Handout

advertisement
Phenomenology and Foucault
Prof. Boedeker
Being and Time, Sections 2-6
Running commentary to
Note on the text: Heidegger’s own footnotes to Being and Time are placed, inconveniently
enough, as endnotes, beginning on p. 399. Make sure you read them, since they are sometimes
quite informative. From time to time, he would write down notes in his own copy of the book.
These are given as footnotes in the text. These are also often quite interesting, especially when
they show his own self-criticisms.
Section 2:
beings: entities, including physical objects, human beings, other animals, plants, and numbers.
being: the being (Sein) of a being (Seiendes) is the way in which that being (Seiendes) is
encountered by someone. In Husserl’s terms, the being of a being is the category of the intended
as such. There are many different ways for entities to “be”. Heidegger later confessed that his
term “being” was misleading. He is interested not in being (which really means something like
reality), but rather in the basic ways in which things are encountered, show up, or become
present. He suggests the term “presence” (Answesen) as a perhaps less misleading way of
putting this theme: intentionality in the broadest possible sense, including one’s relations to
oneself.
For someone to understand a way of being is for her to be able to encounter entities in that way
of being.
Shortly after the publication of Being and Time, Heidegger coined the phrase “ontological
difference” to express the fact that being is not a being. The being of beings is neither a
physical, a mental, nor a universal entity.
Being as such is the totality of ways of being of beings, taken in their distinctness and
interrelatedness. That is, being as such is a sort of unity that is articulated into the various ways
of being of beings.
The official goal of Being and Time is to raise and answer the question of the sense (Sinn) of
being as such. Thus Heidegger characterizes his project as ontology: the study of being as being.
The translator renders Heidegger’s term Sinn not as “sense”, but as “meaning”. This is very
unfortunate, since by “sense”, Heidegger means direction of a motion, not meaning. The sense
of being is not the meaning of the word “being”, but the direction of the motion of human
temporality that makes it possible to understand the being of beings.
In order to ask and answer the question of being, Heidegger proposes to “interrogate” the being
that understands being. He does this because we human beings are the ones who understand
being as such – both our own, that of other people, and that of intraworldly entities (such as
tables, chairs, pizzas, and electrons). Heidegger calls us human beings “Da-sein”. This is the
ordinary German word for “existence”, and literally means “being-there”.
Reaching the goal of the question of being – i.e., ascertaining the sense of being as such –
involves making explicit our usually implicit understanding of being. (After all, we normally
focus on beings, not their ways of being.) His picture is that Da-sein is the being to which an
understanding of being as such belongs. Thus, he hopes, explicating Da-sein’s being (and its
sense) will be a good first step in explicating being as such (as its sense). To anticipate things a
lot, Heidegger (in a lecture-course delivered right after the publication of Being and Time) ends
33
up defining the sense of being as such as Dasein’s temporality in so far as this temporality makes
possible Dasein’s understanding of being.
Section 3:
Each science is determined by the domain of objects it studies. The most basic concepts of a
science are those that delimit its object-domain. These basic concepts are concepts of what it is
to be an object of the science in question. Basic concepts are thus ontological concepts. Since
Heidegger takes philosophy to be the science of being, i.e., ontology, he regards the choice of
basic concepts as a genuinely philosophical matter.
Ontological concepts are not directly observable, but rather must always already be involved in
conducting observations. For example, a biologist must have some – perhaps implicit –
understanding of life in order to be able to conduct biological experiments on living things. Or a
physicist must have some understanding of the being of physical objects in order to begin to
formulate physical theories or perform physical experiments or observations. Because basic
concepts are presupposed by everyday scientific research, they are a priori (literally: “from
before experience”) – but still revisable in the light of new evidence.
A science encounters a “crisis” when it becomes clear that its basic concepts cannot do justice to
its object-domain: that they obscure the objects of the science. What are called “scientific
revolutions”, or “paradigm shifts”, take place as a response to such crises. They consist in part in
the development of new basic concepts, more appropriate to the object-domain. As Heidegger
was writing Being and Time, many sciences were undergoing major crises and revolutions. He
mentions mathematics, physics, biology, history, and theology. Heidegger’s own ontological
investigations are closely related to the ontological questions raised in the scientific crises of the
day. In addition, he is proposing a revolution in the science of ontology itself.
Heidegger’s ontology is not limited to clarifying the basic concepts of the positive sciences. For
he is also interested in showing how the categories employed by the sciences have their
foundation in the way of being of human beings. In his 1929 book, Kant and the Problem of
Metaphysics, Heidegger calls the ontology of human beings a “philosophical anthropology.”
Unlike empirical anthropology, which is the positive science that investigates similarities and
differences among human communities, philosophical anthropology seeks to clarify what human
beings are. Heidegger’s claim is that human beings can understand the ways of being employed
in the positive sciences only because of our distinctive way of being. (Note that since Heidegger
is not attempting to reduce the validity of any scientific theory to something merely
anthropological, psychological, or biological, he is not guilty of any kind of relativism.)
Section 4:
One of the ways in which our (human) way of being is distinctive is that, unlike rocks, plants,
and probably many other animals, we have an understanding of our own way of being. This selfunderstanding, however, is normally not explicit, or ontological. Instead, it is implicit, or preontological.
Heidegger defines existence as the human way of being, i.e., the way of being of Dasein. Note
that existence is by definition different from reality, the way of being of physical objects as such.
An ontological feature of an entity is a feature that the entity must have in virtue of its way of
being. For example, Dasein’s ontological features include the facts that it inhabits some world,
has some relation to some human community, and is mortal. On the other hand, an ontic feature
of an entity is a feature than the entity may, but need not, have in virtue of its being. For
34
example, ontological features of Abraham Lincoln include his being able to relate to other people
as such, his ability to use tools, his pursuing human projects in his own life, his being mortal, etc.
And ontic features of Abraham Lincoln include the facts that he was a great orator, that he was
American, and that he died in 1865.
Since Dasein’s being is existence, Heidegger calls ontological features of Dasein existential, and
ontic features of Dasein existentiell. Ontological features of entities other than Dasein are
categories.
ontic
ontological
features of Dasein (=existence)
existentiell
existential
features of beings other than Dasein
(no special term)
categorial/categories
Heidegger calls the project of clarifying being as such fundamental ontology. Thus
fundamental ontology consists of the question “What is being as such?”, and what is found out,
or ascertained, in the questioning “The sense of being as such is the temporal sense of Dasein’s
being.” This is analogous to asking someone how to get to a particular destination, and then
finding out, or ascertaining, just which streets to take, etc.
Recall from Section 2 (p. 5) that Heidegger proposes to conduct (fundamental) ontology by
“interrogating” Dasein, the being that has a pre-ontological understanding of being as such.
Heidegger characterizes this ontological interrogation of Dasein as the existential analysis of
Dasein.
Section 5:
Here Heidegger lays out the whole project of fundamental ontology. It proceeds in three stages:
an analysis of Dasein’s being (= Division One, up through p. 211), an explication of Dasein’s
Being in terms of its temporality (= Division Two, through the end of the book), and an
explication of being as such (including the being of beings other than Dasein) in terms of
temporality. Note that he never finished it, since the book ends with Division Two.
It might be helpful in understanding Heidegger’s remarks on time here to see what he says in a
1928 lecture-course, The Metaphysical Foundations of Logic, about Husserl’s analysis of
internal time-consciousness:
For Husserl, “time remains also here still a flowing-away of the now, just-passed, and almost –
correlated with an entirely particular knowledge about them. With respect to all previous
interpretations, Husserl’s contribution is to have seen these structures for the first time, with the
help of the intentional structure. A glance at contemporary psychology or epistemology is
sufficient to appreciate what an essential step he has made here. Nevertheless, everything in
relation to the problem of time remains with the old, and this to such an extent that time is taken
as something immanent; it remains as something inner ‘within the subject’ (thus the title ‘internal
time-consciousness’). Husserl’s whole investigation is occasioned by the fact that he examines
the primary and originary consciousness of time in knowing about a mere sense-datum; the
whole investigation then moves thoroughly about the phenomenon of the running-off of a tone.”
(For comments on BT Section 6, see handout V A 2 b ii, handout p. 26)
35
Download