be verified elsewhere as well, although they are slow to impact on the numbers of nominal adherents who, while not ‘practising’, continue to identify with a particular religion, undermine the credibility, acceptability and political weight of the public advocacy role of the churches, and threaten the demise of church structures (at least in the health and welfare fields) which in the past enabled the massive church endeavours in these fields. The “plausibility structures” (social structures of communal life which support the worldviews and values of religious organizations) are becoming visibly weaker, the “constituency” for which church leaders may be presumed to speak is becoming much smaller, and the financial contributions of active participants are increasingly insufficient to maintain Church charitable works at anything remotely resembling their former levels. There seems little reason to believe that the publicly expressed views of the leaders of a church reduced to an organizational shell would continue to command a hearing in public debates on social policy. New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 31 --and living in Australia 31 References Australian Bureau of Statistics. 2001. Schools, 2000. Canberra: ABS. Casanova, José. 1996. Public Religions in the Modern World. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Bellah, Robert. 1970. “Religious evolution” in Beyond Belief. New York: Harper and Row. Bellamy, John, Alan Black, Keith Castle, Philip Hughes and Peter Kaldor. 2002. Why People Don’t Go To Church. Adelaide: Openbook and NCLS Research. Berger, Peter L. 1969. The Sacred Canopy. New York: Doubleday Anchor. ____. 1970. ‘On the obsolescence of the concept of honor’. European Journal of Sociology XI, 339-347. ____. 1979. The Heretical Imperative: Contemporary Possibilities of Religious Affirmation. New York: Doubleday Anchor. ____. 1980. “From secularity to world religions.” The Christian Century 97, 4-8. ____. (ed.) 1999 The Desecularization of the World. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans. ____. 2001 ‘Postscript’ in Linda Woodhead (ed.) Peter Berger and the Study of Religion. London: Routledge, 189-198. Berger, Peter L., and Thomas Luckmann. 1967. The Social construction of reality: a treatise in the sociology of knowledge. New York: Doubleday Anchor. Bruce, Steve. 1990. A House Divided: Protestantism, Schism and Secularization. London: Routledge. ____. (ed.) 1992. Religion and Modernization: Sociologists and Historians Debate the Secularization Thesis. Oxford: Clarendon Press. ____. 1996. Religion in the Modern World. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ____. 1999. Choice and Religion: A Critique of Rational Choice Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ____. 2001. “The curious case of the unnecessary recantation: Berger and secularization.” In Linda Woodhead (ed.) Peter Berger and the Study of Religion. London: Routledge, 87-100. ____. 2002. The Death of God: Secularization in the West. Oxford: Blackwell. Carlin, David R. 1997. “The denomination called Catholic.” First Things November, pp. 18-21. Chadwick, Owen. 1975. The Secularization of the European Mind in the Nineteenth Century. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Dillenberger, John and Welch, Claude. 1954. Protestant Christianity. New York: Scribner. Duffy, Eamon. 1992. The Stripping of the Altars: Traditional Religion in England c.1400 – c.1580. London: Yale University Press. Duncan, Bruce. 2001. Crusade or Conspiracy? Catholics and the Anti-Communist Struggle in Australia. Sydney: University of New South Wales Press. Eisenstadt, S. N. 2000. “Multiple modernities” Daedalus 129/1 (Winter). Gallagher, Michael Paul. 1990. Struggles of faith: essays. Dublin: Columba Press. Geertz, Clifford. 1973. The Interpretation of Cultures. New York: Basic. Greeley, Andrew M. 1974. Ecstasy: A Way of Knowing. Englewood Cliffs NJ: Prentice-Hall. ____. 1981. Religion--A Secular Theory. New York: Free Press. ____. 1996. Religion as Poetry. London: Transaction Press. Hally, Cyril. 1975. A Survey of the Religious Attitudes of the People of the Diocese of Ballarat. Ballarat, Vic.: Diocese of Ballarat. Hewitt, Paul. 1978. Catholics Divided Brisbane: Archdiocese of Brisbane. Ireland, Rowan. 1988. The Challenge of Secularization. Melbourne: Collins Dove. James, William. [1902]1973. The Varieties of Religious Experience: A Study in Human Nature. New York: Macmillan. Ladurie, Le Roy Emmanuel. 1978. Montaillou: Cathars and Catholics in a French Village, 1294-1324. Scholar’s Press. New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 32 --and living in Australia 32 Lechner, Frank J. 1989. “Catholicism and social change in the Netherlands: a case of radical secularization?” Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion 28:136-47. ____. 1996. “Secularization in the Netherlands?” Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion 35/3 (September): 252-265. Lijphart, A. 1975. The politics of accommodation: pluralism and democracy in the Netherlands. Berkeley: University of California Press. Luckmann, Thomas. 1967. The Invisible Religion: the Transformation of Symbols in Industrial Society. London: Collier Macmillan. ____. 1977. “Theories of religion and social change.” Annual Review of the Social Sciences of Religion I. ____. 1990. “Shrinking transcendence, expanding religion?” Sociological Analysis 50/2 (Summer), 139152. McLeod, Hugh. 2000. Secularization in Western Europe 1848-1914. New York: St. Martin’s Press. Martin, David. 1978. A General Theory of Secularization. Oxford: Blackwell. ____. 1990. Tongues of Fire: the Explosion of Protestantism in Latin America. Oxford: Blackwell. ____. 2002. Pentecostalism: The World Their Parish. Oxford: Blackwell. Mol, Hans. 1971. Religion in Australia. Melbourne: Nelson. ____. 1985. The Faith of Australians. Sydney: Allen and Unwin. Moleski, Martin. 2002. Personal Catholicism. Putnam, Robert. 2000. Bowling Alone. New York: Simon and Schuster. Stark, Rodney. 1999. “Secularization, R.I.P.” Sociology of Religion, (Fall), 249-273. Stark, Rodney, and Finke, Roger. 2000. Acts of Faith: Explaining the Human Side of Religion. London and Berkeley: University of California Press. Voas, David, Daniel V. A. Olson and Alasdair Crockett. 2002. eligious pluralism and participation: why previous research is wrong.” American Sociological Review 67/2 (April): 212-230. Weber, Max. 1947. Theory of Social and Economic Organization. New York: Free Press. Wilson, Bryan. 1966. Religion in Secular Society. London: Watts. ____. 1982. Religion in Sociological Perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press. New Turns in the Secularization Debate M. Mason 33 --and living in Australia 33 Table 2: Responses from Catholic laity to questions on clergy sexual abuse in the Church Life Surveys of 1996 and 2001 Full text of questions: 1996 The cases of sexual abuse by priests and religious have seriously damaged my confidence in the Church. Strongly agree / Agree / Unsure / Disagree /Strongly disagree 2001 The cases of sexual abuse by priests have seriously damaged my confidence in Church authorities. Strongly agree / Tend to agree / Tend to disagree / Strongly disagree 1996 The response of church authorities to these incidents has been inadequate and shows a complete failure of responsibility. 2001 Despite procedures that have been set up, the response of Church authorities to clergy sexual abuse is still inadequate: reluctant and legalistic in acknowledging claims; over-emphasising ‘damage-control’ and insufficiently concerned for victims; minimising offenses and leaving offenders in their positions. 1996 My respect for priests and religious has greatly declined as a result of these offences. 2001 My confidence in priests in general has not decreased, even though some have committed offenses. Analysis There was considerable change in the pattern of responses of over the five year interval, mainly because the proportion who were formerly undecided now express a view. Caveat: partly this is because the questions in 2001 did not offer the option “Unsure”; if the respondent could not choose to agree or disagree, his only option was not to answer. In the following tables, Strongly agree / Agree and Strongly Disagree / Disagree have been combined. Table 1: All respondents Australia-wide PRIEST SEX ABUSE HAS DAMAGED MY CONFIDENCE IN CHURCH (AUTHORITIES) Agree Unsure/No answer Disagree 1996 37% 27% 36% 2001 48% 17% 35% THE CHURCH’S RESPONSE TO SEX ABUSE BY CLERGY HAS BEEN INADEQUATE Agree Unsure/No answer Disagree 1996 45% 37% 19% 2001 56% 26% 18% I HAVE LESS RESPECT FOR PRIESTS IN GENERAL BECAUSE OF ABUSE CASES Agree Unsure/No answer Disagree 1996 17% 32% 52% 2001 14% 22% 64% Appendix. Table 1. Religion, Australia. Selected censuses 1961-2001