1 Teleosemantics and Indeterminacy David Papineau Department of Philosophy King's College London Strand London WC2R 2LS UK d.papineau@kcl.ac.uk 2 Teleosemantics and Indeterminacy I. Introduction The aim of this paper is to defend the teleological theory of representation against an objection by Jerry Fodor. I shall argue that previous attempts to answer this objection fail to recognize the importance of belief-desire structure for the teleological theory of representation. The central thesis of the teleological theory (I shall take "of mental representation" as read from now on) is that the representational contents of mental states can be explained in terms of the biological functions of those states. More specifically, this theory equates the contents of informational states (and in particular, therefore, of beliefs) with those conditions in which those states are biologically supposed to be present; and it equates the contents of affective states (and in particular, therefore, of desires) with the conditions which those states are biologically supposed to produce. (For versions of this theory, see Dennett [4, ch. 9], [6, ch. 8]; Fodor [7]; Millikan [12], [14]; Papineau [19], [20], [22]; McGinn [10, ch. 2].) Defenders of the teleological theory standardly cash out their references to biological purposes etiologically, in terms of past processes of natural selection. According to the etiological account of biological function, an item X has a biological purpose Y if and only if X is now present because previous versions of X were selected in virtue of doing Y. (Cf. Wright [30]; Millikan [14, ch. 1]CHECK; Neander [16], [17].) The paradigm case of such selection is inter-generational Darwinian selection of genetic traits. But many advocates of the teleological theory (though not Millikan) also take representational functions to derive from non-genetic selection of mental states during individual learning. II. Fodor's Objection The teleological theory developed in response to "indicator" theories of content (Dretske [6], Stampe [27]). Theories of this kind equate the contents of mental states with the conditions that those states covary with. The difficulty facing such theories is that not all co-variation seems to be representational (Fodor [7]). My temporal beliefs co-vary with the position of the hands on my watch, but represent something else, 3 namely, the local time, which will be different if my watch is faulty. The attraction of the teleological theory is that it seems to impose extra constraints on which kinds of covariation count as representational. It is not enough that a mental state actually co-vary with such-and-such a condition. The teleological theory requires in addition that the state is biologically supposed so to co-vary. Fodor [8, ch. 3] argues that this advantage is illusory. He considers the state that is produced in a frog's brain when its eye is stimulated by a nearby small black moving object. At first sight, says Fodor, it may seem as if the teleological theory will ascribe the content fly to this state, in line with pre-theoretical intuition. For the frog state has presumably been favoured by natural selection because of the advantageous consequences it produced on those occasions it was copresent with flies. However, continues Fodor, this isn't the only answer the teleological theory authorizes. For, given that most small black things in the frog's evolutionary history have been flies, isn't it equally true that the frog state has been selected because of the advantageous consequences it produced when co-present with small black things? So this seems to imply that the teleological theory should ascribe the content small black thing to the frog's brain state, as much as the content fly. So Fodor argues the teleological theory is unable to assign determinate content to states like the frog's brain state after all. In addition to his example, Fodor offers a general diagnosis of the difficulty facing the teleological theory. He ascribes the difficulty to the "extensionality" of natural selection. According to Fodor, it matters to natural selection which situations a given trait has advantageous results in; but it doesn't matter to natural selection how that class of situations is described. So, given that "fly" and "small black moving thing" have been more or less co-extensional in frog history, it is unsurprising that the teleological theory is unable to decide between them as readings of the frog brain state. I think that, while Fodor is right that frog-type examples present a difficulty for the teleological theory, he is wrong in his general diagnosis of the difficulty. There seems to me no good reason to think that natural selection is "extensional" in the way Fodor suggests. On the contrary, biologists are not so much interested in when a trait is advantageous, as why it is advantageous, and for that reason restrict themselves to causally relevant descriptions of biological situations. 4 (Cf. Millikan, [15, p. xx]CHECK; Neander [18, pp. v, xiii-xiv]CHECK.) If this were not so, it wouldn't only be "fly" and "small black thing" that were candidate descriptions of the frog state's function, but also any grue-like characteristic that just happened accidentally to have been present on all past occasions when the frog's state proved advantageous. Maybe there are underlying metaphysical puzzles about the fact that "fly" and "small black thing" are causally relevant descriptions, while grue-like descriptions are not; but since nobody would say that these metaphysical puzzles invalidate biological analysis in general, it would be unreasonable to argue that they are an obstacle to a biological analysis of representation in particular. (Cf. Sterelny [28, pp. 00-00]CHECK.) Still, the frog problem does point to a general indeterminacy in selection-based function ascriptions, even if it is not the indeterminacy that Fodor identifies. The real source of the frog-problem is not that natural selection is "extensional", but rather that the ascription of biological functions still seems indeterminate even if we restrict ourselves to causally relevant descriptions. To borrow an example of Karen Neander's [18, pp. 00-00]CHECK, imagine that a species of highland antelope has some distinctive trait T which has been selected because it (a) alters the antelope's haemoglobin structure (b) increases oxygen uptake (c) enables the antelope to live on higher ground (d) gives it access to a plentiful food supply (e) increases reproductive success. Which of this "concertina" of effects is T's function? There seems no obvious answer. After all, by hypothesis it is because T has produced all the effects in the concertina on various past occasions that it has been selected. So the etiological notion of function seems to provide no basis for identifying any one of the effects as T's function. We can view the frog problem as the consequence of this general indeterminacy for the teleological theory of representation. The frog's brain state enables the frog (i) to detect small black things, and thereby (ii) to detect flies. But since the frog's state was selected in virtue of its doing both these things, the etiological notion of function does not discriminate between them. III. Millikan's Response I shall now proceed by considering in turn the responses to Fodor made by Ruth Millikan (section III) and Karen Neander (sections IV-VI). I shall argue that, while each contains a good idea, they both founder because they pay insufficient attention to the significance of beliefdesire structure. I shall then give my own response to 5 Fodor (sections VII-X), which will appeal to these two good ideas but will also focus specifically on the representational purposes of belief and desires. Ruth Millikan argues that Fodor's problem arises because he is focusing on the causes of the frog's brain state, rather than the way in which the frog uses the state in directing actions. The purpose of the state does not depend on which condition is supposed to cause it, argues Millikan, but rather on which condition will enable the use of the state to fulfil some further biological function. (Millikan [14, esp. chs 4 and 11], [15].) The frog's state makes the frog stick its tongue out. What ensures that sticking its tongue out will have biologically advantageous results for the frog? Not just a small black thing, for this certainly won't lead to advantageous results, if it is a speck of dust rather than a fly. Nor is it exactly the presence of a fly, since any other edible bug will suit the frog equally well, and an inedible fly won't. So Millikan argues that the content of the frog state is something like food, rather than small black moving thing, or even fly [15, p. xxvi]CHECK). I agree entirely with Millikan that we need to focus on results, rather than causes. If a biological trait has a function, this is because it produces advantageous effects. In the case of an informational state, it will produce advantageous effects by being present in suchand-such circumstances. The teleological theory should therefore identify the content of an informational state with the circumstances in which it so leads to advantageous effects. Where Millikan goes wrong, however, is equating "advantageous effects" here with any biologically advantageous effects. As I shall argue in sections VIIX, the teleological theory will only work if we equate advantageous effects specifically with effects that satisfy desires, rather than with any biologically advantageous effects. Without this modification, Millikan's suggestion runs into the general "concertina" problem raised at the end of the last section. She says that the frog state represents food, rather than fly, or small black moving thing, because it is only when food is present that the frog action has advantageous effects. But why stop there? If the food triggers an allergic reaction, or in any other way fails to foster the frog's health, then no biological advantage accrues. So why not take the frog state to represent health-preserver, rather than food? 6 By the same coin, why not take the frog state to represent reproduction-enhancer? Eating the fly won't have any advantageous effects which contribute natural selection, on those occasions where, say, the fly contains some substance that sterilizes the frog, or for any other reason does not help the frog to find a mate and reproduce. (Cf. Goode and Griffith, [9, p. 00]CHECK, Neander [18, pp. xvi-xviii]CHECK.) IV. Neander's Response Karen Neander tries a different tack. She starts with the general concertina problem, as exemplified in her own example of the highland antelope. Her response to this problem is that all the effects of the antelope's trait T are indeed genuine functions. Her reasoning is that, when everything works as it is biologically supposed to, then the antelope's trait does produce all these effects. I agree with Neander that this is the right thing to say. The trait T has the whole concertina of effects as its functions. After all, the past selection of T occurred precisely when all these effects were produced, rather than any subset. However, Neander then points out, if we focus on the notion of malfunction, rather than of function, then it is possible to identify one of these effects as a function which is specific to the antelope's trait T. The point is that not all the effects in question are ones whose absence means that T is malfunctioning. Suppose that there is in fact no increased oxygen uptake in some particular member of the antelope species. Does this mean that T is not doing its job? Not necessarily, because increased oxygen uptake also depends on other traits, such as efficient lungs, and so the lack of increased oxygen uptake may be due to the lungs malfunctioning instead. In such a case, where the antelope has deficient lungs, say, the trait T will not perform most of its functions. But it would be wrong on that account to say that trait T is malfunctioning, since the absence of these effects is the fault of the deficient lungs, rather than T. Of course, if there is no increased oxygen uptake (or highland habitat, or reproductive success) this may be because T is malfunctioning. But it could equally be because other parts of the organism are not doing their job. So if we ask, "Which absence ensures that T is malfunctioning?" we get a unique answer, "The absence of that effect that depends on T alone, namely, altered haemoglobin structure." The point of Neander's emphasis on malfunction is that it gives us a rationale for identifying, among the 7 different effects that have been responsible for a trait's selection, one particular function that is specific to that trait. Neander amplifies this idea by relating it to Robert Cummins' notion of "functional analysis" [3]. Cummins points out that that the workings of any complex entity like a biological organism can be successively decomposed into subsystems. The first decomposition of an organism might give us the circulatory system, the respiratory system, the immune system, the nervous system, and so on; the circulatory system can then be decomposed into the heart, the blood vessels, the blood, and so on. At each level the contribution made by each part to the working of the whole can be described. Neander argues that the function specific to any trait is the immediate effect it produces at the lowest level of description where it appears as an unanalysed component in the functional analysis. The idea is that, given any trait T, we should analyse the system until T features as a basic but not itself decomposed component, and then note what immediate effect T produces at this level of decription. Neander then argues that this general idea provides an answer to Fodor's indeterminacy challenge to the teleologial theory of content. More specifically, she holds that if we apply her general analysis of functions to the frog, then we can conclude that the frog's state represents small black things, rather than flies, or food, or reproduction-enablers. For, if we take the lowest level at which the frog's "bug-detection" system is an unanalysed component, argues Neander, then the most immediate effect produced by this system is detecting small black things. It is only as a result of doing this that the system detects flies, or frog food, or reproduction-enablers. So the content of the states of this system is small black things. V. Frogs are Bad Examples I think that Neander has the right solution to the general indeterminacy problem facing all ascriptions of functions. We can identify the function specific to a given biological trait by focusing on cases where that trait malfunctions. Moreover, as I shall explain later, I think that this general analysis of functions helps answer Fodor's more specific objection that teleosemantic ascriptions of content are indeterminate. However, I do not think that Neander's own use of her general analysis is the right way to answer Fodor. My answer to Fodor will use her general analysis of functions in a rather different way. 8 In a moment I shall explain what is wrong with Neander's own answer to Fodor. But first I would like to enter a general complaint about the excessive attention paid to the frog example in the literature on Fodor's objection. Note that our discussion so far has shown that there are no clear pre-theoretical intuitions about what the frog's state does represent. Different participants in the debate favour quite different ascriptions of content to the frog state. Fodor's initial discussion assumes that a good theory ought to make this state represent fly. Millikan is happy with a theory that implies it represents food. Now Neander defends a theory which has it representing small black thing. One obvious consequence is that we are not going to be able to evaluate theories of representation by noting what they imply about frogs. In the absence of any pretheoretical agreement, each theory is free to interpret the frogs in its own way. Moreover, I suspect that behind this methodological point there lies a more substantial moral. Namely, that the reason there are no firm intuitions about the content of the frog's state is that there isn't really any fact of the matter about it. My own response to Fodor will imply that a cognitive state only has a definite content when it is part of a psychological structure with the complexity of belief-desire psychology. A corollary is that the frog's state, which is not embedded in such a structure (at least as the frog is described in the philosophical literature)1, does not in fact definitely represent fly, rather than frog food, or small black thing. Some commentators on the teleological theory argue that its first task is to deal with biologically simple examples like the frog's state. If the theory can't cope with the simple representational states of frogs, then what chance does it have with the far more complicated representational states of human beings? (Cf. Agar [1, pp. 1-2].) After all, it must be easier to identify the functional facts in simple animals like frogs than in more complicated organisms like human beings. And if representational facts depend on functional facts, as the teleological theory argues, then doesn't it follow that frog representation must be easier to undertstand than human representation? But this is too quick. We don't yet know how representational facts are related to functional facts. Even if we assume that they are somehow related, the discussion so far shows that the dependence is not 9 obvious. So it is perfectly possible that the kind of functional facts required to fix representational facts display a complexity which the frog lacks. This is what I shall argue. The frog's traits have perfectly good functions, but these aren't the kind of functions that fix determinate representations. Representation only becomes determinate when we move away from frogs towards beings with more complicated psychologies. True, by the time we reach the full complexity of human beings, the teleological theory faces various further problems. (For example, it needs to show how the many sophisticated mental states that humans acquire in the course of individual development, most of which have no obvious biological relevance, somehow derive their representational powers from genetic or non-genetic selection processes.) However, such further problems are not my present concern. My aim here is merely to answer Fodor's indeterminacy objection, and my contention is that we will not be able to deal with this objection until we have moved away from frogs to beings with beliefs and desires. VI. Objections to Neander I still owe my response to Neander. Recall that Neander takes the frog state to represent small black things, on the grounds that "detecting small black things" is the most immediate effect produced by the frog's bug-detector at the lowest level where it is an unanalyzed component. Neander's strategy is to identify the functions specific to given biological traits by noting which of their effects are most immediate. And she says that "detecting small black things" is the most immediate effect of the frog's detection system. My fundamental objection to this strategy is that "detecting small black things" doesn't seem to be an effect at all. The following are surely the effects of the frog's detection system: the frog sticks its tongue out; it catches a small black thing; it catches a fly; it gets food; and so on. If anything, the most immediate effect is sticking its tongue out. In any case, "detecting suchand-such" does not feature among the effects. I would say that "detecting X" is a cognate notion to "representing X". It is the kind of notion that the teleological theory needs to analyze, not a notion it can take as given. In order for Neander to solve the frog problem, she ought to start with the structure of effects produced by the frog's detection system, and thereby reach a conclusion about what it detects. It seems to beg the question to have "detecting Xs" appearing among the effects. 10 Couldn't Neander say that the most immediate effect of the detection system is that the frog sticks-out-itstongue-in-response-to-small-black-things?2 But if we are going to include the stimulus producing the response as part of the description of the most immediate effect, why not say the most immediate effect is sticking-out-itstongue-in-response-to-flies, or sticking-out-its-tonguein-response-to-food, or so on? These all seem respectable alternative decriptions of the most immediate effect of the frog's detection system, namely, its sticking out its tongue. True, actually catching small black things is a more immediate effect than catching flies, or getting food. But this is a matter of the effects which issue from the frog's state, not of what the state is responding to. It would seem to be a confusion to infer from this that sticking-out-its-tongue-in-response-to-small-black-things must somehow be privileged over sticking-out-its-tonguein-response-to-flies. There is no obvious reason to hold that the most immediate effect (sticking out its tongue) must be characterized as a response to the condition required for the next most immediate effect (small black things). After all, as I have just observed, it seems to make perfectly good initial sense to say the frog is sticking out its tongue in response to flies, or food, or so on. I would argue that Neander has taken insufficient note of Millikan's point that representational content hinges on how the representation is used, not on what causes it. In her general discussion of teleology, Neander focuses, quite rightly, on the effects of biological traits. But as soon as she turns to representation she shifts to the question of what is supposed to cause the frog's state (what it is supposed to detect). From the teleological point of view, this is to start at the wrong end. The teleosemantic strategy requires us first to identify which result the state is supposed to produce, and then use this to tell us what it is representing. Neander, however, tries to decide directly what the state is representing, without consdering what effect the state is supposed to produce. Perhaps further elaboration could show how this input-orientated strategy can be made to work. But such a strategy would have more in common with older indicator theories of content than with the kind of teleosemantic theory that Neander is trying to defend 7 An Alternative Solution Let me now offer my own solution to the indeterminacy problem. I shall first state this solution briefly, and then go into details. 11 Consider some animal that has definite desires. Suppose in particular that it desires to eat a fly. (It wants to eat a fly, not just any small black thing, nor any other food -- just as a human being might want to eat chocolate, not any stuff that looks brown and soft, nor any other food.) Suppose in addition that this desire, when combined with some belief S, causes the animal to shoot out its tongue. If we now assume that the biological purpose of beliefs is to be present in those circumstances where the behaviour they prompt will satisfy the desires they are combining with, then it follows that the content of the belief S is that a fly is in tongue-reach, rather than food, or a moving black thing. For it is only when a fly is in fact within tongue-reach that the animal's desire for a fly will be satisfied. If it is responding to food which isn't a fly, or a small black thing which isn't a fly, then it won't satsify its desire for a fly by catching it. This analysis is just a version of Millikan's idea that we should identify the content of an informational state with that condition which will ensure that the behaviour this state generates will have biologically successful results. But it goes beyond Millikan in focusing specifically on results which are successful in the specific sense of satisfying desires, not on any results which are biologically successful in any sense. It is because of this restriction that my suggestion avoids the indeterminacy which remains in Millikan's approach. While food, health and reproductive success are all no doubt successful results which are biologically supposed to follow from the animal's behaviour, the circumstances required for them to follow won't count as the content of S, on my suggestion, unless these are results that the animal desires. If this account of belief contents is right, then it will follow that animals which lack a belief-desire psychology are cognitively too simple to have mental states with definite contents. The contents of mental states are only pinned down by their roles in an interlocking structure of beliefs and desires. 8 Beliefs and Desires The suggestion in the last section was an instance of a familiar strategy for fixing belief contents in terms of desire contents: a belief's content is that condition which will ensure the satisfaction of whichever desires it combines with to generate behaviour. (Cf. Ramsey [25, p. 159], Putnam [24], Appiah [2], Mellor [11], Whyte [1990], Papineau [21].) Some readers may be curious at this point why we should do things this way round. 12 Suppose we take it as given that belief contents and desire contents are interdependent. Even so, why assume that we should fix beliefs contents in terms of desire contents? Why not fix desire contents in terms of belief contents? Or why not fix both in terms of something else?3 All these different directions of explanation have been pursued in the literature. But the teleological approach I am defending here is committed to explaining belief contents in terms of desire contents. This is because biological functions are always a matter of effects -- functions are effects in virtue of which traits are selected. Beliefs, however, do not have any effects to call their own. Rather, their biological purpose is to produce whichever results will fulfil the purposes of the desires they are acting in concert with. So the teleological theory will start with the results which desires are biologically supposed to produce, and which it will count as the satisfaction conditions of those desires. And then it will then explain the contents of beliefs derivatively, by saying that the purpose of beliefs is to generate actions which will produce desired results in such-and-such conditions, which conditions will therefore count as the truth conditions of those beliefs.4 So I am committed to explaining belief contents in terms of desire contents. Given this, however, it may seem that I am still open to an obvious variant of Fodor's objection. For doesn't Fodor's problem arise as much for desires as beliefs? If we think of the contents of desires, in line with the teleological theory, as the results that they are biologically supposed to produce, then why fix on the content fly, say, for a given desire? After all, aren't small black thing, food, health, survival, and reproductive success equally effects that this desire is biologically supposed to produce? (Cf. Fodor [8, p. 72].) If desire contents are as indeterminate as belief contents, then the strategy of using desres to tie down beliefs is not going to work. However, I now think we now have the resources to answer this objection. We can use Neander's general account of which functions are specific to which biological traits to identify the contents of desire states.5 The general idea will be that the function which is specific to a desire, in Neander's sense, should be counted as its satisfaction condition. I shall elaborate this idea in the section after next. But first it will be useful to make some further remarks about the 13 interlocking biological functions of beliefs and desires in beings like ourselves. The function of beliefs is perhaps the more obvious. Beliefs allow organisms to tailor their behaviour to circumstances. We can bring this out by comparing beings like ourselves with a simpler sort of organism (let us call them "simpletons"). "Simpletons" don't have two kinds of mental states, informational and motivational, which interact in generating behaviour. In so far as they have mental states at all, each is triggered by some specific stimulus and leads to some specific behaviour. We are supposing frogs are like this. Any small black thing triggers a state which makes the frog stick its tongue out. But human beings are different. Our desires do not always generate the same behaviour. Which behaviour issues from a given desire depends on which beliefs it is acting in concert with. The point of this dependence of behaviour on belief is that it allows us to vary our behaviour according to the circumstances. If the belief does its job properly (that is, it is held in circumstances which make it true), then the behaviour chosen will be appropriate for producing the desired result in those circumstances. So we are able to do much better than the "simpletons", in that we can pursue our desires with appropriately flexible responses across the range of differerent circumstances our beliefs inform us about. Let us now focus on the role of desires. The role of desires in our belief-desire psychology is less often remarked than that of beliefs, which is a pity, since it is in some ways less obvious. From the point of view of evolution, it is not clear why we have a range of different desires at all. Why don't we just choose whichever behaviour will maximize reproductive success? To see the point of this question, compare ourselves with a type of organism I shall call a "super-brain". "Superbrains" are like us, and unlike simpletons, in having beliefs, but their beliefs always inform the singleminded pursuit of reproductive success. Super-brains always choose the action which they believe will maximize reproductive success. Given sufficiently streamlined brains, these super-brains would be biologically ideal beings. However, we human beings are different, presumably because it would be too difficult, given our limited cognitive capacities (not to mention the limited capacities of our evolutionary ancestors), for us reliably to work out in real time which actions will maximize reproductive success. So instead natural selection has given us states (innate and acquired desires) which make us use our beliefs to select actions which will produce certain intermediate results, like food and warmth and coca-cola. These results correlate 14 reasonably well with reproductive success, which is why we have evolved to seek them. But even when we can see that they conflict with reproductive success, we seek them anyway, which is the difference between us and the "super-brains". The difference between us and the super-brains may not be fully clear, Won't super-brains also have intermediate desires? For example, mightn't a superbrain judge that the best current means to its reproductive success is to eat some ice-cream, and for this reason desire some ice-cream? But while a superbrain might pursue ice-cream as a means, it won't desire it as we do. For by hypothesis the super-brain will cease to pursue the ice-cream as soon as it comes to believe that it isn't good for its health, or is otherwise deleterious to reproductive success. We aren't like that. Even though my desire for ice-cream is presumably environmentally acquired, rather than genetically innate, it will still persist even after I discover ice-cream only makes me fat. Life would be much simpler if all our desires for intermediate results simply dissolved as soon as we discover that they interfere with more ultimate biological goals.6 9 Psychological Realism Some readers may be worried about the status of the last section's relatively detailed empirical claims about the structure and biological function of human belief-desire psychology. A full response to this worry is clearly not possible here, but a couple of brief comments may be helpful. (For further discussion see Papineau [22], [23].) Consider the "simpletons" and the "super-brains" again. I have taken it that we humans are different from both. I have assumed that we are different from the simpletons, in that our behaviour varies depending on what our beliefs indicate to be the best means to certain ends. And I have assumed that we are different from the super-brains, in that the ends we pursue are the intermediate results we desire, and not just reproductive success. So far I have offered no evidence for these claims about human beings. I have simply presented them as truisms of everyday psychology. But we do not have to rest with the fact that everyday psychology says we are different from the simpletons and the super-brains. For there is any amount of direct behavioural evidence to show we are so different. After all, we don't behave like simpletons or super-brains. As soon as I learn that the pub has no beer, the arrival of 7 pm ceases to 15 stimulate me to go there. So I'm not a simpleton. And even after I discover that drinking beer only hinders my reproductive success, I continue drinking it. So I'm not a super-brain. Clearly this kind of evidence can be multiplied indefinitely. The structure of our behaviour would be quite different if it were not directed by beliefs and desires. So we have every reason to accept that we really do have the structure of beliefs and desires posited by everyday psychology.7 Moreover, if we do have this structure, then presumably it is a matter of biological design. It would be very odd to accept that humans do indeed have a structure of beliefs and desires, yet deny that this structure has evolved because it enables humans to tailor their behaviour to current circumstances and thereby achieve outcomes which are correlated with (but distinct from) reproductive success. We should not of course believe every fanciful "just-so story" which is offered in explanation of any biological trait. But in the case of human belief-desire psychology it is hard to see how there could be any other possible explanation apart from evolutionary design. (Cf. Millikan [13, pp. 292-4].) 10 The Contents of Desires The task I still face is to show how the teleological theory can pin down the content of desires in the face of Fodor's indeterminacy objection. My strategy is to take Neander's analysis of which functions are specfic to which traits, and then apply it, not as she does, but rather within the conext of belief-desire psychology, to pin down which of the results produced by a desire is its specific function. So my suggestion is that the teleological theory should identify the satisfaction condition of a desire as that result which is the desire's specific function. It will be helpful to switch examples slightly at this point, and consider now the desire for food in some organism with a belief-desire psychology. My task is to show that getting food into your stomach is the specific function of this desire, in Neander's sense, in the face of Fodor's complaint is that this desire is equally supposed to produce a number of other results. Consider a typical case where your desire for food leads you to put the contents of your spoon into your mouth. If all goes well, your desire has the following results: you move your right arm, your spoon enters your mouth, your stomach receives food, the food is digested, your health is preserved, you survive, you reproduce. 16 Fodor would point out that the biological purpose of the desire state is to produce just this kind of "concertina" of results. So what entitles the teleological theory to pick out just one -- the stomach's reception of food -as the desire's satisfaction condition? As a preliminary step, it will be helpful to split this into two problems. First, what shows that the initial results in the above sequence (you move your arm, the spoon enters your mouth) are not the satisfaction condition of the desire? Second, what shows that the later results (the food is digested, your health is preserved, you survive, you reproduce) are not the satisfaction condition of the desire? The answer to the first problem is obvious enough. The initial stages in the concertina of results depend as much on the beliefs behind your behaviour as on the desire itself. (If you didn't believe that there is food in your spoon, your desire for food wouldn't make you put the spoon in your mouth. And if you believed instead that there is food in the cupboard across the room, then the desire would make you walk across the room.) So if we want a result that attaches to the desire as such, and not just to the conjunction of the desire with specific beliefs, then we need to look further along the concertina, to those results which the desire is always supposed to produce, when things work as they are biologically supposed to. We can amplify this answer to our first problem by contrasting ourselves with the "simpletons". The cognitive states of simpletons are designed always to trigger exactly the same sequence of results (tongue shoots out, black thing caught, . . .) But our cognitive states work differently. Which sequence of effects is produced by any given cognitive state depends on which other cognitive states it interacts with. In particular, the initial effects produced by any desire will depend on which beliefs it interacts with, since different beliefs will indicate different behaviours as the means to the desire's satisfaction. So if we want to identify effects which it is the function of the desire to produce, we need to go far enough along the concertina to reach results which do not depend on which beliefs the desire happens to be interacting with. This now brings us to the second problem. Even if we can dismiss the initial results in the concertina, we are still left with the many further results the desire is always supposed to produce (the stomach receives food, the food is digested, your health is preserved, you survive, you reproduce). It is here that I think we should appeal to Neander's analysis. We can agree that 17 the desire for food not only has the function of putting food in your stomach, but also the further functions of allowing digestion, forstering health, and so on. For presumably it was when this desire caused this whole sequence of results that selection preserved it. However, if we apply Neander's analysis, then we see that the function of acquiring food is nevertheless specific to this desire. For the non-fulfilment of the further functions, like digestion and reproduction, doesn't show that this desire is malfunctioning, since these further functions depend not just on the desire doing its job, but also on other traits, like the digestive and reproductive systems, doing their jobs too. So if the teleological theory equates the cosntents of desires with those effects which it is their specific function to produce, then it implies the wanted conclusion that in this case the desire is for food. We can think of the role of desires as follows. When a desire is activated, it combines with current beliefs (there is some food in the kitchen, say) to generate behaviour (going to the kitchen) which will produce some specific result (food) if those beliefs are true. SO this specific result (food) is the job of the psychological system activated by the desire. Further effects (digestion, health, survival, reproduction) depend on other systems as well (the digestive system, reproductive system, and so on). If these further effects fail to ensue, then something has gone wrong, biologically speaking. But this won't be a failure of the psychological system activated by the desire, as long as this system has done its specific job of getting food. Note how this explains why the knowledge that some desired result is biologically disadvantageous does not necessarily stop us pursuing that result. (Knowing that beer hinders my reproductive success, say, does not stop me drinking beer.) The reason is that is not usually the specific function of the psychological system which directs our behaviour to ensure ultimate biological success, but rather to achieve intermediate results, namely, the satisfaction conditions of desires. It might be helpful to compare ourselves to the "super-brains" once more. Our difference from the superbrains brings out the sense in which the specific function of desires, in Neander's sense, is normally to produce intermediate goals. As we have seen, there is not necessarily a psychological malfunction in beings like us if reproductive success is not achieved, since the psychological system activated by our desires will have done its job if we get food, say, even if reproductive success does not follow. But with the "super-brains" it is indeed a failing of their psychology 18 if the ultimate goal of maximizing reproductive success is not achieved. For the job of the super-brains' psychological system is precisely to work out which actions will yield maximum reproductive success, and so this system has failed if it gets this wrong.8 So the difference between us and the super-brains is that our psychology, unlike theirs, often has the specific function of producing some intermediate result, like food or warmth or coca-cola, depending on which desires are activated. 11. Conclusion I have argued that the teleological theory should answer Fodor's objection by appealing to the structure of belief-desire psychology. Within this context, it can equate a belief's content with that condition which will ensure the satisfaction of desires. The challenge of indeterminacy then shifts to the satisfaction condition of desires. This challenge can be answered by appealing to Neander's analysis of specific functions. This analysis implies that desires in beings like us have the specific function of producing specific results, as is illustrated by the difference between us and the superbrains. The teleological theory can therefore equate the satisfaction conditions of desires with those specific results. _____________________ I would like to thank Tim Crane, Jerry Fodor, Peter Goldie, Keith Hossack, Michael Martin, Ruth Millikan, Karen Neander, Lucy O'Brien, Georges Rey, Gabriel Segal, Barry Smith, Scott Sturgeon, Bernhard Weiss and two anonymous readers for the Australasian Journal of Philosophy for commenting on earlier versions of this paper. 19 Bibliography 1. N. Agar, "What Do Frogs Really Believe?", Australian Journal of Philosophy 71 (1993), pp. 00-00. 2. A. Appiah, "Truth Conditions: A Causal Theory", in J. Butterfield (ed.) Language, Mind and Logic (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986). 3. R. Cummins, "Functional Analysis", Journal of Philosophy 72 (1975), pp. 741-765. 4. D. Dennett, Content and Consciousness (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1969). 5. D. Dennett, The Intentional Stance (Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press, 1987). 6. F. Dretske, Knowledge and the Flow of Information (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1981). 7. J. Fodor, "Semantics, Wisconsin Style", Synthese 59 (1984), pp. 231-250. 8. J. Fodor, A Theory of Content, (Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press, 1990). 9. R. Goode and P. Griffiths, "The Misuse of Sober's Selection of/Selection for Distinction", Biology and Philosophy 10 (1995), pp. 99-108. 10. C. McGinn, Mental Content, (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1989). 11. D.H. Mellor, "I and Now", Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 89 (1988), pp. 00-00. 12. R. Millikan, Language, Thought, and other Biological Categories, (Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press, 1984). 13. R. Millikan, "Biosemantics", Journal of Philosophy, 86 (1989), pp. 00-00. 14. R. Millikan, White Queen Psychology and other Essays for Alice, (Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press, 1993) 15. R. Millikan, "Speaking up for Darwin" in G. Rey and B. Loewer (eds) Meaning and Mind: Fodor and his Critics (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1993), pp. 00-00. 16. K. Neander, "Functions as Selected Effects: The Conceptual Analyst's Defence", Philosophy of Science 58 (1991), pp. 168-184. 20 17. K. Neander, "The Teleological Notion of a Function", Australasian Journal of Philosophy 69 (1991), pp. 454468. 18. K. Neander, "Misrepresenting and Malfunctioning" Philosophical Studies 0 (199?), pp. 00-00. 19. D. Papineau, "Representation and Explanation", Philosophy of Science 51 (1984), pp. 00-00. 20. D. Papineau, Reality and Representation (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1987). 21. D. Papineau, "Truth and Teleology", in D. Knowles (ed.) Explanation (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991). pp. 00-00. 22. D. Papineau, Philosophical Naturalism (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1993). 23. D. Papineau, "Reply to Godfrey-Smith, Symposium on Philosophical Naturalism", Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, forthcoming. 24. H. Putnam, "Reference and Understanding", in his Meaning and the Moral Sciences (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1978). 25. F. Ramsey, "Facts and Propositions", Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 7 (1927), pp. 00-00. 26. R. Stalknaker, Inquiry (Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press, 1984). 27. D. Stampe, "Towards a Causal Theory of Linguistic Representation", in P. French, T. Ueling and H. Wettstein (eds) Midwest Studies in Philosophy 2 (1977) pp. 00-00. 28. K. Sterelny, The Representational Theory of Mind, (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1990). 29. J. Whyte, "Success Semantics', Analysis 50 (1990), pp. 149-157. 30. L. Wright, "Functions", Philosophical Review 82 (1973), pp.139-168. It is a moot point whether frogs are as simple as philosophers suppose. The standard philosophical story is that frogs will go on sticking out their tongues indefinitely, sphex-like, if prompted with small dark moving things. But I have heard it said that frogs are not really sphex-like, but only seem so in laboratories 1 21 where they are fed bee-bees or other small black things which fail to assuage their hunger. On this story, frogs who are fed enough flies will stop sticking out their tongue until they are hungry again. In the interests of expository simplicity, however, I shall continue with the standard assumption that the frog's behaviour is a invariable reflex unaffected by the frog's current digestive state. Neander suggested this possibility to me in correspondence. 2 Something else will be needed, if want to fix both belief and desire contents, for we cannot solve for two unknowns (belief contents and desire contents) with one equation (the truth of beliefs ensures the satisfaction of desires). Cf. Stalnaker [26, esp. pp. 15-18], Papineau [19, p. 555]. 3 Perhaps some beliefs also have a different kind of purpose. Consider the belief that some fierce animal is closer than it is, or, again, the belief that you will emerge unscathed from some imminent trial of violence. Perhaps these beliefs serve an extra biological function, in addition to aiding the satisfaction of desires -namely, the function of making us act in ways which will protect our biological needs, even at the cost of frustrating our desires. For example, the fierce-animal belief might stop you satisfying your curiosity and make you flee without delay; and the immunity-from-injury belief might stop you avoiding dangers and make you fight without fear.) However, if there are such cases, the teleological theory of representation should ignore these extra functions, and analyze the truth-conditional contents of beliefs specifically in terms of their more standard function of satisfying desires. For note that the conditions required for beliefs to serve special need-protecting functions will standardly not be part of those beliefs' truth conditions. For example, the belief "the animal is close" serves its special function when the animal is in fact further away; similarly, the "I won't be injured" belief does its special work precisely when a real injury is likely. For further discussion of this issue, see Papineau [22, ch. 3.4]. 4 Let me reiterate the distinction between Neander's general account of biological functions, which I endorsed in section 4, and her own application of this idea to the Fodor's problem, which I criticized in section 6. I want to use Neander's general account of functions, but I shall apply it to Fodor's problem in my own way. 6 Given that the overall function of our cognitive system is to enhance reproductive success, it is sub5 22 optimal that our desires should persist in the face of evidence that they are unhealthy. But this is the cost of having a system which has been designed to calculate the best means to certain proximate results in real time. It is true that those results will themselves have been picked out because of their association with reproductive success in our long-term evolutionary and individual experience. But since the whole point of having desires for these results is to avoid our having to consider their causal relevance to reproductive success every time we make a decision, it is inevitable that new information about this relevance will have no immediate effect on our decisions. Whether beliefs and desires have real compositional structure is a further question, which lies at the centre of the current debate between traditional and connectionist programmes in artificial intelligence. However, while this question is relevant to the details of the teleological theory, it is not crucial to the topics discussed of this paper. (Cf. Papineau [23].) 7 A complication. One reason a super-brain might make a mistake about what will maximize reproductive success would be that its digestive system isn't working, when it thinks it is. In this case, the failure to achieve reproductive success would in a sense be due to a failing of the digestive system too. But note that even here its not due to the failure of the digestive system alone. For the super-brain's psychological system has also failed, in mistakenly assuming that the faulty digestive system is working, when it isn't. 8